Karl Marx,
revolutionary, sociologist, historian, and economist, was the author (with
Friedrich Engels) of Manifest der
Kommunistischen Partei (1848), commonly known as The Communist Manifesto, the
most celebrated pamphlet in the history of the socialist movement, as well as of
its most important book, Das Kapital. These writings and
others by Marx and Engels form the basis of the body of thought and belief known
as Marxism.
This article deals with Marx's life, his
thinking, his accomplishments, and the development of Marxist theory. See the
articles SOCIALISM and COMMUNISM
for full treatment of those ideologies.
Karl Heinrich Marx was born on May 5,
1818, in the city of Trier in the Rhine province of Prussia, now in Germany. He
was the oldest surviving boy of nine children. His father, Heinrich, a
successful lawyer, was a man of the Enlightenment, devoted to Kant and Voltaire,
who took part in agitations for a constitution in Prussia. His mother, born
Henrietta Pressburg, was from Holland. Both parents were Jewish and were
descended from a long line of rabbis, but, a year or so before Karl was born,
his father--probably because his professional career required it--was baptized
in the Evangelical Established Church. Karl was baptized when he was six years
old. Although as a youth Karl was influenced less by religion than by the
critical, sometimes radical social policies of the Enlightenment, his Jewish
background exposed him to prejudice and discrimination that may have led him to
question the role of religion in society and contributed to his desire for
social change.
Marx was educated from 1830 to 1835 at
the high school in Trier. Suspected of harbouring liberal teachers and pupils,
the school was under police surveillance. Marx's writings during this period
exhibited a spirit of Christian devotion and a longing for self-sacrifice on
behalf of humanity. In October 1835 he matriculated at the University of Bonn.
The courses he attended were exclusively in the humanities, in such subjects as
Greek and Roman mythology and the history of art. He participated in customary
student activities, fought a duel, and spent a day in jail for being drunk and
disorderly. He presided at the Tavern Club, which was at odds with the more
aristocratic student associations, and joined a poets' club that included some
political activists. A politically rebellious student culture was, indeed, part
of life at Bonn. Many students had been arrested; some were still being expelled
in Marx's time, particularly as a result of an effort by students to disrupt a
session of the Federal Diet at Frankfurt. Marx, however, left Bonn after a year
and in October 1836 enrolled at the University of Berlin to study law and
philosophy.
Marx's crucial experience at Berlin was
his introduction to Hegel's philosophy, regnant there, and his adherence to the Young
Hegelians. At first he felt a repugnance toward Hegel's doctrines; when
Marx fell sick it was partially, as he wrote his father, "from intense
vexation at having to make an idol of a view I detested." The Hegelian
pressure in the revolutionary student culture was powerful, however, and Marx
joined a society called the Doctor Club, whose members were intensely involved
in the new literary and philosophical movement. Their chief figure was Bruno
Bauer, a young lecturer in theology, who was developing the idea that the
Christian Gospels were a record not of history but of human fantasies arising
from emotional needs and that Jesus had not been a historical person. Marx
enrolled in a course of lectures given by Bauer on the prophet Isaiah. Bauer
taught that a new social catastrophe "more tremendous" than that of
the advent of Christianity was in the making. The Young Hegelians began moving
rapidly toward atheism and also talked vaguely of political action.
The Prussian government, fearful of the
subversion latent in the Young Hegelians, soon undertook to drive them from the
universities. Bauer was dismissed from his post in 1839. Marx's "most
intimate friend" of this period, Adolph Rutenberg, an older journalist who
had served a prison sentence for his political radicalism, pressed for a deeper
social involvement. By 1841 the Young Hegelians had become left republicans.
Marx's studies, meanwhile, were lagging. Urged by his friends, he submitted a
doctoral dissertation to the university at Jena, which was known to be lax in
its academic requirements, and received his degree in April 1841. His thesis
analyzed in a Hegelian fashion the difference between the natural philosophies
of Democritus and Epicurus. More distinctively, it sounded a note of Promethean
defiance: (see also Index: Hegelianism)
Philosophy makes no secret of it.
Prometheus' admission: "In sooth all gods I hate," is its own
admission, its own motto against all gods, . . . Prometheus is the noblest saint
and martyr in the calendar of philosophy.
In 1841 Marx, together with other Young
Hegelians, was much influenced by the publication of Das Wesen des Christentums (1841; The Essence of Christianity) by Ludwig
Feuerbach. Its author, to Marx's mind, successfully criticized Hegel, an
idealist who believed that matter or existence was inferior to and dependent
upon mind or spirit, from the opposite, or materialist, standpoint, showing how
the "Absolute Spirit" was a projection of "the real man standing
on the foundation of nature." Henceforth Marx's philosophical efforts were
toward a combination of Hegel's dialectic--the idea that all things are in a
continual process of change resulting from the conflicts between their
contradictory aspects--with Feuerbach's materialism, which placed material
conditions above ideas. (see also Index:
dialectical materialism)
In January 1842 Marx began contributing
to a newspaper newly founded in Cologne, the Rheinische
Zeitung. It was the liberal democratic organ of a group of young
merchants, bankers, and industrialists; Cologne was the centre of the most
industrially advanced section of Prussia. To this stage of Marx's life belongs
an essay on the freedom of the press. Since he then took for granted the
existence of absolute moral standards and universal principles of ethics, he
condemned censorship as a moral evil that entailed spying into people's minds
and hearts and assigned to weak and malevolent mortals powers that presupposed
an omniscient mind. He believed that censorship could have only evil
consequences.
On Oct. 15, 1842, Marx became editor of
the Rheinische Zeitung. As such, he
was obliged to write editorials on a variety of social and economic issues,
ranging from the housing of the Berlin poor and the theft by peasants of wood
from the forests to the new phenomenon of communism. He found Hegelian idealism
of little use in these matters. At the same time he was becoming estranged from
his Hegelian friends for whom shocking the bourgeois was a sufficient mode of
social activity. Marx, friendly at this time to the "liberal-minded
practical men" who were "struggling step-by-step for freedom within
constitutional limits," succeeded in trebling his newspaper's circulation
and making it a leading journal in Prussia. Nevertheless, Prussian authorities
suspended it for being too outspoken, and Marx agreed to coedit with the liberal
Hegelian Arnold Ruge a new review, the Deutsch-französische
Jahrbücher ("German-French Yearbooks"), which was to
be published in Paris.
First, however, in June 1843 Marx, after
an engagement of seven years, married Jenny von Westphalen. Jenny was an
attractive, intelligent, and much-admired woman, four years older than Karl; she
came of a family of military and administrative distinction. Her half-brother
later became a highly reactionary Prussian minister of the interior. Her father,
a follower of the French socialist Saint-Simon, was fond of Karl, though others
in her family opposed the marriage. Marx's father also feared that Jenny was
destined to become a sacrifice to the demon that possessed his son.
Four months after their marriage, the
young couple moved to Paris, which was then the centre of socialist thought and
of the more extreme sects that went under the name of communism. There, Marx
first became a revolutionary and a communist and began to associate with
communist societies of French and German workingmen. Their ideas were, in his
view, "utterly crude and unintelligent," but their character moved
him: "The brotherhood of man is no mere phrase with them, but a fact of
life, and the nobility of man shines upon us from their work-hardened
bodies," he wrote in his so-called "Ökonomisch-philosophische
Manuskripte aus dem Jahre 1844" (written in 1844; Economic
and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 [1959]). (These manuscripts were
not published for some 100 years, but they are influential because they show the
humanist background to Marx's later historical and economic theories.)
The "German-French Yearbooks"
proved short-lived, but through their publication Marx befriended Friedrich
Engels, a contributor who was to become his lifelong collaborator, and in
their pages appeared Marx's article "Zur Kritik der Hegelschen
Rechtsphilosophie" ( "Toward the Critique of the Hegelian Philosophy
of Right") with its oft-quoted assertion that religion is the "opium
of the people." It was there, too, that he first raised the call for an
"uprising of the proletariat" to realize the conceptions of
philosophy. Once more, however, the Prussian government intervened against Marx.
He was expelled from France and left for Brussels--followed by Engels--in
February 1845. That year in Belgium he renounced his Prussian nationality.
The next two years in Brussels saw the
deepening of Marx's collaboration with Engels. Engels had seen at firsthand in
Manchester, Eng., where a branch factory of his father's textile firm was
located, all the depressing aspects of the Industrial Revolution. He had also
been a Young Hegelian and had been converted to communism by Moses Hess, who was
called the "communist rabbi." In England he associated with the
followers of Robert Owen. Now he and Marx, finding that they shared the same
views, combined their intellectual resources and published Die heilige Familie (1845; The
Holy Family), a prolix criticism of the Hegelian idealism of the
theologian Bruno Bauer. Their next work, Die
deutsche Ideologie (written 1845-46, published 1932; The
German Ideology), contained the fullest exposition of their important
materialistic conception of history, which set out to show how, historically,
societies had been structured to promote the interests of the economically
dominant class. But it found no publisher and remained unknown during its
authors' lifetimes.
During his Brussels years, Marx
developed his views and, through confrontations with the chief leaders of the
working-class movement, established his intellectual standing. In 1846 he
publicly excoriated the German leader Wilhelm Weitling for his moralistic
appeals. Marx insisted that the stage of bourgeois
society could not be skipped over; the proletariat could not just leap into
communism; the workers' movement required a scientific basis, not moralistic
phrases. He also polemicized against the French socialist thinker Pierre-Joseph
Proudhon in Misère de la philosophie (1847; The
Poverty of Philosophy), a mordant attack on Proudhon's book subtitled
Philosophie de la misère (1846;
The Philosophy of Poverty). Proudhon
wanted to unite the best features of such contraries as competition and
monopoly; he hoped to save the good features in economic institutions while
eliminating the bad. Marx, however, declared that no equilibrium was possible
between the antagonisms in any given economic system. Social structures were
transient historic forms determined by the productive forces: "The handmill
gives you society with the feudal lord; the steammill, society with the
industrial capitalist." Proudhon's mode of reasoning, Marx wrote, was
typical of the petty bourgeois, who failed to see the underlying laws of
history.
An unusual sequence of events led Marx
and Engels to write their pamphlet The
Communist Manifesto. In June 1847 a secret society, the League
of the Just, composed mainly of emigrant German handicraftsmen, met in
London and decided to formulate a political program. They sent a representative
to Marx to ask him to join the league; Marx overcame his doubts and, with
Engels, joined the organization, which thereupon changed its name to the Communist
League and enacted a democratic constitution. Entrusted with the task of
composing their program, Marx and Engels worked from the middle of December 1847
to the end of January 1848. The London Communists were already impatiently
threatening Marx with disciplinary action when he sent them the manuscript; they
promptly adopted it as their manifesto. It enunciated the proposition that all
history had hitherto been a history of class struggles, summarized in pithy form
the materialist conception of history worked out in The German Ideology, and asserted that the forthcoming victory of
the proletariat would put an end to class society forever. It mercilessly
criticized all forms of socialism founded on philosophical "cobwebs"
such as "alienation." It rejected the avenue of "social
Utopias," small experiments in community, as deadening the class struggle
and therefore as being "reactionary sects." It set forth 10 immediate
measures as first steps toward communism, ranging from a progressive income tax
and the abolition of inheritances to free education for all children. It closed
with the words, "The proletarians have nothing to lose but their chains.
They have a world to win. Workingmen of all countries, unite!"
Revolution suddenly erupted in Europe in
the first months of 1848, in France, Italy, and Austria. Marx had been invited
to Paris by a member of the provisional government just in time to avoid
expulsion by the Belgian government. As the revolution gained in Austria and
Germany, Marx returned to the Rhineland. In Cologne he advocated a policy of
coalition between the working class and the democratic bourgeoisie, opposing for
this reason the nomination of independent workers' candidates for the Frankfurt
Assembly and arguing strenuously against the program for proletarian revolution
advocated by the leaders of the Workers' Union. He concurred in Engels' judgment
that The
Communist Manifesto should be shelved and the Communist League
disbanded. Marx pressed his policy through the pages of the Neue
Rheinische Zeitung, newly founded in June 1849, urging a constitutional
democracy and war with Russia. When the more revolutionary leader of the
Workers' Union, Andreas Gottschalk, was arrested, Marx supplanted him and
organized the first Rhineland Democratic Congress in August 1848. When the king
of Prussia dissolved the Prussian Assembly in Berlin, Marx called for arms and
men to help the resistance. Bourgeois liberals withdrew their support from
Marx's newspaper, and he himself was indicted on several charges, including
advocacy of the nonpayment of taxes. In his trial he defended himself with the
argument that the crown was engaged in making an unlawful counterrevolution. The
jury acquitted him unanimously and with thanks. Nevertheless, as the last
hopeless fighting flared in Dresden and Baden, Marx was ordered banished as an
alien on May 16, 1849. The final issue of his newspaper, printed in red, caused
a great sensation. (see also Index: "Neue
Rheinische Zeitung")
Expelled once more from Paris, Marx went
to London in August 1849. It was to be his home for the rest of his life.
Chagrined by the failure of his own tactics of collaboration with the liberal
bourgeoisie, he rejoined the Communist League in London and for about a year
advocated a bolder revolutionary policy. An "Address of the Central
Committee to the Communist League," written with Engels in March 1850,
urged that in future revolutionary situations they struggle to make the
revolution "permanent" by avoiding subservience to the bourgeois party
and by setting up "their own revolutionary workers' governments"
alongside any new bourgeois one. Marx hoped that the economic crisis would
shortly lead to a revival of the revolutionary movement; when this hope faded,
he came into conflict once more with those whom he called "the alchemists
of the revolution," such as August von Willich, a communist who proposed to
hasten the advent of revolution by undertaking direct revolutionary ventures.
Such persons, Marx wrote in September 1850, substitute "idealism for
materialism" and regard
pure will as the motive power of
revolution instead of actual conditions. While we say to the workers: "You
have got to go through fifteen, twenty, fifty years of civil wars and national
wars not merely in order to change your conditions but in order to change
yourselves and become qualified for political power," you on the contrary
tell them, "We must achieve power immediately."
The militant faction in turn ridiculed
Marx for being a revolutionary who limited his activity to lectures on political
economy to the Communist Workers' Educational Union. The upshot was that Marx
gradually stopped attending meetings of the London Communists. In 1852 he
devoted himself intensely to working for the defense of 11 communists arrested
and tried in Cologne on charges of revolutionary conspiracy and wrote a pamphlet
on their behalf. The same year he also published, in a German-American
periodical, his essay "Der Achtzehnte Brumaire des Louis Napoleon" (The
Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte), with its acute analysis of the
formation of a bureaucratic absolutist state with the support of the peasant
class. In other respects the next 12 years were, in Marx's words, years of
"isolation" both for him and for Engels in his Manchester factory.
From 1850 to 1864 Marx lived in material
misery and spiritual pain. His funds were gone, and except on one occasion he
could not bring himself to seek paid employment. In March 1850 he and his wife
and four small children were evicted and their belongings seized. Several of his
children died--including a son Guido, "a sacrifice to bourgeois
misery," and a daughter Franziska, for whom his wife rushed about
frantically trying to borrow money for a coffin. For six years the family lived
in two small rooms in Soho, often subsisting on bread and potatoes. The children
learned to lie to the creditors: "Mr. Marx ain't upstairs." Once he
had to escape them by fleeing to Manchester. His wife suffered breakdowns.
During all these years Engels loyally
contributed to Marx's financial support. The sums were not large at first, for
Engels was only a clerk in the firm of Ermen and Engels at Manchester. Later,
however, in 1864, when he became a partner, his subventions were generous. Marx
was proud of Engels' friendship and would tolerate no criticism of him. Bequests
from the relatives of Marx's wife and from Marx's friend Wilhelm Wolff also
helped to alleviate their economic distress.
Marx had one relatively steady source of
earned income in the United States. On the invitation of Charles A. Dana,
managing editor of The New
York Tribune, he became in 1851 its European correspondent. The
newspaper, edited by Horace Greeley, had sympathies for Fourierism,
a Utopian socialist system developed by the French theorist Charles Fourier.
From 1851 to 1862 Marx contributed close to 500 articles and editorials (Engels
providing about a fourth of them). He ranged over the whole political universe,
analyzing social movements and agitations from India and China to Britain and
Spain.
In 1859 Marx published his first book on
economic theory, Zur Kritik der
politischen Ökonomie (A
Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy). In its preface he
again summarized his materialistic conception of history, his theory that the
course of history is dependent on economic developments. At this time, however,
Marx regarded his studies in economic and social history at the British Museum
as his main task. He was busy producing the drafts of his magnum opus, which was
to be published later as Das Kapital. Some of these drafts, including the Outlines
and the Theories of Surplus Value, are important in their own right and were
published after Marx's death.
Marx's political isolation ended in 1864
with the founding of the International Working Men's Association. Although he
was neither its founder nor its head, he soon became its leading spirit. Its
first public meeting, called by English trade union leaders and French workers'
representatives, took place at St. Martin's Hall in London on Sept. 28, 1864.
Marx, who had been invited through a French intermediary to attend as a
representative of the German workers, sat silently on the platform. A committee
was set up to produce a program and a constitution for the new organization.
After various drafts had been submitted that were felt to be unsatisfactory,
Marx, serving on a subcommittee, drew upon his immense journalistic experience.
His "Address and the Provisional Rules of the International Working Men's
Association," unlike his other writings, stressed the positive achievements
of the cooperative movement and of parliamentary legislation; the gradual
conquest of political power would enable the British proletariat to extend these
achievements on a national scale.
As a member of the organization's
General Council, and corresponding secretary for Germany, Marx was henceforth
assiduous in attendance at its meetings, which were sometimes held several times
a week. For several years he showed a rare diplomatic tact in composing
differences among various parties, factions, and tendencies. The International
grew in prestige and membership, its numbers reaching perhaps 800,000 in 1869.
It was successful in several interventions on behalf of European trade unions
engaged in struggles with employers.
In 1870, however, Marx was still unknown
as a European political personality; it was the Paris
Commune that made him into an international figure, "the best
calumniated and most menaced man of London," as he wrote. When the Franco-German
War broke out in 1870, Marx and Engels disagreed with followers in
Germany who refused to vote in the Reichstag in favour of the war. The General
Council declared that "on the German side the war was a war of
defence." After the defeat of the French armies, however, they felt that
the German terms amounted to aggrandizement at the expense of the French people.
When an insurrection broke out in Paris and the Paris Commune was proclaimed,
Marx gave it his unswerving support. On May 30, 1871, after the Commune had been
crushed, he hailed it in a famous address entitled Civil
War in France:
History has no comparable example of
such greatness. . . . Its martyrs are enshrined forever in the great heart of
the working class.
In Engels' judgment, the Paris Commune
was history's first example of the "dictatorship of the proletariat."
Marx's name, as the leader of The First International and author of the
notorious Civil War, became synonymous
throughout Europe with the revolutionary spirit symbolized by the Paris Commune.
The advent of the Commune, however,
exacerbated the antagonisms within the International Working Men's Association
and thus brought about its downfall. English trade unionists such as George
Odger, former president of the General Council, opposed Marx's support of the
Paris Commune. The Reform Bill of 1867, which
had enfranchised the British working class, had opened vast opportunities for
political action by the trade unions. English labour leaders found they could
make many practical advances by cooperating with the Liberal Party and,
regarding Marx's rhetoric as an encumbrance, resented his charge that they had
"sold themselves" to the Liberals.
A left opposition also developed under
the leadership of the famed Russian revolutionary Mikhail Alexandrovich Bakunin.
A veteran of tsarist prisons and Siberian exile, Bakunin could move men by his
oratory, which one listener compared to "a raging storm with lightning,
flashes and thunderclaps, and a roaring as of lions." Bakunin admired
Marx's intellect but could hardly forget that Marx had published a report in
1848 charging him with being a Russian agent. He felt that Marx was a German
authoritarian and an arrogant Jew who wanted to transform the General Council
into a personal dictatorship over the workers. He strongly opposed several of
Marx's theories, especially Marx's support of the centralized structure of the
International, Marx's view that the proletariat class should act as a political
party against prevailing parties but within the existing parliamentary system,
and Marx's belief that the proletariat, after it had overthrown the bourgeois
state, should establish its own regime. To Bakunin, the mission of the
revolutionary was destruction; he looked to the Russian peasantry, with its
propensities for violence and its uncurbed revolutionary instincts, rather than
to the effete, civilized workers of the industrial countries. The students, he
hoped, would be the officers of the revolution. He acquired followers, mostly
young men, in Italy, Switzerland, and France, and he organized a secret society,
the International Alliance of Social Democracy, which in 1869 challenged the
hegemony of the General Council at the congress in Basel, Switz. Marx, however,
had already succeeded in preventing its admission as an organized body into the
International.
To the Bakuninists, the Paris Commune
was a model of revolutionary direct action and a refutation of what they
considered to be Marx's "authoritarian communism." Bakunin began
organizing sections of the International for an attack on the alleged
dictatorship of Marx and the General Council. Marx in reply publicized Bakunin's
embroilment with an unscrupulous Russian student leader, Sergey Gennadiyevich
Nechayev, who had practiced blackmail and murder.
Without a supporting right wing and with
the anarchist left against him, Marx feared losing control of the International
to Bakunin. He also wanted to return to his studies and to finish Das
Kapital. At the congress of the International at The Hague in 1872, the only
one he ever attended, Marx managed to defeat the Bakuninists. Then, to the
consternation of the delegates, Engels moved that the seat of the General
Council be transferred from London to New York City. The Bakuninists were
expelled, but the International languished and was finally disbanded in
Philadelphia in 1876.
During the next and last decade of his
life, Marx's creative energies declined. He was beset by what he called
"chronic mental depression," and his life turned inward toward his
family. He was unable to complete any substantial work, though he still read
widely and undertook to learn Russian. He became crotchety in his political
opinions. When his own followers and those of the German revolutionary Ferdinand
Lassalle, a rival who believed that socialist goals should be achieved through
cooperation with the state, coalesced in 1875 to found the German
Social Democratic Party, Marx wrote a caustic criticism of their program
(the so-called Gotha Program), claiming that it made too many compromises with
the status quo. The German leaders put his objections aside and tried to mollify
him personally. Increasingly, he looked to a European war for the overthrow of
Russian tsarism, the mainstay of reaction, hoping that this would revive the
political energies of the working classes. He was moved by what he considered to
be the selfless courage of the Russian terrorists who assassinated the tsar,
Alexander II, in 1881; he felt this to be "a historically inevitable means
of action."
Despite Marx's withdrawal from active
politics, he still retained what Engels called his "peculiar
influence" on the leaders of working-class and socialist movements. In
1879, when the French Socialist Workers' Federation was founded, its leader
Jules Guesde went to London to consult with Marx, who dictated the preamble of
its program and shaped much of its content. In 1881 Henry Mayers Hyndman in his England
for All drew heavily on his conversations with Marx but angered him by being
afraid to acknowledge him by name.
During his last years Marx spent much
time at health resorts and even traveled to Algiers. He was broken by the death
of his wife on Dec. 2, 1881, and of his eldest daughter, Jenny Longuet, on Jan.
11, 1883. He died in London, evidently of a lung abscess, on March 14, 1883.
At Marx's funeral in Highgate Cemetery,
Engels declared that Marx had made two great discoveries, the law of development
of human history and the law of motion of bourgeois society. But "Marx was
before all else a revolutionist." He was "the best-hated and
most-calumniated man of his time," yet he also died "beloved, revered
and mourned by millions of revolutionary fellow-workers."
The contradictory emotions Marx
engendered are reflected in the sometimes conflicting aspects of his character.
Marx was a combination of the Promethean rebel and the rigorous intellectual. He
gave most persons an impression of intellectual arrogance. A Russian writer,
Pavel Annenkov, who observed Marx in debate in 1846 recalled that "he spoke
only in the imperative, brooking no contradiction," and seemed to be
"the personification of a democratic dictator such as might appear before
one in moments of fantasy." But Marx obviously felt uneasy before mass
audiences and avoided the atmosphere of factional controversies at congresses.
He went to no demonstrations, his wife remarked, and rarely spoke at public
meetings. He kept away from the congresses of the International where the rival
socialist groups debated important resolutions. He was a "small
groups" man, most at home in the atmosphere of the General Council or on
the staff of a newspaper, where his character could impress itself forcefully on
a small body of coworkers. At the same time he avoided meeting distinguished
scholars with whom he might have discussed questions of economics and sociology
on a footing of intellectual equality. Despite his broad intellectual sweep, he
was prey to obsessive ideas such as that the British foreign minister, Lord
Palmerston, was an agent of the Russian government. He was determined not to let
bourgeois society make "a money-making machine" out of him, yet he
submitted to living on the largess of Engels and the bequests of relatives. He
remained the eternal student in his personal habits and way of life, even to the
point of joining two friends in a students' prank during which they
systematically broke four or five streetlamps in a London street and then fled
from the police. He was a great reader of novels, especially those of Sir Walter
Scott and Balzac; and the family made a cult of Shakespeare. He was an
affectionate father, saying that he admired Jesus for his love of children, but
sacrificed the lives and health of his own. Of his seven children, three
daughters grew to maturity. His favourite daughter, Eleanor, worried him with
her nervous, brooding, emotional character and her desire to be an actress.
Another shadow was cast on Marx's domestic life by the birth to their loyal
servant, Helene Demuth, of an illegitimate son, Frederick; Engels as he was
dying disclosed to Eleanor that Marx had been the father. Above all, Marx was a
fighter, willing to sacrifice anything in the battle for his conception of a
better society. He regarded struggle as the law of life and existence.
The influence of Marx's ideas has been
enormous. Marx's masterpiece, Das Kapital,
the "Bible of the working class," as it was officially described in a
resolution of the International Working Men's Association, was published in 1867
in Berlin and received a second edition in 1873. Only the first volume was
completed and published in Marx's lifetime. The second and third volumes,
unfinished by Marx, were edited by Engels and published in 1885 and 1894. The
economic categories he employed were those of the classical British economics of
David Ricardo; but Marx used them in accordance with his dialectical method to
argue that bourgeois society, like every social organism, must follow its
inevitable path of development. Through the working of such immanent tendencies
as the declining rate of profit, capitalism would die and be replaced by
another, higher, society. The most memorable pages in Das Kapital are the descriptive passages, culled from Parliamentary
Blue Books, on the misery of the English working class. Marx believed that this
misery would increase, while at the same time the monopoly of capital would
become a fetter upon production until finally "the knell of capitalist
private property sounds. The expropriators are expropriated."
Marx never claimed to have discovered
the existence of classes and class struggles in modern society.
"Bourgeois" historians, he acknowledged, had described them long
before he had. He did claim, however, to have proved that each phase in the
development of production was associated with a corresponding class structure
and that the struggle of classes led necessarily to the dictatorship of the
proletariat, ushering in the advent of a classless society. Marx took up the
very different versions of socialism current in the early 19th century and
welded them together into a doctrine that continued to be the dominant version
of socialism for half a century after his death. His emphasis on the influence
of economic structure on historical development has proved to be of lasting
significance.
Although Marx stressed economic issues
in his writings, his major impact has been in the fields of sociology and
history. Marx's most important contribution to sociological theory was his
general mode of analysis, the "dialectical" model, which regards every
social system as having within it immanent forces that give rise to
"contradictions" (disequilibria) that can be resolved only by a new
social system. Neo-Marxists, who no longer accept the economic reasoning in Das Kapital, are still guided by this model in their approach to
capitalist society. In this sense, Marx's mode of analysis, like those of Thomas
Malthus, Herbert Spencer, or Vilfredo Pareto, has become one of the theoretical
structures that are the heritage of the social scientist. (L.S.F./D.T.McL.)
The term Marxism is used in a number of
different ways. In its most essential meaning it refers to the thought of Karl
Marx but is usually extended to include that of his friend and collaborator
Friedrich Engels. There is also Marxism as it has been understood and practiced
by the various socialist movements, particularly
before 1914. Then there is Soviet Marxism as worked out by Lenin and modified by
Stalin, which under the name of Marxism-Leninism became the doctrine of the
communist parties set up after the Russian Revolution. Offshoots of this include
Marxism as interpreted by the anti-Stalinist Leon Trotsky and his followers, Mao
Zedong's (Mao Tse-tung's) Chinese variant of Marxism-Leninism, and various Third
World Marxisms. There are also the post-World War II nondogmatic Marxisms that
have modified Marx's thought with borrowings from modern philosophies,
principally from those of Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger but also from
Sigmund Freud and others.
The written work of Marx cannot be
reduced to a philosophy, much less to a philosophical system. The whole of his
work is a radical critique of philosophy, especially of Hegel's
idealist system and of the philosophies of the left and right post-Hegelians. It
is not, however, a mere denial of those philosophies. Marx declared that
philosophy must become reality. One could no longer be content with interpreting
the world; one must be concerned with transforming it, which meant transforming
both the world itself and men's consciousness of it. This, in turn, required a
critique of experience together with a critique of ideas. In fact, Marx believed
that all knowledge involved a critique of ideas. He was not an empiricist.
Rather, his work teems with concepts (appropriation, alienation, praxis,
creative labour, value, etc.) that he had inherited from earlier philosophers
and economists, including Hegel, Johann Fichte, Kant, Adam Smith, David Ricardo,
and John Stuart Mill. What uniquely characterizes the thought of Marx is that,
instead of making abstract affirmations about a whole group of problems such as
man, knowledge, matter, and nature, he examines each problem in its dynamic
relation to the others and, above all, tries to relate them to historical,
social, political, and economic realities. (see also Index:
Hegelianism)
In 1859, in the preface to his Contribution
to the Critique of Political Economy, Marx wrote that the hypothesis
that had served him as the basis for his analysis of society could be briefly
formulated as follows:
In the social production that men carry
on, they enter into definite relations that are indispensable and independent of
their will, relations of production which correspond to a definite stage of
development of their material forces of production. The sum total of these
relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real
foundation, on which rises a legal and political superstructure, and to which
correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production in
material life determines the general character of the social, political, and
intellectual processes of life. It is not the consciousness of men which
determines their existence; it is on the contrary their social existence which
determines their consciousness.
Raised to the level of historical law,
this hypothesis was subsequently called historical materialism. Marx applied it
to capitalist society, both in The Communist Manifesto and Das
Kapital and in other writings. Although Marx reflected upon his working
hypothesis for many years, he did not formulate it in a very exact manner:
different expressions served him for identical realities. If one takes the text
literally, social reality is structured in the following way:
1. Underlying everything as the real
basis of society is the economic structure (what in late 20th-century language
is sometimes called the infrastructure). This structure includes (a) the
"material forces of production," that is, the labour and means of
production, and (b) the overall "relations of production," or the
social and political arrangements that regulate production and distribution.
Although Marx stated that there is a correspondence between the "material
forces" of production and the indispensable "relations" of
production, he never made himself clear on the nature of the correspondence, a
fact that was to be the source of differing interpretations among his later
followers.
2. Above the economic structure rises
the superstructure consisting of legal and political "forms of social
consciousness" that correspond to the economic structure. Marx says nothing
about the nature of this correspondence between ideological forms and economic
structure, except that through the ideological forms men become conscious of the
conflict within the economic structure between the material forces of production
and the existing relations of production expressed in the legal property
relations. In other words, "The sum total of the forces of production
accessible to men determines the condition of society" and is at the base
of society. "The social structure and the state issue continually from the
life processes of definite individuals . . . as they are in
reality, that is acting and materially producing." The political
relations that men establish among themselves are dependent on material
production, as are the legal relations. This foundation of the social on the
economic is not an incidental point: it colours Marx's whole analysis. It is
found in Das Kapital as well as in The
German Ideology and the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844.
To go directly to the heart of the work
of Marx, one must focus on his concrete program for man. This is just as
important for an understanding of Marx as are The
Communist Manifesto and Das Kapital. Marx's
interpretation of man begins with human need. "Man," he wrote in the Economic
and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844,
is first of all a natural being. As a natural being and a living natural being, he is
endowed on the one hand with natural
powers, vital powers . . . ; these powers exist in him as aptitudes,
instincts. On the other hand, as an objective, natural, physical, sensitive
being, he is a suffering, dependent
and limited being . . . , that is, the objects
of his instincts exist outside him, independent of him, but are the objects
of his need, indispensable and
essential for the realization and confirmation of his substantial powers.
The point of departure of human history
is therefore living man, who seeks to satisfy certain primary needs. "The
first historical fact is the production of the means to satisfy these
needs." This satisfaction, in turn, opens the way for new needs. Human
activity is thus essentially a struggle with nature that must furnish man with
the means of satisfying his needs: drink, food, clothing, the development of his
powers and then of his intellectual and artistic abilities. In this undertaking,
man discovers himself as a productive being who humanizes himself by his labour.
Furthermore, man humanizes nature while he naturalizes himself. By his creative
activity, by his labour, he realizes his identity with the nature that he
masters, while at the same time he achieves free consciousness. Born of nature
man becomes fully human by opposing it. Becoming aware in his struggle against
nature of what separates him from it, man finds the conditions of his
fulfillment, of the realization of his true stature. The dawning of
consciousness is inseparable from struggle. By appropriating all the creative
energies, he discovers that "all that is called history is nothing else
than the process of creating man through human labour, the becoming of nature
for man. Man has thus evident and irrefutable proof of his own creation by
himself." Understood in its universal dimension, human activity reveals
that "for man, man is the supreme being." It is thus vain to speak of
God, creation, and metaphysical problems. Fully naturalized, man is sufficient
unto himself: he has recaptured the fullness of man in his full liberty.
Living in a capitalist society, however,
man is not truly free. He is an alienated being; he is not at home in his world.
The idea of alienation, which Marx takes from
Hegel and Feuerbach, plays a fundamental role in
the whole of his written work, starting with the writings of his youth and
continuing through Das Kapital. In the
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts the
alienation of labour is seen to spring from the fact that the more the worker
produces the less he has to consume, and the more values he creates the more he
devalues himself, because his product and his labour are estranged from him. The
life of the worker depends on things that he has created but that are not his,
so that, instead of finding his rightful existence through his labour, he loses
it in this world of things that are external to him: no work, no pay. Under
these conditions, labour denies the fullness of concrete man. "The generic
being (Gattungwesen) of man, nature as well as his intellectual faculties,
is transformed into a being which is alien to him, into a means of his individual existence." Nature, his body, his
spiritual essence become alien to him. "Man is made alien to man."
When carried to its highest stage of development, private property
becomes "the product of alienated labour . . . the means
by which labour alienates itself (and) the realization of this
alienation." It is also at the same time "the tangible material
expression of alienated human life."
(see also Index: production)
Although there is no evidence that Marx
ever disclaimed this anthropological analysis of alienated labour, starting with
The German Ideology, the historical,
social, and economic causes of the alienation of labour are given increasing
emphasis, especially in Das Kapital. Alienated
labour is seen as the consequence of market product, the division of labour, and
the division of society into antagonistic classes. As producers in society, men
create goods only by their labour. These goods are exchangeable. Their value
is the average amount of social labour spent to produce them. The alienation of
the worker takes on its full dimension in that system of market production in
which part of the value of the goods produced by the worker is taken away from
him and transformed into surplus value, which
the capitalist privately appropriates. Market production also intensifies the
alienation of labour by encouraging specialization, piecework, and the setting
up of large enterprises. Thus the labour power of the worker is used along with
that of others in a combination whose significance he is ignorant of, both
individually and socially. In thus losing their quality as human products, the
products of labour become fetishes, that is, alien and oppressive realities to
which both the man who possesses them privately and the man who is deprived of
them submit themselves. In the market economy, this submission to things is
obscured by the fact that the exchange of goods is expressed in money. (see also
Index: labour
theory of value)
This fundamental economic alienation is
accompanied by secondary political and ideological alienations, which offer a
distorted representation of and an illusory justification of a world in which
the relations of men with one another are also distorted. The ideas that men
form are closely bound up with their material activity and their material
relations: "The act of making representations, of thinking, the spiritual
intercourse of men, seem to be the direct emanation of their material
relations." This is true of all human activity: political, intellectual, or
spiritual. "Men produce their representations and their ideas, but it is as
living men, men acting as they are determined by a definite development of their
powers of production." Law, morality, metaphysics, and religion do not have
a history of their own. "Men developing their material production modify
together with their real existence their ways of thinking and the products of
their ways of thinking." In other words, "It is not consciousness
which determines existence, it is existence which determines
consciousness."
In bourgeois, capitalist society man is
divided into political citizen and economic man. This duality represents man's
political alienation, which is further intensified by the functioning of the
bourgeois state. From this study of society at the beginning of the 19th
century, Marx came to see the state as the
instrument through which the propertied class dominated other classes.
Ideological alienation, for Marx, takes
different forms, appearing in economic, philosophical, and legal theories. Marx
undertook a lengthy critique of the first in Das Kapital and of the second in The German Ideology. But ideological alienation expresses itself
supremely in religion. Taking up the ideas about religion that were current in
left post-Hegelian circles, together with the thought of Feuerbach, Marx
considered religion to be a product of man's consciousness. It is a reflection
of the situation of a man who "either has not conquered himself or has
already lost himself again" (man in the world of private property). It is
"an opium for the people." Unlike Feuerbach, Marx believed that
religion would disappear only with changes in society.
Marx analyzed the market economy system
in Das Kapital. In this work he
borrows most of the categories of the classical English economists Smith and
Ricardo but adapts them and introduces new concepts such as that of surplus
value. One of the distinguishing marks of Das
Kapital is that in it Marx studies the economy as a whole and not in one or
another of its aspects. His analysis is based on the idea that man is a
productive being and that all economic value comes from human labour. The system
he analyzes is principally that of mid-19th-century England. It is a system of
private enterprise and competition that arose in the 16th century from the
development of sea routes, international trade, and colonialism. Its rise had
been facilitated by changes in the forces of production (the division of labour
and the concentration of workshops), the adoption of mechanization, and
technical progress. The wealth of the societies that brought this economy into
play had been acquired through an "enormous accumulation of commodities."
Marx therefore begins with the study of this accumulation, analyzing the unequal
exchanges that take place in the market. (see also Index:
wealth and income, distribution of)
According to Marx, if the capitalist
advances funds to buy cotton yarn with which to produce fabrics and sells the
product for a larger sum than he paid, he is able to invest the difference in
additional production. "Not only is the value advance kept in circulation,
but it changes in its magnitude, adds a plus to itself, makes itself worth more,
and it is this movement that transforms it into capital."
The transformation, to Marx, is possible only because the capitalist has
appropriated the means of production, including the labour power of the worker.
Now labour power produces more than it is worth. The value of labour power is
determined by the amount of labour necessary for its reproduction or, in other
words, by the amount needed for the worker to subsist and beget children. But in
the hands of the capitalist the labour power employed in the course of a day
produces more than the value of the sustenance required by the worker and his
family. The difference between the two values is appropriated by the capitalist,
and it corresponds exactly to the surplus value realized by capitalists in the
market. Marx is not concerned with whether in capitalist society there are
sources of surplus value other than the exploitation of human labour--a fact
pointed out by Joseph Schumpeter (Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy). He remains content with
emphasizing this primary source:
Surplus value is produced by the
employment of labour power. Capital buys the labour power and pays the wages for
it. By means of his work the labourer creates new value which does not belong to
him, but to the capitalist. He must work a certain time merely in order to
reproduce the equivalent value of his wages. But when this equivalent value has
been returned, he does not cease work, but continues to do so for some further
hours. The new value which he produces during this extra time, and which exceeds
in consequence the amount of his wage, constitutes surplus value.
Throughout his analysis, Marx argues
that the development of capitalism is accompanied by increasing contradictions.
For example, the introduction of machinery is profitable to the individual
capitalist because it enables him to produce more goods at a lower cost, but new
techniques are soon taken up by his competitors. The outlay for machinery grows
faster than the outlay for wages. Since only labour can produce the surplus
value from which profit is derived, this means that the capitalist's rate of
profit on his total outlay tends to decline. Along with the declining rate of
profit goes an increase in unemployment. Thus, the equilibrium of the system is
precarious, subject as it is to the internal pressures resulting from its own
development. Crises shake it at regular intervals, preludes to the general
crisis that will sweep it away. This instability is increased by the formation
of a reserve army of workers, both factory workers and peasants, whose
pauperization keeps increasing. "Capitalist production develops the
technique and the combination of the process of social production only by
exhausting at the same time the two sources from which all wealth springs: the
earth and the worker." According to the Marxist dialectic, these
fundamental contradictions can only be resolved by a change from capitalism to a
new system.
Marx inherited the ideas of class and
class struggle from Utopian socialism and the theories of Saint-Simon. These had
been given substance by the writings of French historians such as Adolphe Thiers
and François Guizot on the French Revolution of 1789. But unlike the
French historians, Marx made class struggle the central fact of social
evolution. "The history of all hitherto existing human society is the
history of class struggles."
In Marx's view, the dialectical nature
of history is expressed in class struggle. With the development of capitalism,
the class struggle takes an acute form. Two basic classes, around which other
less important classes are grouped, oppose each other in the capitalist system:
the owners of the means of production, or bourgeoisie, and the workers, or proletariat.
"The bourgeoisie produces its own grave-diggers. The fall of the
bourgeoisie and the victory of the proletariat are equally inevitable" (The
Communist Manifesto) because
the bourgeois relations of production
are the last contradictory form of the process of social production,
contradictory not in the sense of an individual contradiction, but of a
contradiction that is born of the conditions of social existence of individuals;
however, the forces of production which develop in the midst of bourgeois
society create at the same time the material conditions for resolving this
contradiction. With this social development the prehistory of human society
ends.
When man has become aware of his loss,
of his alienation, as a universal nonhuman situation, it will be possible for
him to proceed to a radical transformation of his situation by a revolution.
This revolution will be the prelude to the establishment of communism and the
reign of liberty reconquered. "In the place of the old bourgeois society
with its classes and its class antagonisms, there will be an association in
which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of
all."
But for Marx there are two views of
revolution. One is that of a final conflagration, "a violent suppression of the old conditions of production," which
occurs when the opposition between bourgeoisie and proletariat has been carried
to its extreme point. This conception is set forth in a manner inspired by the
Hegelian dialectic of the master and the slave, in The Holy Family. The other
conception is that of a permanent revolution involving a provisional coalition
between the proletariat and the petty bourgeoisie rebelling against a capitalism
that is only superficially united. Once a majority has been won to the
coalition, an unofficial proletarian authority constitutes itself alongside the
revolutionary bourgeois authority. Its mission is the political and
revolutionary education of the proletariat, gradually assuring the transfer of
legal power from the revolutionary bourgeoisie to the revolutionary proletariat.
If one reads The Communist Manifesto carefully one discovers inconsistencies that
indicate that Marx had not reconciled the concepts of catastrophic and of
permanent revolution. Moreover, Marx never analyzed classes as specific groups
of men opposing other groups of men. Depending on the writings and the periods,
the number of classes varies; and unfortunately the pen fell from Marx's hand at
the moment when, in Das Kapital (vol.
3), he was about to take up the question. Reading Das Kapital, one is furthermore left with an ambiguous impression
with regard to the destruction of capitalism: will it be the result of the
"general crisis" that Marx expects, or of the action of the conscious
proletariat, or of both at once?
Engels
became a communist in 1842 and discovered the proletariat of England when he
took over the management of the Manchester factory belonging to his father's
cotton firm. In 1844, the year he began his close association and friendship
with Marx, Engels was finishing his "Umrisse zu einer Kritik der Nationalökonomie"
("Outline of a Critique of Political Economy")--a critique of Smith,
Ricardo, Mill, and J.B. Say. This remarkable study contained in seminal form the
critique that Marx was to make of bourgeois political economy in Das
Kapital. During the first years of his stay in Manchester, Engels observed
carefully the life of the workers of that great industrial centre and described
it in Die Lage der arbeitenden Klassen in
England (The
Condition of the Working Class in England), published in 1845 in
Leipzig. This work was an analysis of the evolution of industrial capitalism and
its social consequences. He collaborated with Marx in the writing of The
Holy Family, The German Ideology, and The
Communist Manifesto. The correspondence between them is of fundamental
importance for the student of Das Kapital,
for it shows how Engels contributed by furnishing Marx with a great amount
of technical and economic data and by criticizing the successive drafts. This
collaboration lasted until Marx's death and was carried on posthumously with the
publication of the manuscripts left by Marx, which Engels edited, forming
volumes 2 and 3 of Das Kapital. He
also wrote various articles on Marx's work.
In response to criticism of Marx's ideas
by a socialist named Eugen Dühring, Engels
published several articles that were collected under the title Herr
Eugen Dührings Umwälzung der Wissenschaft, which appeared in 1878
(Herr Eugen Dühring's
Revolution in Science [Anti-Dühring]),
and an unfinished work, Dialektik und
Natur (1927; Dialectics of Nature),
which he had begun around 1875-76. The importance of these writings to the
subsequent development of Marxism can be seen from Lenin's observation that
Engels "developed, in a clear and often polemical style, the most general
scientific questions and the different phenomena of the past and present
according to the materialist understanding of history and the economic theory of
Karl Marx." But Engels was driven to simplify problems with a view to being
pedagogical; he tended to schematize and systematize things as if the
fundamental questions were settled. The connections that he thus established
between some of Marx's governing ideas and some of the scientific ideas of his
age gave rise to the notion that there is a complete Marxist philosophy. The
idea was to play a significant role in the transition of Marxism from a
"critique of daily life" to an integrated doctrine in which
philosophy, history, and the sciences are fused.
Anti-Dühring
is of fundamental importance for it constitutes
the link between Marx and certain forms of modern Marxism. It contains three
parts: Philosophy, Political Economy, and Socialism. In the first, Engels
attempts to establish that the natural sciences and even mathematics are dialectical,
in the sense that observable reality is dialectical: the dialectical method of
analysis and thought is imposed on men by the material forces with which they
deal. It is thus rightly applied to the study of history and human society.
"Motion, in effect, is the mode of existence of matter," Engels
writes. In using materialistic dialectic to make
a critique of Dühring's thesis, according to which political forces prevail
over all the rest in the molding of history, Engels provides a good illustration
of the materialistic idea of history, which puts the stress on the prime role of
economic factors as driving forces in history. The other chapters of the section
Political Economy form a very readable introduction to the principal economic
ideas of Marx: value (simple and complex), labour, capital, and surplus value.
The section Socialism starts by formulating anew the critique of the capitalist
system as it was made in Das Kapital. At
the end of the chapters devoted to production, distribution, the state, the
family, and education, Engels outlines what the socialist society will be like,
a society in which the notion of value has no longer anything to do with the
distribution of the goods produced because all labour "becomes at once and
directly social labour," and the amount of social labour that every product
contains no longer needs to be ascertained by "a detour." A production
plan will coordinate the economy. The division of labour and the separation of
town and country will disappear with the "suppression of the capitalist
character of modern industry." Thanks to the plan, industry will be located
throughout the country in the collective interest, and thus the opposition
between town and country will disappear--to the profit of both industry and
agriculture. Finally, after the liberation of man from the condition of servitude
in which the capitalist mode of production holds him, the state will also be
abolished and religion will disappear by "natural death."
One of the most remarkable features of Anti-Dühring
is the insistence with which Engels refuses to base socialism on absolute
values. He admits only relative values, linked to historical, economic, and
social conditions. Socialism cannot possibly be based on ethical principles:
each epoch can only successfully carry out that of which it is capable. Marx had
written this in his preface of 1859.
Karl
Marx and Marxism
The theoretical leadership after Engels
was taken by Karl Kautsky, editor of the official organ of the German Social
Democratic Party, Die Neue
Zeit. He wrote Karl Marx' ökonomische Lehren (1887; The Economic Doctrines of Karl Marx), in which the work of Marx is
presented as essentially an economic theory. Kautsky reduced the ideas of Marx
and Marxist historical dialectic to a kind of evolutionism.
He laid stress on the increasing pauperization of the working class and on the
increasing degree of capitalist concentration. While opposing all compromise
with the bourgeois state, he accepted the contention that the socialist movement
should support laws benefiting the workers provided that they did not reinforce
the power of the state. Rejecting the idea of an alliance between the working
class and the peasantry, he believed that the overthrow of the capitalist state
and the acquisition of political power by the working class could be realized in
a peaceful way, without upsetting the existing structures. As an
internationalist he supported peace, rejecting war and violence. For him, war
was a product of capitalism. Such were the main features of "orthodox"
German Marxism at the time when the "revisionist"
theories of Eduard Bernstein appeared.
Bernstein created a great controversy
with articles that he wrote in 1896 for Die
Neue Zeit, arguing that Marxism needed to be revised. His divergence widened
with the publication in 1899 of Die
Voraussetzungen des Sozialismus und die Aufgaben der Sozialdemokratie ( Evolutionary
Socialism), to which rejoinders were made by Kautsky in Bernstein
und das Sozialdemokratische Programm: Eine Antikritik (1899; "Bernstein
and the Social Democratic Program") and the Polish-born Marxist Rosa
Luxemburg in Sozialreform oder
Revolution ( Reform
or Revolution), both in 1899. Bernstein focused first of all upon the
labour theory of value. Along with the
economists of his time he considered it outdated, both in the form expounded by
British classical economists and as set forth in Das Kapital. He argued, moreover, that class struggle was becoming
less rather than more intense, for concentration was not accelerating in
industry as Marx had forecast, and in agriculture it was not increasing at all.
Bernstein demonstrated this on the basis of German, Dutch, and English
statistical data. He also argued that cartels and business syndicates were
smoothing the evolution of capitalism, a fact that cast doubt on the validity of
Marx's theory of capitalistic crises. Arguing that quite a few of Marx's
theories were not scientifically based, Bernstein blamed the Hegelian and
Ricardian structure of Marx's work for his failure to take sufficient account of
observable reality. (see also Index: value)
To this, Kautsky replied that, with the
development of capitalism, agriculture was becoming a sector more and more
dependent on industry, and that in addition an industrialization of agriculture
was taking place. Luxemburg took the position that the contradictions of
capitalism did not cease to grow with the progress of finance capitalism and the
exploitation of the colonies, and that these contradictions were leading to a
war that would give the proletariat its opportunity to assume power by
revolutionary means.
One of the most divisive questions was
that of war and peace. This was brought to the fore at the outbreak of World War
I, when Social Democratic deputies in the German Reichstag voted for the
financing of the war. Among German Marxists who opposed the war were Karl
Liebknecht and Luxemburg. Liebknecht was imprisoned in 1916 for agitating
against the war. On his release in 1918 he took the leadership of the Spartacist
movement, which was later to become the Communist Party of Germany. Luxemburg
had also been arrested for her antimilitary activities. In addition to her
articles, signed Junius, in which she debated with Lenin on the subject of World
War I and the attitude of the Marxists toward it (published in 1916 as Die
Krise der Sozialdemokratie [The Crisis
in the German Social-Democracy]), she is known for her book Die
Akkumulation des Kapitals (1913; The
Accumulation of Capital). In this work she returned to Marx's
economic analysis of capitalism, in particular the accumulation of capital as
expounded in volume 2 of Das Kapital. There
she found a contradiction that had until then been unnoticed: Marx's scheme
seems to imply that the development of capitalism can be indefinite, though
elsewhere he sees the contradictions of the system as bringing about
increasingly violent economic crises that will inevitably sweep capitalism away.
Luxemburg concluded that Marx's scheme is oversimplified and assumes a universe
made up entirely of capitalists and workers. If increases in productivity are
taken into account, she asserted, balance between the two sectors becomes
impossible; in order to keep expanding, capitalists must find new markets in
noncapitalist spheres, either among peasants and artisans or in colonies and
underdeveloped countries. Capitalism will collapse only when exploitation of the
world outside it (the peasantry, colonies, etc.) has reached a limit. This
conclusion has been the subject of passionate controversies. (see also Index: "Crisis in the German Social-
Democracy, The," )
The Austrian school came into being when
Austrian socialists started publishing their works independently of the Germans;
it can be dated from either 1904 (beginning of the Marx-Studien
collection) or 1907 (publication of the magazine Der
Kampf ). The most important members of the school were Max Adler, Karl
Renner, Rudolf Hilferding, Gustav Eckstein,
Friedrich Adler, and Otto Bauer. The most
eminent was Bauer, a brilliant theoretician whose Die
Nationalitätenfrage und die Sozialdemokratie (1906; "The
Nationalities Question and the Social Democracy") was critically reviewed
by Lenin. In this work he dealt with the problem of nationalities in the light
of the experience of the Austro-Hungarian Empire. He favoured the
self-determination of peoples and emphasized the cultural elements in the
concept of nationhood. Hilferding was finance minister of the German Republic
after World War I in the Cabinets of the Social Democrats Gustav Stresemann
(1923) and Hermann Müller (1928). He is known especially for his work Das
Finanzkapital (1910), in which he maintained that capitalism had come
under the control of banks and industrial monopolies. The growth of national
competition and tariff barriers, he believed, had led to economic warfare
abroad. Hilferding's ideas strongly influenced Lenin, who analyzed them in Imperialism, the Highest Stage of Capitalism (1916).
Das
Kapital was translated into Russian in 1872. Marx
kept up more or less steady relations with the Russian socialists and took an
interest in the economic and social conditions of the tsarist empire. The man
who originally introduced Marxism into Russia was Georgi Plekhanov, but the man
who adapted Marxism to Russian conditions was Lenin. (see also Index:
Leninism)
Vladimir Ilich Ulyanov, or Lenin, was
born in 1870 at Simbirsk (now Ulyanovsk). He entered the University of Kazan to
study law but was expelled the same year for participating in student agitation.
In 1893 he settled in St. Petersburg and became actively involved with the
revolutionary workers. With his pamphlet What Is To Be Done? (1902), he
specified the theoretical principles and organization of a Marxist party as he
thought it should be constituted. He took part in the second Congress of the Russian
Social-Democratic Workers' Party, which was held in Brussels and London
(1903), and induced the majority of the Congress members to adopt his views. Two
factions formed at the Congress: the Bolshevik
(from the Russian word for "larger")
with Lenin as the leader and the Menshevik (from
the Russian word for "smaller") with Julius
Martov at the head. The former wanted a restricted party of militants and
advocated the dictatorship of the proletariat. The latter wanted a wide-open
proletarian party, collaboration with the liberals, and a democratic
constitution for Russia. In his pamphlet One
Step Forward, Two Steps Back (1904), Lenin compared the organizational
principles of the Bolsheviks to those of the Mensheviks. After the failure of
the 1905 Russian revolution, he drew positive lessons for the future in Two Tactics of Social Democracy in the Democratic Revolution. He
fiercely attacked the influence of Kantian philosophy on German and Russian
Marxism in Materialism and
Empirio-criticism (1908). In 1912 at the Prague Conference the Bolsheviks
constituted themselves as an independent party. During World War I Lenin resided
in Switzerland, where he studied Hegel's Science of Logic and the development of capitalism and carried on
debates with Marxists like Rosa Luxemburg on the meaning of the war and the
right of nations to self-determination. In 1915 at Zimmerwald, and in 1916 at
Kiental, he organized two international socialist conferences to fight against
the war. Immediately after the February 1917 revolution he returned to Russia,
and in October the Bolshevik coup brought him to power.
The situation of Russia and the Russian
revolutionary movement at the end of the 19th century and the beginning of the
20th led Lenin to diverge, in the course of his development and his analyses,
from the positions both of "orthodox Marxism" and of
"revisionism." He rediscovered the original thought of Marx by a
careful study of his works, in particular Das
Kapital and The
Holy Family. He saw Marxism as a practical affair and tried to go
beyond the accepted formulas to plan political action that would come to grips
with the surrounding world.
As early as 1894, in his populist study The
Friends of the People, Lenin took up Marx's distinction between the
"material social relations" of men and their "ideological social
relations." In Lenin's eyes the importance of Das
Kapital was that "while explaining
the structure and the development of the social formation seen exclusively in terms of its relations of production, (Marx) has
nevertheless everywhere and always analyzed the superstructure which corresponds
to these relations of production." In The Development of Russian Capitalism (1897-99)
Lenin sought to apply Marx's analysis by showing the growing role of capital, in
particular commercial capital, in the exploitation of the workers in the
factories and the large-scale expropriation of the peasants.
It was thus possible to apply to Russia the models developed by Marx for western
Europe. At the same time Lenin did not lose sight of the importance of the
peasant in Russian society. Although a disciple of Marx, he did not believe that
he had only to repeat Marx's conclusions. He wrote:
We do not consider the theory of Marx
to be a complete, immutable whole. We think on the contrary that this theory has
only laid the cornerstone of the science, a science which socialists must
further develop in all directions if they do not want to let themselves be
overtaken by life. We think that, for the Russian socialists, an independent
elaboration of the theory is particularly necessary.
Lenin laid great stress upon the
dialectical method. In his early writings he defined the dialectic as
"nothing more nor less than the method of sociology, which sees society as
a living organism, in perpetual development (and not as something mechanically
assembled and thus allowing all sorts of arbitrary combinations of the various
social elements) . . . " (The Friends
of the People, 1894). After having studied Hegel toward the end of 1914, he
took a more activist view. Dialectic is not only evolution; it is praxis,
leading from activity to reflection and from reflection to action.
Lenin also put much emphasis on the
leading role of the party. As early as 1902 he was concerned with the need for a
cohesive party with a correct doctrine, adapted to the exigencies of the period,
which would be a motive force among the masses, helping to bring them to an
awareness of their real situation. In What
Is To Be Done? he called for a party of professional revolutionaries,
disciplined and directed, capable of defeating the police; its aim should be to
establish the dictatorship of the proletariat. In order to do this, he wrote in Two
Tactics of Social-Democracy in the Democratic Revolution, it was necessary
"to subject the insurrection of the proletarian and non-proletarian
masses to our influence, to our direction, to use it in our best
interests." But this was not possible without a doctrine: "Without
revolutionary theory, no revolutionary movement." On the eve of the
revolution of October 1917, in The
State and Revolution he set forth the conditions for the dictatorship
of the proletariat and the suppression of the capitalist state.
Lenin assigned major importance to the peasantry
in formulating his program. It would be a serious error, he held, for the
Russian revolutionary workers' movement to neglect the peasants. Even though it
was clear that the industrial proletariat constituted the vanguard of the
revolution, the discontent of the peasantry could be oriented in a direction
favourable to the revolution by placing among the goals of the party the seizure
of privately owned land. As early as 1903, at the third congress of the party,
he secured a resolution to this effect. Thereafter, the dictatorship of the
proletariat became the dictatorship of the proletariat and the peasantry. In
1917 he encouraged the peasants to seize land long before the approval of
agrarian reform by the Constituent Assembly.
Among Lenin's legacies to Soviet Marxism
was one that proved to be injurious to the party. This was the decision taken at
his behest by the 10th congress of the party in the spring of 1921, while the
sailors were rebelling at Kronstadt and the peasants were growing restless in
the countryside, to forbid all factions, all factional activity, and all
opposition political platforms within the party. This decision had grave
consequences in later years when Stalin used it against his opponents. (see also
Index: Union
of Soviet Socialist Republics, )
It is Joseph
Stalin who codified the body of ideas that, under the name of
Marxism-Leninism, has constituted the official doctrine of the Soviet and
eastern European communist parties. Stalin was a man of action in a slightly
different sense than was Lenin. Gradually taking over power after Lenin's death
in 1924, he pursued the development of the Soviet Union with great vigour. By
practicing Marxism, he assimilated it, at the same time simplifying it. Stalin's
Marxism-Leninism rests on the dialectic of Hegel, as set forth in A
Short History of the Communist Party of the Soviet Union (1938), and on a
materialism that can be considered roughly identical to that of Feuerbach. His
work Problems of Leninism, which appeared
in 11 editions during his lifetime, sets forth an ideology of power and activism
that rides roughshod over the more nuanced approach of Lenin. (see also Index:
Stalinism)
Soviet dialectical
materialism can be reduced to four laws: (1) History is a dialectical
development. It proceeds by successive phases that supersede one another. These
phases are not separate, any more than birth, growth, and death are separate.
Though it is true that phase B necessarily negates phase A, it remains that
phase B was already contained in phase A and was initiated by it. The dialectic
does not regard nature as an accidental accumulation of objects, of isolated and
independent phenomena, but as a unified, coherent whole. Furthermore, nature is
perpetually in movement, in a state of unceasing renewal and development, in
which there is always something being born and developing and something
disintegrating and disappearing. (2) Evolution takes place in leaps, not
gradually. (3) Contradictions must be made manifest. All phenomena contain in
themselves contradictory elements. "Dialectic starts from the point of view
that objects and natural phenomena imply internal contradictions, because they
all have a positive and a negative side." These contradictory elements are
in perpetual struggle: it is this struggle that is the "internal content of
the process of development," according to Stalin. (4) The law of this
development is economic. All other contradictions are rooted in the basic
economic relationship. A given epoch is entirely determined by the relations of production
existing among men. They are social relations; relations of collaboration or
mutual aid, relations of domination or submission; and finally, transitory
relations that characterize a period of passage from one system to another.
"The history of the development of society is, above all, the history of
the development of production, the history of the modes of production which
succeed one another through the centuries." (see also Index: social evolution)
From these principles may be drawn the
following inferences, essential for penetrating the workings of Marxist-Leninist
thought and its application. No natural phenomenon, no historical or social
situation, no political fact, can be considered independently of the other facts
or phenomena that surround it; it is set within a whole. Since movement is the
essential fact, one must distinguish between what is beginning to decay and what
is being born and developing. Since the process of development takes place by
leaps, one passes suddenly from a succession of slow quantitative changes to a
radical qualitative change. In the social or political realm, these sudden
qualitative changes are revolutions, carried out by the oppressed classes. One
must follow a frankly proletarian-class policy that exposes the contradictions
of the capitalist system. A reformist policy makes no sense. Consequently (1)
nothing can be judged from the point of view of "eternal justice" or
any other preconceived notion and (2) no social system is immutable. To be
effective, one must not base one's action on social strata that are no longer
developing, even if they represent for the moment the dominant force, but on
those that are developing.
Stalin's materialist and historical
dialectic differs sharply from the perspective of Karl Marx. In The
Communist Manifesto Marx applied the materialist dialectic to the social and
political life of his time. In the chapter entitled "Bourgeois and
Proletarians," he studied the process of the growth of the revolutionary
bourgeoisie within feudal society, then the genesis and the growth of the
proletariat within capitalism, placing the emphasis on the struggle between
antagonistic classes. To be sure, he connected social evolution with the
development of the forces of production. What counted for him, however, was not
only the struggle but also the birth of consciousness among the proletariat.
"As to the final victory of the propositions put forth in the Manifesto,
Marx expected it to come primarily from the intellectual development of the
working class, necessarily the result of common action and discussion"
(Engels, preface to the republication of The
Communist Manifesto, May 1, 1890).
The result of Stalin's dialectic,
however, was what he called revolution from above, a dictatorial policy to
increase industrialization and collectivize agriculture based upon ruthless
repression and a strong centralization of power. For Stalin what counted was the
immediate goal, the practical result. The move was from a dialectic that
emphasized both the objective and the subjective to one purely objective, or
more exactly, objectivist. Human actions are to be judged not by taking account
of the intentions of the actor and their place in a given historical web but
only in terms of what they signify objectively at the end of the period
considered.
Alongside Marxism-Leninism as expounded
in the former Soviet Union, there arose another point of view expressed by
Stalin's opponent Leon Trotsky and his
followers. Trotsky played a leading role in both the Russian Revolution of 1905
and that of 1917. After Lenin's death he fell out with Stalin. Their conflict
turned largely upon questions of policy, both domestic and foreign. In the realm
of ideas, Trotsky held that a revolution in a backward, rural country could be
carried out only by the proletariat. Once in
power the proletariat must carry out agrarian reform and undertake the
accelerated development of the economy. The revolution must be a socialist one,
involving the abolition of the private ownership of the means of production, or
else it will fail. But the revolution cannot be carried out in isolation, as
Stalin maintained it could. The capitalist countries will try to destroy it;
moreover, to succeed the revolution must be able to draw upon the industrial
techniques of the developed countries. For these reasons the revolution must be
worldwide and permanent, directed against the liberal and nationalist
bourgeoisie of all countries and using local victories to advance the
international struggle.
Tactically, Trotsky emphasized the
necessity of finding or creating a revolutionary situation, of educating the
working class in order to revolutionize it, of seeing that the party remained
open to the various revolutionary tendencies and avoided becoming
bureaucratized, and finally, when the time for insurrection comes, of organizing
it according to a detailed plan.
When the Chinese
Communists took power in 1948, they brought with them a new kind of Marxism that
came to be called Maoism after their leader Mao Zedong.
The thought of Mao must always be seen against the changing revolutionary
reality of China from 1930 onward. His thought was complex, a Marxist type of
analysis combined with the permanent fundamentals of Chinese thought and
culture.
One of its central elements has to do
with the nature and role of contradictions in socialist society. For Mao, every
society, including socialist (communist) society, contained "two different
types of contradictions": (1) antagonistic contradictions--contradictions
between us (the people) and our enemies (the Chinese bourgeoisie faithful),
between the imperialist camp and the socialist camp, and so forth--which are
resolved by revolution, and (2) nonantagonistic contradictions--between the
government and the people under a socialist regime, between two groups within
the Communist Party, between one section of the people and another under a
communist regime, and so forth--which are resolved by vigorous fraternal
criticism and self-criticism.
The notion of contradiction is specific
to Mao's thought in that it differs from the conceptions of Marx or Lenin. For
Mao, in effect, contradictions were at the same time universal and particular.
In their universality, one must seek and discover what constitutes their
particularity: every contradiction displays a particular character, depending on
the nature of things and phenomena. Contradictions have alternating
aspects--sometimes strongly marked, sometimes blurred. Some of these aspects are
primary, others secondary. It is important to define them well, for if one fails
to do so, the analysis of the social reality and the actions that follow from it
will be mistaken. This is quite far from Stalinism and dogmatic
Marxism-Leninism.
Another essential element of Mao's
thought, which must be seen in the context of revolutionary China, is the notion
of permanent revolution. It is an old idea
advocated in different contexts by Marx, Lenin, and Trotsky but lacking, in
Mao's formulation, the international dimension espoused by his predecessors. For
Mao it followed from his ideas about the struggle of man against nature (held
from 1938, at least); the campaigns for the rectification of thought (1942,
1951, 1952); and the necessity of struggling against bureaucracy, wastage, and
corruption in a country of 600,000,000 to 700,000,000 inhabitants, where very
old civilizations and cultures still permeated both the bourgeois classes and
the peasantry, where bureaucracy was thoroughly entrenched, and where the
previous society was extremely corrupt. It arose from Mao's conviction that the
rhythm of the revolution must be accelerated. This conviction appeared in 1957
in his speeches and became manifest in 1958 in the "Great
Leap Forward," followed in 1966 by the Cultural
Revolution.
Mao's concept of permanent revolution
rests upon the existence of nonantagonistic contradictions in the China of today
and of tomorrow. Men must be mobilized into a permanent movement in order to
carry forward the revolution and to prevent the ruling group from turning bourgeois
(as he perceived it had in the Soviet Union). It is necessary to shape among the
masses a new vision of the world by tearing them from their passivity and their
century-old habits. This is the background of the Cultural Revolution that began
in 1966, following previous campaigns but differing from them in its magnitude
and, it would seem, in the mobilization of youth against the cadres of the
party. In these campaigns Mao drew upon his past as a revolutionary Marxist
peasant leader, from his life in the red military and peasant bases and among
the Red Guards of Yen-an, seeking in his past experience ways to mobilize the
whole Chinese population against the dangers--internal and external--that
confronted it in the present.
The distinguishing characteristic of
Maoism is that it represents a peasant type of Marxism, with a principally rural
and military outlook. While basing himself on Marxism-Leninism, adapted to
Chinese requirements, Mao was rooted in the peasant life from which he himself
came, in the revolts against the warlords and the bureaucrats that have filled
the history of China. By integrating this experience into a universal vision of
history, Mao gave it a significance that flows beyond the provincial limits of
China.
In his effort to remain close to the
Chinese peasant masses, Mao drew upon an idea of nature and a symbolism found in
popular Chinese Taoism, though transformed by
his Marxism. It can be seen in his many poems, which were written in the
classical Chinese style. This idea of nature is accompanied in his written
political works by the Promethean idea of man struggling in a war against
nature, a conception in his thought that goes back at least to 1938 and became
more important after 1955 as the rhythm of the revolution accelerated.
The Marxism of Fidel
Castro expresses itself as a rejection of injustice in any
form--political, economic, or social. In this sense it is related to the liberal
democracy and Pan-Americanism of Simón Bolívar in Latin America
during the 19th century. In its liberalism, Castro's early socialism resembled
the various French socialisms of the first half of the 19th century. Only
gradually did Castroism come to identify itself with Marxism-Leninism, although
from the very beginning of the Cuban revolution Castro revealed his attachment
to certain of Marx's ideas. Castro's Marxism rejects some of the tenets and
practices of official Marxism-Leninism: it is outspoken against dogmatism,
bureaucracy, and sectarianism. In one sense, Castroism is a Marxist-Leninist
"heresy." It exalts the ethos of guerrilla revolution over party
politics. At the same time it aims to apply a purer Marxism to the conditions of
Cuba: alleged American imperialism, a single-crop economy, a low initial level
of political and economic development. One may call it an attempt to realize a
synthesis of Marxist ideas and the ideas of Bolívar.
In the ideological and political
conflicts that divide the communist world, Castroism takes a more or less
unengaged position. Castro is above all a nationalist and only after that a
Marxist.
The development of Marxist variants in
the Third World has been primarily influenced by the undeveloped industrial
state and the former colonial status of the nations in question. In the
traditional Marxist view the growth of capitalism is seen as a step necessary
for the breakup of precapitalist peasant society and for the rise of the
revolutionary proletariat class. Some theorists believe, however, that
capitalism introduced by imperialist rather than indigenous powers sustains
rather than destroys the feudal structure of peasant society and promotes
underdevelopment because resources and surplus are usurped by the colonial
powers. Furthermore, the revolutionary socialist movement becomes subordinate to
that of national liberation, which violates Marx's theory of class struggle by
uniting all indigenous classes in the common cause of anti-imperialism. For
these reasons, many Third World countries have chosen to follow the Maoist
model, with its emphasis on agrarian revolution against feudalism and
imperialism, rather than the old Soviet one. Another alternative, one specific
to the Third World, also exists. This policy bypasses capitalism and depends
upon the established strength of other communist countries for support against
imperialism.
There are two main forms of Marxism in
the West: that of the traditional communist parties and the more diffuse
"New Left" form, which has come to be known as "Western
Marxism." In general, the success of western European communist parties had
been hindered by their perceived allegiance to the old Soviet authority rather
than their own countries; the secretive, bureaucratic form of organization they
inherited from Lenin; the ease with which they became integrated into capitalist
society; and their consequent fear of compromising their principles by sharing
power with bourgeois parties. The Western parties basically adhered to the
policies of Soviet Marxism until the 1970s, when they began to advocate
Eurocommunism, a moderate version of communism that they felt would broaden
their base of appeal beyond the working class and thus improve their chances for
political success. As described by Enrico Berlinguer, Georges Marchais, and
Santiago Carrillo, the leaders of the Italian, French, and Spanish communist
parties, respectively, Eurocommunism favoured a peaceful, democratic approach to
achieving socialism, encouraged making alliances with other political parties,
guaranteed civil liberties, and renounced the central authority of the Soviet
party. By the 1980s Eurocommunism had largely been abandoned as unsuccessful,
and communist parties in advanced capitalist nations returned to orthodox
Marxism-Leninism despite the concomitant problems.
Western Marxism, however, can be seen as
a repudiation of Marxism-Leninism, although, when it was first formulated in the
1920s, its proponents believed they were loyal to the dominant Soviet Communist
Party. Prominent figures in the evolution of Western Marxism include the central
Europeans György Lukács, Karl Korsch, and Lucien Goldmann; Antonio
Gramsci of Italy; the German theorists who constituted the Frankfurt school,
especially Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, and Jürgen
Habermas; and Henri Lefebvre, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty of
France.
Western Marxism has been shaped
primarily by the failure of the socialist revolution in the Western world.
Western Marxists were concerned less with the actual political or economic
practice of Marxism than with its philosophical interpretation, especially in
relation to cultural and historical studies. In order to explain the inarguable
success of capitalist society, they felt they needed to explore and understand
non-Marxist approaches and all aspects of bourgeois culture. Eventually, they
came to believe that traditional Marxism was not relevant to the reality of
modern Western society.
Marx had predicted that revolution would
succeed in Europe first, but, in fact, the Third World has proved more
responsive. Orthodox Marxism also championed the technological achievements
associated with capitalism, viewing them as
essential to the progress of socialism. Experience showed the Western Marxists,
however, that technology did not necessarily produce the crises Marx described
and did not lead inevitably to revolution. In particular they disagreed with the
idea, originally emphasized by Engels, that Marxism is an integrated, scientific
doctrine that can be applied universally to nature; they viewed it as a critique
of human life, not an objective, general science. Disillusioned by the terrorism
of the Stalin era and the bureaucracy of the Communist Party system, they
advocated the idea of government by workers' councils, which they believed would
eliminate professional politicians and would more truly represent the interests
of the working class. Later, when the working class appeared to them to be too
well integrated into the capitalist system, the Western Marxists supported more
anarchistic tactics. In general, their views are more in accord with those found
in Marx's early, humanist writings rather than with his later, dogmatic
interpretations.
Western Marxism has found support
primarily among intellectuals rather than the working class, and orthodox
Marxists have judged it impractical. Nevertheless, the Western Marxists'
emphasis on Marx's social theory and their critical assessment of Marxist
methodology and ideas have coloured the way even non-Marxists view the world.
(H.C./
D.T.McL./Ed.)
|
¸¶¸£Å©½º (Karl
(Heinrich) Marx). 1818.
5. 5 ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ¶óÀÎ Æ®¸®¾î~1883. 3. 14 ·±´ø. µ¶ÀÏÀÇ
»çȸÇÐÀÚ¡¤°æÁ¦ÇÐÀÚ¡¤Á¤Ä¡À̷а¡.
|
¸¶¸£Å©½º
|
'¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ'(°ø»êÁÖÀÇ)ÀÇ
â½ÃÀڷμ ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í
ÇÔ²² ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei¡µ(1848)¡¤¡´ÀÚº»·Ð
Das Kapital¡µ(1867, 1885, 1894)À» ÁýÇÊÇß´Ù.
Ãʱâ»ý¾Ö
Ä«¸¦
ÇÏÀθ®È÷ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â 1818³â 5¿ù 5ÀÏ
ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ ¶óÀÎ ÁÖ Æ®¸®¾î ½Ã¿¡¼ 7³²¸Å Áß Ã¹Â°·Î
ž´Ù. ¸í¸ÁÀÖ´Â º¯È£»ç¿´´ø ¾Æ¹öÁö´Â ÄÆ®¿Í º¼Å׸£ÀÇ
°è¸ùÁÖÀÇ »ç»ó¿¡ ½ÉÃëÇØ ÀÖ¾ú°í ¾Æ¸íÀÌ Ç¿¡Å¸
ÇÁ·¹½ººÎ¸£Å©¿´´ø ¾î¸Ó´Ï´Â ³×´ú¶õµå Ãâ½ÅÀ̾ú´Ù. ¾çÄ£
¸ðµÎ À¯´ë Ç÷ÅëÀ̾úÀ¸³ª ¾Æ¹öÁö´Â Ä«¸¦ÀÌ Å¾±â 1³â ÀüÂë(¾Æ¸¶µµ
Çö½ÇÀûÀÎ Çʿ信¼) º¹À½ÁÖÀÇ ±¹±³È¸ÀÇ ¼¼·Ê¸¦ ¹Þ¾Ò°í, Ä«¸¦
¿ª½Ã 6¼¼°¡ µÇ´ø ÇØ¿¡ ¼¼·Ê¸¦ ¹Þ¾Ò´Ù. À¯´ëÀÎÀÌ °¨´çÇØ¾ß
ÇÏ´Â »çȸÀû Æí°ß°ú Â÷º°Àº ¾î¸° ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô Á¾±³ÀÇ
¿ªÇÒ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÀDZ¸½É°ú »çȸ°³ÇõÀÇ ¿¸ÁÀ» ºÒ·¯ÀÏÀ¸Ä×´Ù.
1830³â
Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Æ®¸®¾î ±è³ªÁö¿ò¿¡ ÀÔÇÐÇß´Ù. Çб³´Â
ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇ ±³»ç¿Í ÇлýµéÀÇ Àº½Åó°¡ µÇ¾ú°í, °æÂûÀÇ °¨½Ã°¡
²÷ÀÌÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. û³â ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ±Û ¼Ó¿¡´Â ±×¸®½ºµµ±³Àû
ºÀ»ç¿Í ÀÚ±âÈñ»ýÀÇ ÀÇÁö°¡ ¿ª·ÂÈ÷ µå·¯³ª ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. 1835³â 10¿ù
Ä«¸¦Àº º»´ëÇб³·ÎºÎÅÍ ÀÔÇÐÅëÁö¸¦ ¹Þ¾Ò´Ù. ±×°¡ ¼ö°ÇÑ
°ú¸ñµéÀº ±×¸®½º¾î¿Í ·Î¸¶ ½ÅÈ, ¹Ì¼ú»ç¿Í °°Àº ¿À·ÎÁö
Àι®ÁÖÀÇÀûÀÎ °ÍµéÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Åë»óÀûÀÎ ÇлýȰµ¿¿¡
Âü°¡Çß°í °áÅõ¸¦ ¹ú¿´À¸¸ç ¼ú¿¡ ÃëÇØ ¼Ò¶õÀ» ÀÏÀ¸ÄÑ
°¨¹æ¿¡¼ ÇϷ縦 º¸³½ Àûµµ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ±×ÀÇ »ý¾Ö¸¦ ÅëÆ²¾î ´Ü
ÇѹøÀÇ °¨±ÝÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¼úÁý¸ðÀÓÀ» ÁÖ°üÇß°í
Á÷Á¢ÇൿÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀÌ Æ÷ÇÔµÈ ½ÃÀΠŬ·´¿¡ ÃâÀÔÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù.
½Ç·Î ¹Ýµ¿ÀûÀÎ ´ëÇй®È°¡ º» »ýȰÀÇ ÁÖ·ù¸¦ ÀÌ·ç°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.
±¹¹ÎÀÇȸ(ÇÁ¶ûũǪ¸£Æ®)¸¦ °ÅºÎÇß´ø ÇлýµéÀÌ °Ë°ÅµÇ°í ±×
°¡¿îµ¥ ÀϺδ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Àü»ý¾Ö µ¿¾È Ãß¹æ´çÇØ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. 1³â
ÈÄ Ä«¸¦Àº ¹ý·ü°ú öÇÐÀ» °øºÎÇϱâ À§ÇØ º£¸¦¸°À¸·Î ¶°³µ´Ù.
Ä«¸¦
¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ º£¸¦¸°´ëÇб³¸¦ ÈÛ¾µ°í ÀÖ´ø Çì°ÖöÇаú
¸¸³ª û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¸¦ ÃßÁ¾ÇÏ°Ô µÈ »ç½ÇÀº ¸Å¿ì Áß´ëÇÑ
Àǹ̸¦ °®´Â´Ù. óÀ½¿¡ Ä«¸¦Àº G.W. F. Çì°Ö¿¡
´ëÇØ Àû´ë°¨À» ´À²¼À¸¸ç, ±×¹«·Æ ¸öÁ® ´¯°Ô µÈ ¾ó¸¶°£ÀÇ
ÀÌÀ¯´Â ¾Æ¹öÁö¿¡°Ô ½èµíÀÌ "Çø¿ÀÇØ¿Â °ßÇØ¸¦ ¼þ¹èÇØ¾ß
ÇÏ´Â µ¥¼ ¿À´Â È¥¶õ½º·¯¿ò" ¶§¹®À̾ú´Ù. ±×·¯³ª º£¸¦¸°
Çõ¸í¹®È¿¡¼ Çì°ÖÀÌ Â÷ÁöÇÏ´Â ºñÁßÀº ¾ÐµµÀûÀÎ °ÍÀ̾ú°í
Ä«¸¦Àº »õ·Î¿î ¹®¿¹¡¤Ã¶ÇÐ ¿îµ¿À» Àü°³Çϰí ÀÖ´ø '¹Ú»ç Ŭ·´'¿¡
°¡ÀÔÇß´Ù. Ŭ·´ÀÇ Áß½ÉÀι°Àº ÀþÀº ½ÅÇа»ç ºê·ç³ë
¹Ù¿ì¾î¿´´Âµ¥, º¹À½¼´Â ½ÇÁ¦¿ª»çÀÇ ±â·ÏÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó °¨¼ºÀû
Çʿ信 ±âÀÎÇϴ ȯ»óÀÇ ±â·ÏÀÌ¸ç ¿¹¼ö ¶ÇÇÑ ¿ª»ç»óÀÇ
½ÇÁ¸Àι°ÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó´Â ȹ±âÀûÀÎ °¡¼³À» Àü°³½Ã۰í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.
Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿¹¾ðÀÚ ÀÌ»ç¾ß¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ¹Ù¿ì¾îÀÇ °Á¿¡
µî·ÏÇß´Ù. ºê·ç³ë ¹Ù¿ì¾î´Â »õ·Î¿î »çȸÀû ÆÄ±¹, Áï ¿¹¼öÀÇ
À縲½Ã¿¡ ´ÚÄ¥ ½Ã·Ãº¸´Ù ´õ¿í ¹«½Ã¹«½ÃÇÑ ÆÄ±¹ÀÌ ´Ù°¡¿À°í
ÀÖ´Ù°í ¼³ÆÄÇß´Ù. û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ´Â ±Þ¼Óµµ·Î ¹«½Å·Ð¿¡
°¡±î¿öÁö°í ¾î·ÅDzÀÌ Á¤Ä¡Àû Çൿµéµµ °Å·ÐµÇ±â ½ÃÀÛÇß´Ù.
û³â
Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¿¡ ÀáÀçµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Â Á¤ºÎÀüº¹ ºÐÀ§±â¿¡ °øÆ÷¸¦ ´À³¤
ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ Á¤ºÎ´Â À̵鿡 ´ëÇÑ »öÃâÀÛ¾÷¿¡ Âø¼öÇß°í
1839³â ºê·ç³ë ¹Ù¿ì¾î´Â °»çÁ÷À» ¹ÚÅ»´çÇß´Ù. ÀÌ ½ÃÀý °¡Àå
ÀýÄ£ÇÑ Ä£±¸·Î¼ Åõ¿Á»ýȰÀ» Çϱ⵵ Çß´ø Àú³Î¸®½ºÆ®
¾Æµ¹ÇÁ ·çÅÙº£¸£Å©´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô º¸´Ù ´Éµ¿ÀûÀÎ
»çȸÂü¿©¸¦ ±ÇÀ¯Çß´Ù. ±× »çÀÌ ±×ÀÇ ¿¬±¸´Â ÁöüµÇ°í ÀÖ¾ú°í,
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Ä£±¸µéÀÇ ÀçÃË¿¡ ¸øÀÌ°Ü ¿¹³ª´ëÇб³¿¡
¹Ú»ç³í¹®À» Á¦ÃâÇß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ³í¹®Àº Çй®ÀûÀÎ ¸é¿¡¼
º°·Î ¿ì¼öÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´ø °ÍÀ¸·Î ¾Ë·ÁÁ³À¸³ª 1841³â 4¿ù
¹Ú»çÇÐÀ§¸¦ ÃëµæÇÏ´Â µ¥ ¼º°øÇß´Ù. ³í¹®Àº Çì°ÖÁÖÀÇÀÚÀÇ
°üÁ¡¿¡¼ µ¥¸ðÅ©¸®Å佺¿Í
¿¡ÇÇÄí·Î½ºÀÚ¿¬Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ
Â÷ÀÌÁ¡À» ºÐ¼®ÇÑ °ÍÀ̾úÁö¸¸, ºÐ¸íÇÑ °ÍÀº
ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺ÀûÀÎ µµÀüÀÇ ¼Ò¸®¸¦ ³»°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù´Â Á¡ÀÌ´Ù.
"öÇÐÀº
ºñ¹ÐÀ» Áö´ÏÁö ¾Ê´Â´Ù. ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺ÀÇ
'Áø½Ç·Î ³ª´Â ¸ðµç ½ÅµéÀ» ½È¾îÇÑ´Ù'´Â °í¹éÀº ¹Ù·Î öÇÐ
ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ °í¹éÀÌ¸ç ¸ðµç ½Åµé¿¡ ´ëÇ×Çϴ öÇÐÀÇ ½ÅÁ¶ÀÌ´Ù¡¦¡¦
ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺´Â öÇÐÀÇ ÃàÀÏÇ¥¿¡ ÀÖ¾î¼ °¡Àå °í±ÍÇÑ
¼ºÀÚÀÌÀÚ ¼ø±³ÀÚÀÌ´Ù."
1841³â
Ãâ°£µÈ ·çÆ®ºñÈ÷ Æ÷À̾î¹ÙÈåÀÇ
¡´±×¸®½ºµµ±³ÀÇ º»Áú Das Wesen des Christentums¡µÀº
¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¿¡ Ä¿´Ù¶õ ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÌÃÆ´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ »ý°¢Çϱ⿡ Æ÷À̾î¹ÙÈå´Â, ÀÚ¿¬¿¡ ¹ßÀ» ºÙÀ̰í
»ç´Â Çö½Ç Àΰ£À¸·ÎºÎÅÍ Àý´ëÁ¤½ÅÀ» ÃßÃâÇØ³½ Çì°ÖÀÇ
³í¸®Ã¼°è¸¦ ÇØºÎÇÔÀ¸·Î½á ±×ÀÇ °ü³ä·ÐÀû ÀÌ»óÁÖÀǸ¦
È¿°úÀûÀ¸·Î ºñÆÇÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ÀÌÈÄ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀû
³ë·ÂÀº ¸ðµç »ç¹°Àº ¸ð¼øÀûÀÎ ±¹¸éÀÇ Ãæµ¹¿¡ µû¶ó Áö¼ÓÀûÀÎ
º¯È¸¦ °Þ°Ô µÈ´Ù´Â Çì°ÖÀÇ º¯Áõ¹ý°ú ¹°¸®ÀûÀÎ Á¶°ÇµéÀ»
°ü³äÀÇ »óÀ§¿¡ µÎ´Â Æ÷À̾î¹ÙÈåÀÇ À¯¹°·ÐÀ» °áÇÕ½ÃŰ´Â
¹æÇâÀ¸·Î ÀÌ·ç¾îÁö°Ô µÈ´Ù.
1842³â
1¿ù ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Ä븥¿¡¼ â°£µÈ ¡´¶óÀÎ ½Å¹® Rheinische Zeitung¡µÀÇ
±â°í°¡°¡ µÇ¾ú´Ù. Ä븥Àº ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ »ê¾÷ Áß½ÉÁö¿´°í
½Å¹®»ç´Â »óÀΡ¤ÀºÇà°¡¡¤»ê¾÷°¡ µéÀÌ ¸ð¿© ¸¸µç ¹ÎÁÖÀûÀ̰í
ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀûÀÎ ±â°üÀ̾ú´Ù. ÀÌÁîÀ½ ¾ð·ÐÀÇ ÀÚÀ¯¿¡ °üÇÑ
¼Ò³í¹® Çϳª°¡ ¹ßÇ¥µÇ´Âµ¥, ±×¶§±îÁö¸¸ ÇØµµ Àý´ëÀûÀÎ
µµ´ö±âÁذú º¸ÆíÀûÀÎ À±¸®¿øÄ¢À» ´ç¿¬ÇÑ °ÍÀ¸·Î ¹Þ¾ÆµéÀ̰í
ÀÖ´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¾ð·Ð¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ´ç±¹ÀÇ °Ë¿À» ¹ÎÁßÀ»
¿°Å½ÇÏ°í ºñõÇÏ°í ¾ÇÀÇ¿¡ Âù ¼ÓÀε鿡°Ô ½Å°ú °°Àº ±Ç´ÉÀ»
ºÎ¿©ÇÏ´Â Á˾ÇÀ¸·Î ´ÜÁ¤Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù. 1842³â 10¿ù 15ÀÏ Ä«¸¦
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µÀÇ ÁÖÇÊÀÌ µÇ¾ú°í, º£¸¦¸° ºó¹ÎÀÇ
ÁÖÅù®Á¦·ÎºÎÅÍ ³ó¹ÎµéÀÇ »ê¸²¹úä¿Í »õ·Î¿î °ø»êÁÖÀÇ
Çö»ó¿¡ À̸£±â±îÁö °æÁ¦¡¤»çȸ ¹®Á¦¿¡ °üÇÑ ¼ö¾øÀÌ ¸¹Àº
³í¼³À» ÁýÇÊÇØ¾ß¸¸ Çß´Ù. ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ Çì°ÖÀÇ °ü³ä·ÐÀº
ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ Çö½Ç°úÁ¦ÀÇ ÇØ°á¿¡ º°´Ù¸¥ µµ¿òÀÌ µÇÁö ¸øÇß°í,
Ä«¸¦Àº ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ °è±Þ¿¡ Ãæ°ÝÀ» °¡ÇÏ´Â °Í¸¸À¸·Î
»çȸȰµ¿ÀÌ ÃæºÐÈ÷ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù°í ¹Ï´Â Çì°ÖÆÄ µ¿·áµé·ÎºÎÅÍ
¸Ö¾îÁö°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù.
¹ý±Ô¹üÀÇ
ÇÑ°è ³»¿¡¼ Á¡ÁøÀûÀÎ º¯ÇõÀ» ÃßÁøÇÏ´Â ½ÇõÀû
ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀ» °¡±îÀÌÇß´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µÀÇ
¹ßÇàºÎ¼ö¸¦ 3¹è·Î ´Ã¸®°í ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ
ÁÖ¿äÀϰ£Áö·Î ºÎ°¢½ÃŰ´Â µ¥ ¼º°øÇß´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ¼ÖÁ÷Çϰí
ÀÚÀ¯ºÐ¹æÇÑ ³íÁ¶¸¦ ¹®Á¦»ïÀº Á¤ºÎ´ç±¹Àº ½Å¹®À» Á¤°£½ÃÄ×°í,
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´µ¶ÀÏ-ÇÁ¶û½º ¿¬º¸ Deutsch-französische Jahrbücher¡µ¸¦
¹ß°£ÇÏÀÚ´Â ÀÚÀ¯ Çì°ÖÆÄ ¾Æ¸£³îÆ® ·ç°ÔÀÇ Á¦ÀǸ¦ ¹Þ¾ÆµéÀÎ
µÚ ÆÄ¸®·Î ÇâÇß´Ù.
Ä«¸¦
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¾àÈ¥ÇÑ Áö 7³âÀÌ Áö³ 1843³â 6¿ù 4¼¼
¿¬»óÀÎ ¿¹´Ï Æù º£½ºÆ®ÆÈ·»°ú °áÈ¥Çß´Ù. Áö¼º°ú ¸Å·ÂÀ»
°âºñÇÑ ¿¹´Ï´Â ¶Ù¾î³ ±ºÀΰú ÇàÁ¤°üµéÀ» ¹èÃâÇØ³½
¸í¹®°¡ÀÇ µþ·Î¼ ±×³àÀÇ À̺¹ÇüÁ¦´Â Èʳ¯ ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ
³»¹«Àå°ü¿¡ ¿À¸£°Ô µÈ´Ù. »ý
½Ã¸ùÀÇ
ÃßÁ¾ÀÚ¿´´ø ¿¹´ÏÀÇ ¾Æ¹öÁö´Â Ä«¸¦À» ÁÁ¾ÆÇÏ¿© °¡Á·µéÀÇ
¹Ý´ë¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í °áÈ¥À» ¼º»ç½ÃÄ×À¸³ª,
Á¤ÀÛ Ä«¸¦ÀÇ ¾Æ¹öÁö ÇÏÀθ®È÷´Â ±×³à°¡ ¾Ç·É¿¡ »ç·ÎÀâÈù
¾ÆµéÀÇ Á¦¹°ÀÌ µÇÁö³ª ¾ÊÀ»±î °ÆÁ¤½º·¯¿öÇß´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡
ÆÄ¸®·Î ÀÌÁÖÇÑ °ÍÀº °áÈ¥ ÈÄ 4³âÀÌ µÇ´ø
ÇØ¿´´Ù. ´ç½ÃÀÇ ÆÄ¸®´Â »çȸÁÖÀÇ ¼¼·Â°ú º¸´Ù ±ÞÁøÀûÀÎ
°ø»êÁÖÀÇ Çõ¸í¿îµ¿ÀÌ ²ÉÀ» ÇÇ¿ì°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. Çõ¸í°¡°¡ µÈ
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÇÁ¶û½º¡¤µ¶ÀÏ ³ëµ¿ÀÚµéÀÇ °ø»êÁÖÀÇ Á¶Á÷µé°ú
½ÇÁ¦ÀûÀÎ °ü·ÃÀ» ¸Î±â ½ÃÀÛÇß´Ù. ±×µéÀÇ »ç»óÀº ³Ê¹«³ªµµ
Á¶ÀâÇÏ°í ¹«ÁöÇÑ °ÍÀ̾úÁö¸¸ ±×µéÀÇ ÀμºÀº ±×¸¦
°¨µ¿½ÃŰ±â¿¡ ÃæºÐÇß´Ù. ¡´ 1844³âÀÇ °æÁ¦ÇÐ-öÇÐ Ãʰí Ökonomisch-philosophische
Manuskripte aus dem Jahre 1844¡µ¿¡¼ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â "ÇüÁ¦¾Ö´Â
±×µé¿¡°Ô ÀÖ¾î¼ ´Ü¼øÇÑ ±¸È£¸¸ÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï°í »îÀÇ Áø½ÇÀÌ´Ù.
³ëµ¿À¸·Î ´Ü·ÃµÈ ±×µéÀÇ À°Ã¼´Â ¿ì¸®¿¡°Ô Àΰ£ÀÇ °í±ÍÇÔÀ»
Àϱú¿öÁØ´Ù"¶ó°í ¾²°í ÀÖ´Ù. ¡´1844³âÀÇ °æÁ¦ÇÐ-öÇÐ
ÃÊ°í¡µ´Â ÀÌÈÄ 100³â µ¿¾È ºûÀ» ¹ßÇÏÁö ¸øÇßÁö¸¸ ¸¶¸£Å©½º
¿ª»ç¡¤°æÁ¦ ÀÌ·ÐÀÇ ¹ÙÅÁÀ» ÀÌ·ç´Â ÈÞ¸Ó´ÏÁòÀÌ ¼³¸íµÇ°í ÀÖ´Â
Á¡¿¡¼ °¡Ä¡¸¦ ÀÒÁö ¾Ê°í ÀÖ´Ù.
´Ü¸íÀ¸·Î
³¡³ ¡´µ¶ÀÏ-ÇÁ¶û½º ¿¬º¸¡µ°¡ ÇØ¸¶´Ù ÃâÆÇÀ»
°ÅµìÇÏ´Â »çÀÌ¿¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ±â°í°¡¿´´ø ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½º¿ÍÀÇ
°ü°è´Â ±Þ¼Óµµ·Î ¹ßÀüµÇ¾ú´Ù. ¡´µ¶ÀÏ-ÇÁ¶û½º¿¬º¸¡µ¿¡
½Ç¸° ¡´¿ìÀÍ Çì°ÖÆÄ öÇÐ ºñÆÇ¡µ¿¡´Â "Á¾±³´Â ¹ÎÁßÀÇ
¾ÆÆí"À̶ó´Â À¯¸íÇÑ ¹®±¸¿Í ÇÔ²² öÇÐÀÇ ½ÇÇöÀ» À§ÇÑ 'ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ
ºÀ±â'°¡ Á¦Ã¢µÇ°í ÀÖ´Ù. ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ Á¤ºÎ´Â ´Ù½Ã Çѹø Ä«¸¦
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Á¦Àç¿¡ ³ª¼¹°í 1845³â 2¿ù Ä«¸¦Àº ÆÄ¸®¸¦ ¶°³ª
ºê·ò¼¿·Î ÇâÇß´Ù. Ä«¸¦Àº º§±â¿¡¿¡¼ ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í ȸµ¿ÇÑ µÚ
ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ±¹ÀûÀ» Æ÷±âÇß´Ù.
ºê·ò¼¿
½Ã´ë
ºê·ò¼¿¿¡¼ÀÇ
´ÙÀ½ 2³â°£Àº ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ
°øµ¿ÀÛ¾÷ÀÌ ½ÉȵǴø ½Ã±â¿´´Ù. ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ¾Æ¹öÁöÀÇ
Á÷¹°°øÀåÀÌ À§Ä¡ÇØ ÀÖ´ø ¸Çü½ºÅÍ¿¡¼ »ê¾÷Çõ¸íÀÇ ¾Ï¿ïÇÑ
Çö½ÇµéÀ» óÀ½ Á¢Çß´Ù. û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¿¡ ¼ÓÇß´ø ±×´Â
°ø»êÁÖÀÇ ¶øºñ¶ó ºÒ·È´ø ¸ðÁ¦½º Ç콺ÀÇ
¿µÇâÀ» ¹Þ¾Æ °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ°¡ µÇ¾úÀ¸¸ç ¿µ±¹¿¡¼´Â ·Î¹öÆ® ¿À¾ðÀÇ
ÃßÁ¾ÀÚµé°ú ±³·ùÇß´Ù. ÀÌÁ¦ ±×µé »çÀÌÀÇ
°øÅëµÈ °ßÇØ¸¦ È®ÀÎÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º´Â µÎ »ç¶÷ÀÇ ÁöÀû
ÀÚ¿øÀ» °áÇÕ½ÃÄÑ ½ÅÇÐÀÚ ºê·ç³ë ¹Ù¿ì¾îÀÇ Çì°ÖÁÖÀÇÀû
°ü³ä·Ð¿¡ ´ëÇÑ Àå¹®ÀÇ ºñÆò ¡´½Å¼º°¡Á· Die heilige Familie¡µ(1845)À»
Æì³Â´Ù. ±×µéÀÇ ´ÙÀ½ Àú¼ ¡´µ¶ÀÏ
À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â Die deutsche Ideologie¡µ´Â ¿ª»çÀÇ °¢ ´Ü°è¿¡¼ Áö¹è°è±ÞÀÌ
ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ °æÁ¦Àû ÀÌÀÍÀ» µµ¸ðÇϱâ À§ÇØ »çȸ°øµ¿Ã¼¸¦
±¸Á¶ÈÇÑ ¹æ½ÄµéÀ» ±Ô¸íÇÔÀ¸·Î½á ¿ª»çÀû À¯¹°·ÐÀ» óÀ½À¸·Î
¿ÏÀüÇÏ°Ô Á¦½ÃÇϰí ÀÖÁö¸¸, ¾î¶² ÃâÆÇ¾÷ÀÚµµ
¼±¶æ ³ª¼Áö ¾Ê¾Æ µÎ »ç¶÷ÀÇ ÀÏ»ý ³»³» ºûÀ» º¸Áö ¸øÇß´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÁÖ¿ä ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿ÁöµµÀÚµé°úÀÇ ´ë°áÀ» ÅëÇØ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ
°ø»êÁÖÀÇ »ç»óÀ» È®¸³½ÃÄѳª°¬´Ù. 1846³â ±×´Â ºôÇ︧
¹ÙÀÌÆ²¸µÀÇ µµ´öÁÖÀÇÀû ŵµ¸¦ ȤÆòÇϸé¼
ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸ¸¦ ¶Ù¾î³Ñ¾î °ø»êÁÖÀÇ
´Ü°è·Î °ðÀå ºñ¾àÇÒ ¼ö ¾øÀ¸¸ç, ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿Àº À±¸®Àû ±¸È£°¡
¾Æ´Ï¶ó °úÇÐÀûÀÎ ±Ù°Å¸¦ ÇÊ¿ä·Î ÇÑ´Ù°í ¿ª¼³Çß´Ù.
¡´Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ
ºó°ï Das Elend der Philosophie¡µ(1847)Àº ÇÇ¿¡¸£
Á¶Á¦ÇÁ ÇÁ·çµ¿ÀÇ ¡´ºó°ïÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ
Philosophie de la misère¡µ(1846)À» ³í¹ÚÇÑ °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ÇÁ·çµ¿ÀÌ
°æÁ¦Ã¼Á¦ÀÇ ´ë¸³°³³äµé·ÎºÎÅÍ ´ÜÁ¡À» Áö¾çÇϰí ÀåÁ¡À»
µÇ»ì¸®·Á ³ë·ÂÇß´ø ¹Ý¸é, ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â °è±ÞÅõÀï¿¡ »óÈ£
ÃæÁ·Àû Ÿ°áÁ¡Àº ÀÖÀ» ¼ö ¾øÀ¸¸ç »çȸ°øµ¿Ã¼ÀÇ ±¸Á¶´Â
»ý»ê·Â°ú »ý»ê°ü°è¿¡ ÀÇÇØ °áÁ¤µÇ´Â ¿ª»çÀÇ ÀϽÃÀûÀÎ
Çö»óÀÏ »ÓÀ̶ó°í ¹Ý¹ÚÇß´Ù. ¸Ëµ¹Àº ºÀ°Ç¿µÁÖÀÇ Áö¹è¸¦,
Áõ±â±â°üÀº »ê¾÷ÀÚº»°¡ÀÇ Áö¹è¸¦ À̲ø¾î³Â´Ù´Â ¼³¸íÀ̾ú´Ù.
ÇÁ·çµ¿ÀÇ Ã߷оç½ÄÀº ¿ª»çÀÇ ±âº»¹ýÄ¢À» ÆÄ¾ÇÇÏ´Â µ¥
½ÇÆÐÇÑ ¼ÒºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾ÆÀû »çȸÀνÄÀ¸·Î ¿©°ÜÁ³´Ù.
»ç°ÇµéÀÇ
±âÀÌÇÑ ÀüÈİü°è°¡ ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀ»
ź»ý½ÃÄ×´Ù. 1847³â 6¿ù µ¶Àϰè À̹Î
¼ö°ø¾÷ÀÚµé·Î ±¸¼ºµÈ 'ÀÇÀε¿¸Í'(ëùìÑÔÒØï)ÀÌ ·±´ø¿¡¼
ȸÇÕÀ» °®°í Á¤Ä¡Àû °·É äÅÃÀ» °áÀÇÇß´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
À̵é·ÎºÎÅÍ Âü¿©ÀÇ ¿äûÀ» ¹Þ¾Ò°í ¼÷°í ³¡¿¡ µ¿·á ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í
µ¿¸Í¿¡ °¡ÀÔÇß´Ù. ÀÇÀε¿¸ÍÀº '°ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ µ¿¸Í'À¸·Î ¸íĪÀ»
º¯°æÇÑ µÚ ¹ÎÁÖÀû ÇåÀåÀ» Á¦Á¤Çß´Ù. Á¤° ÀÛ¼ºÀ» À§ÀÓ¹ÞÀº
¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º´Â 1847³â 12¿ù Áß¼øºÎÅÍ 1848³â 1¿ù±îÁö
Á¤°ÀÇ ÃʾÈÀÛ¾÷¿¡ ¸ôµÎÇß´Ù. ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀº "Áö±Ý±îÁöÀÇ
¸ðµç ¿ª»ç´Â °è±ÞÅõÀïÀÇ ¿ª»çÀÌ´Ù"¶ó´Â ¸íÁ¦¸¦ ÅëÇØ
¡´µ¶ÀÏ À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â¡µ¿¡¼ Á¤¸³µÈ À¯¹°»ç°üÀ» ¿ä¾àÇϰí
°è±Þ»çȸ´Â ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ½Â¸®¿¡ µû¶ó ¿ª»ç¿¡¼ ÀÚÃ븦
°¨Ãß°Ô µÉ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¼±¾ðÀº '¼Ò¿Ü'·ùÀÇ ¹Ú¾àÇÑ
Ã߷п¡ ±Ù°ÅÇÑ ¸ðµç »çȸÁÖÀÇ ÇüŸ¦ ºñÆÇÇϰí À¯ÅäÇǾÆ
»çȸ¸¦ ÁöÇâÇÑ °øµ¿Ã¼Àû ½ÇÇèµéÀ» °è±ÞÅõÀïÀ» ¹«¸¶½ÃŰ´Â '¹Ýµ¿Àû
ºÐÆÄ'·Î °£ÁÖÇØ ´ÜÈ£È÷ °ÅºÎÇßÀ¸¸ç ´©Áø°ú¼¼, »ó¼ÓÀÇ
ÆóÁö·ÎºÎÅÍ ¾Æµ¿ÀÇ ¹«»ó±³À°¿¡ À̸£±â±îÁö °ø»êÁÖÀÇ »çȸ·Î
³ª¾Æ°¡´Â ù ´Ü°è·Î¼ 10°³ÀÇ Áï°¢ÀûÀÎ Á¶Ä¡¸¦ Á¦½ÃÇß´Ù.
¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀº "ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ°¡ ÀÒÀ» °ÍÀº ¼Ó¹ÚÀÇ
»ç½½¹Û¿¡´Â ¾ø´Ù. ±×µéÀº ¼¼°è¸¦ ¾òÀ» °ÍÀÌ´Ù. ¸¸±¹ÀÇ
³ëµ¿ÀÚ¿© ´Ü°áÇ϶ó"´Â ¸»·Î ³¡À» ¸Î´Â´Ù.
1848³âÃÊÀÇ
¸î °³¿ù µ¿¾È ÇÁ¶û½º¡¤ÀÌÅ»¸®¾Æ¡¤¿À½ºÆ®¸®¾Æ¿¡¼ µ¹¿¬È÷
Çõ¸íÀÌ Ã˹ߵǾú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÓ½ÃÁ¤ºÎÀÇ ÃÊûÀ» ¹Þ¾Æ
ÆÄ¸®·Î ¶°³µ´Âµ¥ º§±â¿¡ ´ç±¹À¸·ÎºÎÅÍ Ãß¹æ·ÉÀÌ ³»·ÁÁö±â
ÀüÀÇ ½Ã±âÀûÀýÇÑ °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ±×·¯³ª µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ¸Á¸íÀÚµéÀº
¹«·ÂÀ¸·Î Á¶±¹À» ÇØ¹æ½ÃŰÀÚ´Â °Ô¿À¸£Å© Ç츣º£Å©ÀÇ ¼±µ¿¿¡
¹Ý´ëÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º·ÎºÎÅÍ ¸Ö¾îÁ®°¬´Ù. ¿À½ºÆ®¸®¾Æ¿Í µ¶ÀÏ¿¡¼
Çõ¸íÀÌ °¡¿µÇ°í ÀÖÀ» ¶§ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¶óÀζõÆ®·Î
µÇµ¹¾Æ¿Ô´Ù. Ä븥¿¡¼ ±×´Â ³ëµ¿ÀÚ°è±ÞÀÌ ¹ÎÁÖÀû
ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾ÆÁö¿Í ¿¬ÇÕÀ» ÀÌ·ç¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ±×´Â
³ëµ¿ÀÚµ¿¸Í ÁöµµÀÚµéÀÇ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ Çõ¸í³ë¼±¿¡ Á¦µ¿À»
°¡ÇÏ°í ³ëµ¿ÀÚ°è±ÞÀº ÇÁ¶ûũǪ¸£Æ® ÀÇȸ¿¡ ´ëÇ¥¸¦ ÆÄ°ßÇÏÁö
¸»¾Æ¾ß ÇÒ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ¿ª¼³Çß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °ßÇØ´Â
¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀÌ À¯º¸µÇ¾î¾ß ÇÏ¸ç °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ µ¿¸ÍÀº
ÇØÃ¼µÇ¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ °ßÇØ¿Í ÀÏÄ¡Çß´Ù.
1849³â 6¿ù Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â »õ·ÎÀÌ Ã¢°£µÈ ¡´½Å(ãæ)¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®
Neue Rheinische Zeitung¡µÀ» ÅëÇØ ÀÔÇåÀû ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀÇ¿Í ·¯½Ã¾Æ¿ÍÀÇ
°³ÀüÀ» Ã˱¸Çß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ³ëµ¿ÀÚµ¿¸ÍÀÇ ±ÞÁøÆÄ ÁöµµÀÚ
¾Èµå·¹¾Æ½º °íÆ®¼£Å©°¡ üÆ÷µÇ¾úÀ» ¶§ ±×¸¦ ´ë½ÅÇØ
¶óÀζõÆ® ¹ÎÁÖÀÇȸ¸¦ â¼³ÇßÀ¸¸ç(1848. 8), ±¹¿ÕÀÌ º£¸¦¸°ÀÇ
ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ÀÇȸ¸¦ ÇØ»ê½ÃŰÀÚ ÁöÇÏÀúÇ׿À» µ½±â À§ÇØ
¹«±â¿Í º´·ÂÀ» ²ø¾î¸ð¾Ò´Ù.
ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀû
ºÎ¸£Á־ƵéÀº ¡´½Å¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÈÄ¿øÀ» Áß´ÜÇß°í
Ä«¸¦ ÀÚ½ÅÀº ³³¼¼°ÅºÎÀÇ Á¶ÀåÀ» ºñ·ÔÇÑ ¿©·¯ ÇøÀǸ¦ ¹Þ¾Æ
±â¼ÒµÇ¾ú´Ù. ¹ýÁ¤¿¡¼ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾
¿ÕÀÌ ºÒ¹ýÀûÀÎ ¹ÝÇõ¸í¿îµ¿¿¡ °ü¿©Çß´Ù´Â ¿äÁö·Î ÀÚ½ÅÀ»
º¯È£ÇßÀ¸¸ç ¹è½É¿ø´ÜÀº È£ÀǸ¦ °¡Áö°í ¸¸ÀåÀÏÄ¡·Î ±×¸¦
¹æ¸é½ÃÄ×´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ÃÖÈÄÀÇ Èñ¸Á ¾ø´Â ½Î¿òÀÌ ¹Ùµ§°ú
µå·¹½ºµ§¿¡¼ Ÿ¿Ã¶ú°í, 1849³â 5¿ù 16ÀÏ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô
Ãß¹æ·ÉÀÌ ³»·ÁÁ³´Ù. ºÓ°Ô ÀμâµÈ ¡´½Å¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µÀÇ
Æó°£È£´Â ¼¾¼¼À̼ÇÀ» ºÒ·¯ÀÏÀ¸Ä×´Ù.
Ãʱâ
·±´ø ½Ã´ë
ÆÄ¸®·ÎºÎÅÍ
´Ù½Ã Çѹø Ãß¹æµÈ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â 1847³â 8¿ù
·±´øÀ¸·Î ÇâÇß°í ·±´øÀº ±×ÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· Á¤ÂøÁö°¡ µÇ¾ú´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀû ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ¿Í Á¦ÈÞÇÏ·Á´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ
°èȹÀÌ ¹«À§·Î µ¹¾Æ°£ °ÍÀ» ¸ø³» ¾Æ½¬¿öÇÏ¸é¼ ÀçÂ÷ ·±´øÀÇ
°ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ µ¿¸Í¿¡ ÇÕ·ùÇß°í, ¾à 1³â µ¿¾È º¸´Ù ´ë´ãÇÑ
Çõ¸íÁ¤Ã¥À» ÃßÁøÇÏ°Ô µÈ´Ù. ±×´Â °æÁ¦ÀûÀÎ À§±â°¡ °ð
Çõ¸í¿îµ¿À» ¼Ò»ý½Ã۸®¶ó°í ±â´ëÇßÀ¸³ª ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ±â´ë°¡
½Ãµé¾îÁöÀÚ ½º½º·Î 'Çõ¸íÀÇ ¿¬±Ý¼ú»ç'¶ó°í ºÒ·¶´ø »ç¶÷µé,
Áï Á÷Á¢ÇൿÀ» ÅëÇØ Çõ¸íÀÇ µµ·¡¸¦ ¾Õ´ç±æ °ÍÀ» ÁÖÀåÇß´ø
¾Æ¿ì±¸½ºÆ® Æù ºô¸®È÷¿Í °°Àº °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚµé°ú ´Ù½Ã Çѹø
´ëÄ¡ÇÏ°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â 1850³â 9¿ù À̵éÀÌ À¯¹°·ÐÀ»
ÀÌ»óÁÖÀÇ·Î ´ëüÇß´Ù°í ºñÆÇÇÏ¸é¼ ´ÙÀ½°ú °°ÀÌ ±â¼úÇß´Ù.
"±×µéÀº
½ÇÁ¦ÀûÀÎ Á¶°ÇµéÀ» µµ¿Ü½ÃÇÑ Ã¤ ¼ø¼öÀÇÁö¸¦ Çõ¸íÀÇ
¿øµ¿·ÂÀ¸·Î °£ÁÖÇÑ´Ù. ¿ì¸®°¡ ³ëµ¿Àڵ鿡°Ô '¿©·¯ºÐµéÀº
´Ü¼øÈ÷ ¿©·¯ºÐµéÀÇ ¿©°ÇÀ» °³¼±½Ã۱â À§Çؼ°¡ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó
½º½º·Î¸¦ º¯È½Ã۰í Á¤Ä¡Àû ±Ç·ÂÀ» ºÐ´ãÇϱâ À§ÇØ ¼ö½Ê ³â
°£ÀÇ ³»¶õ°ú ±¹Á¦ÀüÀïÀ» °Þ¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù'°í ¸»ÇÏ´Â ¹Ý¸é ±×µéÀº
ÀÌ¿Í ´ëÁ¶ÀûÀ¸·Î '¿ì¸®´Â Áï½Ã ±Ç·ÂÀ» ÀïÃëÇØ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù'°í
ºÎÃß±â°í ÀÖ´Ù."
±ÞÁøÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀº
¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ ³ëµ¿ÀÚ ±³À°µ¿¸ÍÀÇ Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐ °»ç°¡ µÇ±â¸¦
ÀÚóÇß´Ù¸ç ±×¸¦ ºñ²¿¾Ò°í, ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ
°ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ ¸ðÀÓ Ãâ¼® Ƚ¼ö´Â Á¡Â÷ ÁÙ¾îµé¾ú´Ù. 1852³â¿¡
Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Ä븥¿¡¼ Á¤ºÎÀüº¹ ÇøÀǷΠüÆ÷µÈ 11¸íÀÇ
°ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀ» º¯È£ÇÏ´Â µ¥ È¥½ÅÀÇ ÈûÀ» ±â¿ï¿´À¸¸ç À̸¦
À§ÇÏ¿© ÆÊÇ÷¿À» ÀÛ¼ºÇÏ ±âµµ Çß´Ù. ¡´·çÀÌ º¸³ªÆÄ¸£Æ®ÀÇ
ºê·ò¸Þ¸£ 18ÀÏ Der Achtzehnte Brumaire des Louis Bonaparte¡µÀÌ ¾º¾îÁø
°Íµµ À̹«·ÆÀε¥ ¿©±â¼ ±×´Â ³ó¹Î°è±ÞÀÇ ÁöÁö¸¦ ¹ÙÅÁÀ¸·Î
°ü·áÁÖÀÇÀû Àý´ë±¹°¡°¡ Çü¼ºµÇ´Â °úÁ¤À» ³¯Ä«·Ó°Ô ºÐ¼®Çϰí
ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌÈÄÀÇ 12³â°£Àº ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ç¥Çö¿¡ µû¸£ÀÚ¸é µÎ
»ç¶÷¿¡°Ô '°í¸³'ÀÇ ½Ã°£ÀÌ µÇ¾ú´Ù. 1850~64³â ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
¹°ÁúÀûÀÎ ±ÃÇ̰ú Á¤½ÅÀûÀÎ °íÅë ¼Ó¿¡¼ »ì¾Ò´Ù. Àç¿øÀº
°í°¥µÇ°í ´Ü ÇѹøÀ» »©°í´Â ¼öÀÔÀÌ ÀÖ´Â Á÷¾÷À» °¡ÁöÁö
¸øÇß´Ù. 1850³â 3¿ù Ä«¸¦°ú ¿¹´Ï, ±×¸®°í 4¸íÀÇ ÀÚ³àµé¿¡°Ô
°Á¦Åð°Å¸í·ÉÀÌ ³»·ÁÁ³°í ÀÚ»êÀº ¾Ð·ùµÇ¾ú´Ù. ÀÚ³àµé Áß
¸î¸îÀº Á×¾ú´Ù. ±×Áß¿¡´Â ±×°¡ 'ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸÀÇ Èñ»ýÀÚ'¶ó°í
À̾߱âÇÑ ¾Æµé ±Íµµ¿Í µþ ÇÁ¶õÄ¡½ºÄ«°¡ Æ÷ÇԵǾî ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.
¿¹´Ï´Â ¾ÆÀ̵éÀÇ °üÀ» »ì µ·À» ¸¶·ÃÇÏ·Á°í °ÅÀÇ ¹ÌÄ£ µíÀÌ
¶Ù¾î´Ù³æ´Ù. 6³âÀ» ´ëºÎºÐ »§°ú °¨ÀÚ·Î ¿¬¸íÇÏ¸ç °¡Á·Àº
¼ÒÈ£ÀÇ ¹æ 2Ä¿¡¼ »îÀ» ²Ù·Á³ª°¬°í, ¾ÆÀ̵éÀº ¸ô·Á¿Â
ä±ÇÀڵ鿡°Ô "¸¶¸£Å©½º ¼±»ý´ÔÀº 2Ãþ¿¡ °è½ÃÁö ¾Ê¾Æ¿ä"¶ó´Â
°ÅÁþ¸»À» ÇØ¾ß¸¸ Çß´Ù. ºúÀïÀ̵éÀ» ÇÇÇØ Ä«¸¦Àº ¸Çü½ºÅÍ·Î
µµ¸ÁÇØ¾ß Çß°í ¾Æ³» ¿¹´Ï´Â ½Å°æ¼è¾à¿¡ ½Ã´Þ·È´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ
¿ª°æÀÇ ½Ã°£À» ÅëÇØ ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÀçÁ¤ÀûÀÎ ÈÄ¿øÀ» ¾Æ³¢Áö
¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. óÀ½¿¡´Â ¸Çü½ºÅÍ ¼ÒÀç ¾î¸Õ¾Øµå¿¨°Ö½º»ç(Þä)ÀÇ
Æò»ç¹«¿ø¿¡ ºÒ°úÇßÀ¸¹Ç·Î µ·ÀÇ ¾×¼ö°¡ ¸¹Áö ¾Ê¾ÒÁö¸¸ 1864³â
±×°¡ µ¿¾÷ÀÚ°¡ µÇ¾úÀ» ¶§´Â Áö¿ø±ÝÀÇ ±Ô¸ðµµ Ä¿Á³´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿¨°Ö½º¿ÍÀÇ ¿ìÁ¤À» ÀÚ¶ûÀ¸·Î ¿©°å°í ±×¿¡ ´ëÇÑ
¾î¶°ÇÑ ºñÆÇµµ ¿ë³³ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. ¾Æ³»ÀÇ Ä£Áöµé°ú Ä£±¸
ºôÇ︧ º¼ÇÁÀÇ À¯»êÀ¸·Î ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °æÁ¦Àû °íÅëÀº Å©°Ô
°æ°¨µÇ¾ú´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
¹Ì±¹¿¡ ºñ±³Àû Áö¼ÓÀûÀÎ ¼öÀÔ¿øÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ¾ú´Âµ¥,
Ǫ¸®¿¡ÁÖÀÇ¿¡ °ø°¨Çϰí ÀÖ´ø ¡´´º¿å Æ®¸®ºå The New York Tribune¡µÀÇ
À¯·´ Åë½Å¿øÀÌ µÈ °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. 1851~62³â Ä«¸¦Àº 500Æí¿¡ °¡±î¿î
±â»ç¿Í ³í¼³µéÀ» ±â°íÇϸé¼(±×Áß 1/4Àº ¿¨°Ö½º Á¦°ø) Àεµ¿Í
Áß±¹, ¿µ±¹°ú ½ºÆäÀÎÀÇ »çȸ¿îµ¿°ú ¼Ò¿äµéÀ» ºÐ¼®¡¤°ËÅäÇß´Ù.
1859³â ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â °æÁ¦À̷п¡ °üÇÑ ÃÖÃÊÀÇ Àú¼úÀÎ ¡´Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐ ºñÆÇ
Zur Kritik der politischen Okonomie¡µÀ» ¿Ï¼ºÇß´Ù. ¡´Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐ
ºñÆÇ¡µÀÇ ¼¹®¿¡´Â À¯¹°»ç°ü¿¡ µµ´ÞÇÏ°Ô µÈ ³í¸®°úÁ¤ÀÌ
»ó¼¼ÇÏ°Ô ¼³¸íµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù. "¹°ÁúÀûÀÎ »ý»ê¾ç½ÄÀº »îÀÇ
»çȸÀû¡¤Á¤Ä¡Àû¡¤Á¤½ÅÀû Â÷¿øµéÀ» °áÁ¤ÇÑ´Ù. Àΰ£ÀÇ ÀǽÄÀÌ
±×µéÀÇ Á¸À縦 ±ÔÁ¤Áþ´Â °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ¹Ý´ë·Î ±×µéÀÇ »çȸÀû
»ýȰÀÌ ÀǽÄÀ» Á¿ìÇÑ´Ù."
Ä«¸¦Àº
´ë¿µ¹Ú¹°°ü¿¡¼ °æÁ¦¡¤»çȸ»ç ¿¬±¸¿¡
¸ôµÎÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ» ÁÖ¿äÀϰú·Î »ï¾ÒÀ¸¸ç µ¶ÀÏÀÇ »õ·Î¿î
³ëµ¿¿îµ¿¿¡ µ¿ÂüÇØ´Þ¶ó´Â Æä¸£µð³Æ® ¶ó»ìÀÇ
±ÇÀ¯¸¦ °ÅºÎÇß´Ù. ¶ó»ìÀº È¥ÀÚ¼ 'Àü(îï)µ¶ÀÏ
³ëµ¿ÀÚµ¿¸Í'ÀÇ °á¼º¿¡ Âø¼öÇß´Ù.
Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î
1864³â
Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î(±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸ)ÀÇ Ã¢¼³°ú ´õºÒ¾î
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Á¤Ä¡Àû °í¸³µµ ³¡ÀÌ ³µ´Ù. ±×´Â ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ
â¼³ÀÚµµ ȸÀåµµ ¾Æ´Ï¾úÁö¸¸ °ð ÇùȸÀÇ Á¤½ÅÀûÀÎ ÁöÁÖ°¡
µÇ¾ú´Ù. ÃÖÃÊÀÇ °ø½ÄȸÀÇ´Â 1864³â 9¿ù 28ÀÏ ·±´øÀÇ ¼¼ÀÎÆ®
¸¶Æ¾ Ȧ¿¡¼ ¿µ±¹ ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕÀÇ ÁöµµÀÚµé°ú ÇÁ¶û½º ³ëµ¿ÀÚ
´ëÇ¥µé¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ¼ÒÁýµÇ¾ú´Ù. ÇÁ¶û½ºÀÇ Áß°³ÀÎÀ» ÅëÇØ µ¶ÀÏ
´ëÇ¥ ÀÚ°ÝÀ¸·Î ÃÊûµÇ¾ú´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ħ¹¬À» Áö۸ç
¿¬´Ü¿¡ ÀÚ¸®Çϰí ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. °·É°ú ÇåÀåÀ» äÅÃÇϱâ À§ÇÑ
À§¿øÈ¸°¡ ¼³Ä¡µÇ°í ¸¸Á·½º·´Áö ¸øÇÑ ¸¹Àº ÃʾȵéÀÌ Á¦ÃâµÈ
ÈÄ ºÐ°úÀ§¿øÈ¸¿¡ ¸ö´ã°í ÀÖ´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â dzºÎÇÑ ¾ð·Ð°èÀÇ
°æÇèÀ» ¹ÙÅÁÀ¸·Î °·É°ú ÇåÀåÀ» ±âÃÊÇß´Ù.
±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸÀÇ ÀӽñÔÄ¢Àº ±×ÀÇ ´Ù¸¥ Àú¼úµé°ú´Â ´Þ¸®
°è±Þ°£ÀÇ Á¦ÈÞÁ¤Ã¥°ú ÀÇȸÀÔ¹ýÀÇ ±àÁ¤ÀûÀÎ Ãø¸éÀ» °Á¶Çß´Ù.
¿µ±¹ÀÇ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â Á¡ÁøÀûÀÎ ³ë·ÂÀ» ÅëÇØ ±¹°¡Àû
Â÷¿øÀÇ Á¤Ä¡±Ç·ÂÀ» ȹµæÇÏ°Ô µÉ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ³»´Ùº¸¾Ò´Ù.
ÇùȸÀÇ È°µ¿Àº 1ÁÖÀÏ¿¡µµ ¸î ¹ø¾¿ ȸÇÕÀÌ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁö´Â µî
Å©°Ô Ȱ¼ºÈµÇ¾ú°í, ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÃÑȸÀÇ È¸¿øÀÌÀÚ µ¶ÀÏ
Áö¿ªÀÇ Åë½Å°£»ç·Î¼ ´Ù¾çÇÑ ÆÄ¹ú°ú °æÇâµéÀÇ ÈÇÕÀ»
ÀÌ·ç¾î³»´Â º¸±â µå¹® ÀÚÁúÀ» ¹ßÈÖÇß´Ù. ³¯·Î ³ô¾ÆÁ®°¡´Â
¸í¼º°ú ÇÔ²² 1869³â Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ ±Ô¸ð´Â ¾à 80¸¸ ȸ¿øÀ¸·Î
È®ÀåµÇ¾ú°í °¢ Áö¿ª ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕÀ» À§ÇÑ ºÐ±ÔÁ¶Á¤¿¡
°ü¿©ÇÔÀ¸·Î½á »ó´çÇÑ ¼º°øÀ» °ÅµÎ±âµµ Çß´Ù.
ÆÄ¸®
ÄÚ¹ÀÀº
Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¸¦ ±¹Á¦ÀûÀÎ Àι°·Î ¸¸µç »ç°ÇÀ̾ú´Ù.
1870³â ÇÁ¶û½º-ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ÀüÀïÀÌ ¹ß¹ßÇÏÀÚ µ¶ÀÏ ÀÇȸÀÇ
»çȸÁÖÀÇ ¼¼·ÂÀº ÀüÀï°øÃ¤¾È ÅõÇ¥¸¦ °ÅºÎÇß´Ù. óÀ½¿¡ Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î
°øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ´Â ÇÁ¶û½º-ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ÀüÀïÀ» µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ¹æ¾îÀüÀïÀ¸·Î
±ÔÁ¤ÇßÀ¸³ª ÆÄ¸®°¡ ÇÔ¶ôµÈ ÈÄ µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ¹è»ó¿ä±¸°¡ Áö³ªÄ£
¼öÁØ¿¡ À̸£ÀÚ ºÐÀ§±â´Â ¹ÝÀüµÇ¾ú´Ù. ÆÄ¸®¿¡¼ Æøµ¿ÀÌ
ÀϾ°í ÄÚ¹ÀÀÌ ¼±Æ÷µÇ¾úÀ» ¶§ ÀüÆøÀûÀÎ ÁöÁö¸¦ Ç¥¸íÇß´ø
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â À̵ëÇØ 5¿ù 30ÀÏ ÄÚ¹ÀÀÌ ºÐ¼âµÇÀÚ 'ÇÁ¶û½º ³»Àü'À̶ó´Â
Á¦¸íÀ¸·Î ¼º¸í¼¸¦ ¹ßÇ¥ÇÑ´Ù.
"¿ª»ç´Â
ÀÌÅä·Ï À§´ëÇÑ °Í¿¡ ÇÊÀûÇÒ ¸¸ÇÑ »ç·Ê¸¦ °¡Áö°í ÀÖÁö ¾Ê´Ù¡¦¡¦
ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀÇ ¼ø±³ÀÚµéÀº ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÀÇ °¡½¿ ¼Ó¿¡ ¿µ¿øÈ÷
»ì¾Æ ÀÖÀ» °ÍÀÌ´Ù."
¿¨°Ö½º´Â
ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀ» Àηù ÃÖÃÊÀÇ 'ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ µ¶Àç'·Î
Æò°¡ÇßÀ¸¸ç ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ À̸§Àº ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀÇ Çõ¸íÁ¤½Å°ú
µ¿ÀǾ µÇ¾ú´Ù.
ÆÄ¸®
ÄÚ¹ÀÀº ±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸÀÇ ³»ºÎ°¥µîÀ» ÁõÆø½ÃÄÑ °á±¹ ºØ±«¸¦
ÃÊ·¡ÇÏ´Â °è±â·Î ÀÛ¿ëÇß´Ù. °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ
ÀÇÀåÀ» Áö³Â´ø ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕÁÖÀÇÀÚ Á¶Áö ¿ÀÀú´Â ÄÚ¹À¿¡ °¥Ã¤¸¦
º¸³½ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã³½ÅÀ» ºÒ¸¸½º·¯¿öÇß°í 1867³âÀÇ ¼±°Å¹ý
°³Á¤¾ÈÀ¸·Î Á¤Ä¡Âü¿©ÀÇ ÆøÀÌ ³Ð¾îÁø ¿µ±¹ÀÇ ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕµéÀº
ÀÚÀ¯´ç°úÀÇ Çù·ÂÀ» ÅëÇØ ½ÇÁúÀûÀÎ ¼º°ú¸¦ ¾ò¾î³»±â¸¦
Èñ¸ÁÇß´Ù. ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕ ÁöµµÀÚµéÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ´Éº¯À»
°ÅÃßÀ彺·¯¿î °É¸²µ¹·Î »ý°¢Çß°í ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀڵ鿡°Ô
¸Å¼öµÇ¾ú´Ù´Â ±×ÀÇ ºñ³¿¡ ´ëÇØ ºÐ°³Çß´Ù.
Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î
³» ÁÂÆÄÀÇ µµÀüÀº ·¯½Ã¾ÆÀÇ ¹«Á¤ºÎÁÖÀÇÀÚ ¹ÌÇÏÀÏ
¾Ë·º»êµå·ÎºñÄ¡ ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀÇ ÁÖµµÇÏ¿¡ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù (¡æ »öÀÎ : ¹ÙÄí´Ñ).
½Ãº£¸®¾Æ À¯Çü°ú ½¢ÇÑ °¨¿Á»ýȰÀ» °æÇèÇÑ Çõ¸í°¡·Î¼ '³ëÈ£ÇÏ´Â
ÆøÇ³¿ì¿Í »çÀÚÀÇ Æ÷È¿'·Î ºñÀ¯µÇ´Â ¿õº¯ÀÇ ´ë°¡À̱⵵ Çß´ø
¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº ¹µ»ç¶÷µéÀ» »ç·ÎÀâÀ» ¸¸ÇÑ ¸Å·ÂÀ» °¡Áø
Àι°À̾ú´Ù. ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Áö¼º¿¡ Âù»ç¸¦ º¸³»±â´Â
ÇßÀ¸³ª ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ ÀÚ½ÅÀ» ·¯½Ã¾Æ ½ºÆÄÀÌ·Î ¸ÅµµÇß´ø
»ç½ÇÀ» ÀØÀ» ¼ö´Â ¾ø¾ú´Ù. ±×°¡ º¸±â¿¡ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ±ÇÀ§ÁÖÀÇÀÚÀÌÀÚ ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î ÃÑȸ¸¦ ³ëµ¿ÀÚ Áö¹è¸¦
À§ÇÑ °³ÀÎÀÇ ÅÍÀüÀ¸·Î Å»¹Ù²Þ½ÃŰ·Á´Â ±³¸¸ÇÑ À¯´ëÀÎÀ̾ú´Ù.
±×´Â ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ Áß¾ÓÁý±Çȸ¦ ºñ·ÔÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿©·¯
À̷п¡ ¹Ý¹ßÇß°í ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â ±âÁ¸ ÀÇȸÁ¦µµ ³»¿¡¼
ÇϳªÀÇ Á¤´çÀ¸·Î ±â´ÉÇØ¾ß Çϸç ÀÏ´Ü ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ ±¹°¡°¡
Àüº¹µÈ ´ÙÀ½¿¡ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ® ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ Á¤±ÇÀ» ¼ö¸³Çؾß
ÇÑ´Ù´Â ½Å³ä¿¡µµ ºÎÁ¤ÀûÀ̾ú´Ù.
¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº
Çõ¸í°¡µéÀÇ ÀÓ¹«´Â 'ÆÄ±«'¿¡ ÀÖ´Ù°í »ý°¢Çß´Ù.
±×´Â ¼±Áø»ê¾÷±¹°¡ÀÇ ³ª¾àÇÑ ³ëµ¿Àڵ麸´Ù ·¯½Ã¾Æ ³ó¹ÎÀÇ
Á¦¾îÇϱâ Èûµç Çõ¸íÀû º»´É¿¡ ±â´ë¸¦ °É°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ÇлýµéÀÌ
Çõ¸íÀÇ ÁßÃß¼¼·ÂÀÌ µÇ±â¸¦ Èñ¸ÁÇß´ø ±×´Â ÀÌÅ»¸®¾Æ¡¤½ºÀ§½º¡¤ÇÁ¶û½º¿¡¼
û³â Áö¼ºÀεéÀÇ ¸¹Àº È£ÀÀÀ» ¾ò¾ú°í ºñ¹Ð°á»çÀÎ '±¹Á¦»çȸ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀǵ¿¸Í'À»
Á¶Á÷Çß´Ù. »çȸ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀǵ¿¸ÍÀº 1869³â ½ºÀ§½º ¹ÙÁ©¿¡¼ Á¦1Â÷
±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸ°¡ °³ÃֵǾúÀ» ¶§ °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸÀÇ Áö¹è±Ç¿¡
µµÀüÀåÀ» ³ÂÁö¸¸ À̵éÀÇ °¡ÀÔÀ» »çÀü ÀúÁö½ÃŰ·Á´Â
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¼ÕÀÌ Á¶±Ý ´õ »¡¶ú´Ù. ¹ÙÄí´ÑÁÖÀÇÀڵ鿡°Ô ÆÄ¸®
ÄÚ¹ÀÀº Çõ¸íÀû Á÷Á¢ÇൿÀÇ º»º¸±â¿Í °°¾Ò°í Ä«¸¦
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ±ÇÀ§ÁÖÀÇÀû °ø»êÁÖÀǸ¦ ¹Ý¹ÚÇÒ ¼ö Àִ ȣ±â¸¦
Á¦°øÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ¹ÌÇÏÀÏ ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î ³»ºÎ¿¡
ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ Á¶Á÷À» ±¸ÃàÇØ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ¸¦ °ø°ÝÇϱâ
½ÃÀÛÇß°í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Æí¿¡¼´Â ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀÌ Çù¹Ú°ú »ìÀÎÀ»
ÀÏ»ï¾Æ¿Â ·¯½Ã¾ÆÀÇ Çлý Çõ¸í°¡ ¼¼¸£°ÔÀÌ ³×Â÷¿¹ÇÁ¿Í
¿¬·çµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù´Â »ç½ÇÀ» °øÇ¥Çß´Ù.
º°´Ù¸¥
ÁöÁö ±â¹Ýµµ ¾øÀÌ ¹«Á¤ºÎÁÖÀÇ ÁÂÆÄ¿¡ ´ëÇ×ÇØ ¼± ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
¹ÙÄí´Ñ¿¡°Ô ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ ÁÖµµ±ÇÀ» »©¾Ñ±â°Ô µÇÁö³ª ¾ÊÀ»±î
µÎ·Á¿öÇß´Ù. ÇÑÆíÀ¸·Î´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ¿¬±¸·Î
µÇµ¹¾Æ°¡ ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀÇ ÁýÇÊÀ» ¸¶¹«¸®ÇÏ°í ½ÍÀº »ý°¢µµ
°£ÀýÇß´Ù. 1872³â ³×´ú¶õµå ÇìÀ̱׿¡¼ ÃÖÃÊ·Î ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î
ÀüüȸÀÇ¿¡ Âü¼®ÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¹ÙÄí´ÑÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀ»
ÆÐ¹è½ÃŰ´Â µ¥ ¼º°øÇßÀ¸¸ç ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÀÌ¿Í º¸Á¶¸¦ ¸ÂÃß¾î
°øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ¸¦ ·±´ø¿¡¼ ´º¿åÀ¸·Î ÀÌÀü½ÃŰÀÚ´Â ÀǰßÀ»
Á¦½ÃÇß´Ù. ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀÇ ÃßÁ¾ÀÚµéÀº ÃàÃâµÇ¾úÀ¸³ª Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ
¿µÇâ·ÂÀº ±â¿ï¾î°¬°í 1876³â Çʶóµ¨ÇǾƿ¡¼ ¸¶Ä§³»
ÇØÃ¼µÇ±â¿¡ À̸¥´Ù.
Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î
ÀÌÈÄÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· 10³â µ¿¾È ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã¢ÀÛ´É·ÂÀº ±Þ°ÝÈ÷
°¨¼ÒµÇ¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ½º½º·Î °í¹éÇßµíÀÌ ¸¸¼ºÀûÀÎ Á¤½ÅÀÇ
ħü¿¡ »ç·ÎÀâÇû°í ³»¸éÈµÈ °ü½ÉÀº °¡Á·µé¿¡°Ô ÇâÇß´Ù.
¿©ÀüÈ÷ µ¶¼·®ÀÌ ¸¹¾Ò°í ·¯½Ã¾Æ¾î ÇнÀ¿¡ Âø¼öÇϱ⵵
ÇßÁö¸¸ ½ÇÁúÀûÀ¸·Î ¾î¶°ÇÑ ÀÛ¾÷µµ ÀÌ·ç¾î³»Áö ¸øÇß´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Á¤Ä¡Àû °ßÇØ´Â ±× º¯´ö½º·¯¿òÀ¸·Î ÀÎÇØ Á¾ÀâÀ»
¼ö°¡ ¾ø°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù. ½ÉÁö¾î ±×´Â ¼Ò³â³ëµ¿ÀÇ ÆóÁö¸¦
¹Ý´ëÇϱâ±îÁö Çß´Ù. 1875³â ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÚµé°ú µ¶ÀÏÀÇ
¶ó»ìÆÄ°¡ µ¶ÀÏ »çȸ¹ÎÁÖ´çÀ» â¼³Çϱâ À§ÇØ °íŸ¿¡¼
ȸµ¿Çß´Ù. Æä¸£µð³Æ® ¶ó»ìÀº »çȸÁÖÀÇÀÇ ÀÌ»óÀÌ
±âÁ¸Ã¼Á¦¿ÍÀÇ Çù·Â ¼Ó¿¡¼ ´Þ¼ºµÉ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù°í ¹Ï¾ú´ø
Àι°À̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´°íŸ °·É ºñÆÇ Kritik des Gothaer
Programms¡µÀ» ÅëÇØ »çȸ¹ÎÁÖ´ç °·ÉÀÇ Áö³ªÄ£ Çö½ÇŸÇù¼ºÀ»
³í¹ÚÇß°í µ¶ÀÏ ÁöµµÀÚµéÀº ±×ÀÇ ºÐ³ë¸¦ °¡¶ó¾ÉÈ÷±â À§ÇØ
¿°ú ¼ºÀ» ´ÙÇß´Ù.
Á¡Â÷·Î
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â À¯·´¿¡¼ ÀüÀïÀÌ ÀϾ º¸¼ö ¹Ýµ¿ÁÖÀÇÀÇ
¸¶Áö¸· º¸·çÀÎ Â÷¸£ üÁ¦¸¦ ŸµµÇϱ⸦ ¹Ù¶ú´Ù.
ÀÌ ÀüÀïÀ¸·Î ³ëµ¿ÀÚ °è±ÞÀÇ Çõ¸íÀû ¿¡³ÊÁö°¡ ´Ù½Ã
¼Ò»ýµÉÁöµµ ¸ð¸¥´Ù´Â ¸·¿¬ÇÑ ±â´ë°¨¿¡¼¿´´Ù. 1881³â Â÷¸£
¾Ë·º»êµå¸£ 2¼¼°¡ ¾Ï»ìµÇÀÚ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ·¯½Ã¾Æ ³ª·Îµå´ÏŰÀÇ
»ç½É¾ø´Â ¿ë±â¿¡ ±íÀº °¨¸íÀ» ¹Þ¾Ò´Ù. Å×·¯´Â
¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô '»óȲÀûÀ¸·Î ºÒ°¡ÇÇÇÑ ¼ö´ÜÀÇ Çϳª'·Î
¿©°ÜÁ³´Ù. ºñ·Ï Çö½ÇÁ¤Ä¡¿¡¼ ÇÑ °ÉÀ½ ¹°·¯¼± °ÍÀº
»ç½ÇÀ̾úÁö¸¸ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿¨°Ö½º°¡ ¸»Çß´ø °Íó·³
»çȸÁÖÀÇÀû ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿¿¡ ´ëÇØ ¿©ÀüÈ÷ 'µ¶Æ¯ÇÑ ¿µÇâ·Â'À»
Çà»çÇϰí ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. 1879³â Áæ °Ôµå°¡ ÇÁ¶û½º »çȸÁÖÀÇ
³ëµ¿ÀÚ¿¬¸ÍÀÇ Ã¢¼³¿¡ ÁîÀ½ÇÏ¿© ·±´øÀ» ¹æ¹®,
¸¶¸£Å©½º·ÎºÎÅÍ °·ÉÀÇ Àü¹®°ú ³»¿ë¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÚ¹®À»
¾ò¾î°¬´Ù. 1881³â¿¡´Â ¡´À×±Û·£µå Æ÷ ¿Ã England for All¡µÁö(ò¼)ÀÇ
Ç ¸ÞÀ̾ ÇÏÀεå¸ÕÀÌ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿ÍÀÇ ´ë´ãÀ» ºñÁßÀÖ°Ô
´Ù·ç¾úÁö¸¸ ±×ÀÇ À̸§À» ¹àÈ÷±â¸¦ ²¨·ÁÇÏ¿© ³ë¿©¿òÀ» »ò´Ù.
¸»³âÀÇ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ´ëºÎºÐÀÇ ½Ã°£À» ÈÞ¾çÁö¿¡¼ º¸³Â°í
¾ËÁ¦¸®±îÁö ¿©ÇàÀ» ¶°³ª±âµµ Çß´Ù. Ä«¸¦Àº ¾Æ³»(1881.12.2)¿Í
Àå³à ¿¹´Ï ·Õ±¸¿¡Æ®(1883.1.11)ÀÇ Á×À½À¸·Î ºñź¿¡ Á¥¾î »ì´Ù°¡
1883³â 3¿ù ¿µ±¹ÀÇ ·±´ø¿¡¼ ÆóÁ¾¾çÀ¸·Î »ç¸ÁÇß´Ù.
Æò°¡
ÇÏÀ̰ÔÀÌÆ®
ÇÁ¶óÀÌÈ£ÇÁÀÇ Àå·Ê½Ä¿¡¼ ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡
'Àηù¿ª»ç ¹ßÀüÀÇ ¹ýÄ¢'°ú 'ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ »çȸ¿îµ¿ÀÇ ¹ýÄ¢'À»
¹ß°ßÇØ³Â´Ù°í ¼±¾ðÇß´Ù. "¹«¾ùº¸´Ù Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
À§´ëÇÑ Çõ¸í°¡¿´´Ù. Áõ¿ÀÀÇ ´ë»óÀÌ µÇ¾î ±Ø´ÜÀûÀÎ ºñ¹æ°ú
¸ð·«¿¡ ½Ã´Þ·È´ø ±×´Â ÀÌÁ¦ ¼ö¹é¸¸ ³ëµ¿ÀÚµéÀÇ »ç¶û°ú Á¸°æ,
¾Öµµ ¼Ó¿¡¼ ´«À» °¨´Â´Ù."
¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô´Â
ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺ÀûÀÎ ¹ÝÇ×°ú ¹«·ÂÇÑ Áö¼ºÀÌ º¹ÇյǾî ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÁÖÀ§ »ç¶÷µé¿¡°Ô ÁöÀû ±³¸¸ÇÔÀÇ ÀλóÀ»
ÀüÇØÁÖ¾ú´Ù. 1846³â ·¯½Ã¾ÆÀÇ ÀÛ°¡ ÆÄº§ ¾È³ÙÄÚÇÁ´Â Åä·Ð¿¡
Âü¿©ÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¸¦ °üÂûÇÑ µÚ ÀÌ·¸°Ô ȸ»óÇß´Ù. "±×ÀÇ
¸»Åõ´Â Ç×»ó ¸í·ÉÁ¶¿¡ °¡±î¿ü°í ¹Ý·ÐÀ» ¿ëÀÎÇÏ´Â ¹ýÀÌ
¾ø¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ¸¶Ä¡ ȯ»ó ¼Ó¿¡¼³ª ³ªÅ¸³¯ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â ¹ÎÁÖÀû
µ¶ÀçÀÚ¿Í °°¾Ò´Ù." ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ´Ù¼öÀÇ Ã»Áß ¾Õ¿¡ ³ª¼´Â
°Í¿¡ ºÒÆíÇÔÀ» ´À²¼°í ÆÄ¹ú³íÀïÀÇ ºÐÀ§±â¸¦ ÁÁ¾ÆÇÏÁö
¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. ¾Æ³» ¿¹´Ï ¿ª½Ã ±×°¡ ½ÃÀ§¿¡ Âü¿©ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾ÒÀ¸¸ç
°ø°øÈ¸ÀÇ ¼®»ó¿¡¼ °ÅÀÇ À̾߱⸦ ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù°í ¹àÈ÷°í
ÀÖ´Ù. ±×´Â ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ³ª ½Å¹®»ç °£ºÎ¸ðÀÓ°ú
°°Àº ¼Ò±Ô¸ð ºÐÀ§±â¸¦ °¡Àå Æí¾ÈÇÏ°Ô ´À²¼´Ù. ±×ÀÇ ¼º°ÝÀº
¼ÒÁý´ÜÀÇ µ¿·áµé¿¡°Ô °·ÂÇÑ ÈûÀ» ¹ßÈÖÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. µ¿½Ã¿¡
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ´ëµîÇÑ À§Ä¡¿¡¼ °æÁ¦Çаú »çȸÇÐÀÇ ¿©·¯
¹®Á¦µéÀ» ³íÀÇÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â ¸í¸ÁÀÖ´Â ÇÐÀÚµé°úÀÇ È¸ÇÕÀ»
±âÇÇÇß´Ù. ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ³ÐÀº ½Ä°ß¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
¿µ±¹ÀÇ ¿Ü¹«Àå°ü ÆÄ¸Ó½ºÅÏ °æÀÌ ·¯½Ã¾Æ Á¤ºÎÀÇ Ã¸ÀÚ¶ó´Â
½ÄÀÇ °¹Ú°ü³ä¿¡ »ç·ÎÀâÇô ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸ°¡
ÀÚ½ÅÀ» 'µ· ¸¸µå´Â ±â°è'·Î Àü¶ô½ÃŰÁö ¸øÇÏ°Ô Çϰڴٰí
°á½ÉÇϸ鼵µ ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ Áõ¿©¿Í ģôµéÀÇ ¿©·¯ À¯»ê¿¡
»ý°è¸¦ ÀÇÁ¸Çß´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
¿¹¼ö°¡ ¾î¸°À̵éÀ» »ç¶ûÇ߱⠶§¹®¿¡ ¿¹¼ö¸¦ Âù¾çÇÑ´Ù°í
¸»ÇÒ Á¤µµ·Î ¾ÖÁ¤ÀÌ ³ÑÄ¡´Â ¾Æ¹öÁö¿´Áö¸¸ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ »ýȰÀ̳ª
°Ç°À» µ¹º¸Áö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. ±×´Â 'ÅõÀï'À» »î°ú
Á¸ÀçÀÇ ¹ýÄ¢À¸·Î °£ÁÖÇßÀ¸¸ç ¾ð¾îÀÇ ½ÀµæÁ¶Â÷µµ »îÀÇ
ÅõÀï¿¡¼ »õ·Î¿î ¹«±â¸¦ ȹµæÇÏ´Â ÀÏÀ̶ó°í »ý°¢ÇÒ
Á¤µµ¿´´Ù. °³ÀÎÀûÀÎ ½À¼ºÀ̳ª »ýȰ¹æ½Ä¿¡ ÀÖ¾î¼
¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿µ¿øÇÑ ÇлýÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â µÎ Ä£±¸¿Í ÇÔ²²
°Å¸®ÀÇ °¡·ÎµîÀ» ±úºÎ¼ö°í °æÂûÀÌ ¸ô·Á¿ÀÀÚ ²Ç¹«´Ï¸¦ »©´Â
¾î¸®±¤½º·¯¿î Àå³À» Çϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ±×´Â ´ë´ÜÇÑ
¼Ò¼³±¤À¸·Î¼ ƯÈ÷ ¿ùÅÍ ½ºÄà °æ°ú ¹ßÀÚÅ©¿¡ Ž´ÐÇß°í
°¡Á·Àº ¸ðµÎ ¼ÎÀͽºÇǾîÀÇ ¿¹Âù·ÐÀÚµéÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í
¿¹´Ï »çÀÌ¿¡´Â 7¸íÀÇ Àڳడ ÀÖ¾úÀ¸³ª ¼¼ µþ¸¸ ³²°í
³ª¸ÓÁö´Â À¯³â±â¿¡ ÀÒ°í ¸»¾Ò´Ù. °¡Àå ÃѾÖÇß´ø
¿¤·¹¾Æ³ë¸£´Â ½Å°æÁúÀûÀÌ°í °¨¼ºÀûÀÎ ¼º°ÝÀ» Áö³æÀ¸¸ç
¿©¹è¿ì°¡ µÇ·Á´Â ¼Ò¸ÁÀ¸·Î ÀÎÇØ ±×¸¦ ±Ù½ÉÇÏ°Ô Çß´Ù. ¶Ç´Ù¸¥
±×¸²ÀÚ°¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °¡Á¤»ýȰÀ» ¾îµÓ°Ô ¸¸µé¾ú´Âµ¥ Çϳà
Çï·¹³× µ¥¹«Æ®°¡ ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷¶ó´Â »ç»ý¾Æ¸¦ Ãâ»êÇß±â
¶§¹®À̾ú´Ù. ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ÀÓÁ¾½Ã¿¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡
ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ÀÇ ¾Æ¹öÁöÀÓÀ» ¿¤·¹¾Æ³ë¸£¿¡°Ô ÀÏ·¯ÁÖ¾ú´Ù.
±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸÀÇ
°áÀǼ¿¡ '³ëµ¿°è±ÞÀÇ ¼º¼'¶ó°í °ø½Ä ±â¼úµÈ
¹Ù ÀÖ´Â ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀº 1867³â
º£¸¦¸°¿¡¼ ÃâÆÇµÇ¾ú°í 1873³â ÀçÆÇµÇ¾ú´Ù. ¿ÀÁ÷ ù ±Ç¸¸ÀÌ
»ýÁ¸½Ã¿¡ ¿Ï¼ºµÇ¾ú°í Á¦2±Ç°ú Á¦3±ÇÀº ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ ÆíÁý¿¡ ÀÇÇØ
1885³â°ú 1894³â Ãâ°£µÇ¾úÀ¸¸ç, óÀ½ Á¦4±ÇÀ¸·Î ±¸»óµÇ¾ú´ø
ºÎºÐÀº 1905~10³â ¡´À׿©°¡Ä¡Çм³»ç¡µ¶ó´Â µ¶¸³µÈ ÇüÅ·Î
Ä«¸¦ Ä«¿ìÃ÷Ű¿¡ ÀÇÇØ Ãâ°£µÇ¾ú´Ù.
Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â µ¥À̺ñµå ¸®Ä«µµÀÇ
°íÀü °æÁ¦ÇÐÀ» ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸ´Â ¸ðµç »çȸÀû À¯±âü¿Í
¸¶Âù°¡Áö·Î ºÒ°¡ÇÇÇÑ ¹ßÀüÀÇ °æ·Î¸¦ °ÅÃÄ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â
À¯¹°º¯Áõ¹ý°ú °áÇÕ½ÃÄ×´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡
¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀ» ÁغñÇÏ¸é¼ ¼öÇàÇß´ø ÀÛ¾÷ÀÌ ¾ó¸¶³ª
±¤¹üÀ§Çߴ°¡¸¦ ¾Ë·Á¸é ¸ÕÀú ¸¹Àº ¾çÀÇ À¯°í(ë¶ÍÃ)¿Í ¼ö°í(â¢ÍÃ),
¹æÁÖ(Û¨ñÉ), ¼½Å±³È¯ µîÀ» Á¶»çÇØº¸¾Æ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù. ±×ÀÇ
ºÐ¼®´ë»óÀº ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ »ý»ê°úÁ¤ÀÇ º»Áú, ÀÚº»ÀÇ À¯Åë°úÁ¤,
ÀÚº»ÀÇ ÃѰúÁ¤, Àΰ£°ú ÀÚ¿¬ÀÇ ¹°Áú´ë»ç, À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â ºñÆÇ,
Àΰ£»ó, À׿©°¡Ä¡·Ð°ú ±× ¿ª»ç¿¡±îÁö À̸£·¶´Ù. »Ó¸¸ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó
±×´Â »çȸÇС¤±â¼ú¡¤°øÇÐÀû ¹®Á¦µéÀ» ¿¬±¸Çß°í ¼öÇÐ ¹×
ÀÚ¿¬°úÇÐÀ» ¿¬±¸ÇßÀ¸¸ç ¿ª»çÀû °úÁ¤°ú ³ó¾÷°æÁ¦¸¦
ºÐ¼®Çߴ°¡ Çϸé, Çì°ÖÀÇ ¡´³í¸®ÇÐ Wissenschaft der Logik¡µ¿¡
Ưº°È÷ ÁÖ¸ñÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ »çȸÀÇ
¹ýÄ¢¼º¿¡ °üÇÑ ¿¬±¸¸¦ ÀÚ¿¬»çÀû(í»æÔÞÈîÜ) °úÁ¤À̶ó´Â
¼º°ÝÀ» °®´Â »çȸ±¸¼ºÃ¼ ¹ßÀüÀÌ·ÐÀ¸·Î ÃѰýÇßÀ¸¸ç °æÁ¦Àû
Åä´ë, À̵¥¿Ã·Î±âÀû »óºÎ±¸Á¶, »ý»ê·Â, »ý»ê°ü°è µî
»çȸ±¸¼ºÃ¼ÀÇ »ý»ê°ü°è¸¦ ¹àÈ÷°í »çȸ±¸¼ºÃ¼ÀÇ ¿©·¯ ¿ä¼Òµé
»çÀÌÀÇ »óÈ£°ü°è¸¦ ޱ¸Çß´Ù.
¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀº
ÀÌÀ±ÀÇ °¨¼ÒÀ²°ú °°Àº ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇÀÇ ³»ÀçÀû ¸ð¼øµéÀÌ
ÇöÀúÇØÁü¿¡ µû¶ó ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ´Â »ç¶óÁö°í ´õ ³ªÀº »çȸ·ÎÀÇ
ÀÌÇàÀÌ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁú °ÍÀ̶ó°í ¿¹¾ðÇÑ´Ù. ±â¾ïÇÒ
¸¸ÇÑ ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀÇ ³»¿ë °¡¿îµ¥ ¿µ±¹ ÀÇȸÀÇ Ã»¼(ôìßö)¿¡¼
¹ßÃéÇÑ °ÍÀ¸·Î ³ëµ¿°è±ÞÀÇ ºñÂüÇÑ »ýȰÀ» ¼¼úÇÑ
ÆäÀÌÁöµéÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÌ ºñÂüÇÔÀÌ Áõ°¡µÇ°í µ¿½Ã¿¡
ÀÚº»ÀÇ µ¶Á¡ÀÌ »ý»ê¿¡ ´ëÇÏ¿© ÂøÃë·Î ÀÛ¿ëÇÏ´Â °¡¿îµ¥
¸¶Ä§³» ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çÀ¯Àç»êÀÇ Á¶Á¾(ðÀñ¤)ÀÌ ¿ï¸®°Ô µÇ°í
ÂøÃëÀÚ°¡ ÇÇÂøÃëÀÚ·Î Àü¶ôÇÏ°Ô µÇ¸®¶ó°í ¹Ï¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â
°è±Þ°ú °è±ÞÅõÀïÀÇ Á¸À縦 ÀÚ½ÅÀÌ ¹ß°ßÇÑ °ÍÀ̶ó°í
ÁÖÀåÇÏÁö´Â ¾Ê°í ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ ¿ª»ç°¡µéÀÌ Àڱ⺸´Ù ÈξÀ
ÀÌÀü¿¡ ÀÌ ¹®Á¦µéÀ» ´Ù·ç¾î¿ÔÀ½À» ÀÎÁ¤Çß´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ±×´Â
»ý»ê¹ßÀüÀÇ °¢ ´Ü°è´Â ÀÌ¿¡ »óÀÀÇÏ´Â °è±Þ±¸Á¶¿Í ¿¬°üÀÌ
ÀÖ´Ù´Â °Í°ú °è±ÞÅõÀïÀº ÇÊ¿¬ÀûÀ¸·Î ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ
µ¶À縦 ³º¾Æ ¹«°è±Þ »çȸÀÇ µµ·¡°¡ ½ÇÇöµÉ °ÍÀÓÀ» ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù.
¾î¶»°Ô ±×°¡ ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ÁÖÁ¦µé¿¡ °üÇÑ ¸î¸î ´Ü¶ôµéÀ» Çй®Àû
Ç¥ÁØ¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁø ÇÙ½ÉÀûÀÎ Áõ°Å·Î °£ÁÖÇϰÔ
µÇ¾ú´Â°¡¸¦ ÀÌÇØÇϱâ¶õ ½±Áö ¾ÊÀº ÀÏÀÌ´Ù.
²÷ÀÓ¾øÀÌ
¿Ï¼ºµÇ¾î°¡´Â Çõ¸í°úÁ¤ ¼Ó¿¡¼ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º´Â
ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ À¯´ÉÇÑ ÁöµµÀÚ¿Í À̷а¡¸¦ ÇÑ ¼¼´ë¿¡
°ÉÃÄ ±æ·¯³Â´Ù. º£º§,
ºôÇ︧ ¸®ÇÁÅ©³×È÷Æ®,
¶ó ÆÄ¸£±×, ¸Þ¸µ,
Ä«¿ìÃ÷Ű µîÀÌ ±×·¯ÇÑ Àι°µéÀÌ´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®¿¡°Ô ±×µéÀÇ Ã³Áö¿Í ¿å±¸¸¦ °úÇÐÀûÀ¸·Î
ÀνÄÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ°Ô ÇØÁÖ¾ú´Ù. ³ëµ¿ÀÚ °è±ÞÀÇ ¿ª»çÀû »ç¸íÀ»
½ÇÇöÇÏ´Â µ¥ Çù·ÂÇÏ´Â °Í, À̰ÍÀÌ ±×ÀÇ ÁøÁ¤ÇÑ ÇÊ»ýÀÇ
Á÷¹«¿´´Ù. ±×ÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀº °áÄÚ ÀÚ±â¸ñÀûÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¾ú°í Ç×»ó
»çȸ¸¦ ÀνÄÇÏ°í º¯ÇõÇÏ´Â ¹«±â¿´´Ù. ±×°ÍÀº °æÁ¦»ýȰ°ú
Á¤Ä¡Àû °è±ÞÅõÀï, °úÇаú ±â¼úÀÇ Çõ¸í, ±×¸®°í ÀιÎÀÇ
¹®ÈÀû¡¤Á¤Ä¡Àû ¹ßÀü µî°úÀÇ °áÇÕ¿¡¼ ¾ò¾îÁø °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀº °ÅÀÇ 150³â¿¡ °ÉÄ£ ¿ª»ç ¼Ó¿¡¼ »ý¸í·ÂÀ»
ÀÔÁõÇßÀ¸¸ç Çõ¸íÀû ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿°ú ½ÇÀçÇÏ´Â »çȸÁÖÀÇ ¼Ó¿¡¼
½ÇÇöµÇ¾ú´Ù. ±×°ÍÀº »çȸÁÖÀÇ »çȸÀÇ ÀÌ·ÐÀû¡¤½ÇõÀû
¹®Á¦Çذá°úÁ¤ ¼Ó¿¡ Áö¾çµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù. ±×°ÍÀº ºí¶óµð¹Ì¸£
Àϸ®Ä¡ ·¹´Ñ¿¡
ÀÇÇØ ´õ¿í ¹ßÀüµÇ¾úÀ¸¸ç °ø»ê´ç°ú ³ëµ¿ÀÚ´çÀÇ Á¤Ä¡¿¡
ÀÖ¾î¼ ÀÌ·ÐÀû Åä´ë¸¦ Çü¼ºÇß´Ù.
»çȸÇÐ
À̷п¡ ÀÖ¾î ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °¡Àå Áö´ëÇÑ °øÇåÀº ±×ÀÇ ÀϹÝÀû
ºÐ¼®¾ç½Ä, Áï 'º¯Áõ¹ýÀûÀÎ' ¾ç½Ä¿¡ ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ
¾ç½ÄÀº ¸ðµç »çȸü°è°¡ ³»ÀçÀû ¸ð¼ø(ºÒ¾ÈÁ¤)À» ¹ß»ý½Ã۸ç
ÀÌ ¸ð¼øÀº »õ·Î¿î »çȸÀÇ µîÀå¿¡ ÀÇÇØ¼¸¸ ÇØ°áµÉ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù°í
°£ÁÖÇÑ´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ºÐ¼®¾ç½ÄÀº Åä¸Ó½º ¸È¼½º,
Çã¹öÆ® ½ºÆæ¼,
ºôÇÁ·¹µµ ÆÄ·¹ÅäÀÇ
¾ç½Ä°ú ´õºÒ¾î »çȸ°úÇÐÀÇ ´ëÇ¥ÀûÀÎ À̷б¸Á¶ÀÇ Çϳª·Î
Á¤¸³µÇ¾ú°í, ´õÀÌ»ó ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀÇ °æÁ¦ÇÐÀû
Ãß·ÐÀ» ¹Þ¾ÆµéÀÌÁö ¾Ê´Â ½Å¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀڵ鵵 ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ
»çȸüÁ¦ÀÇ ºÐ¼®¿¡ À־ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ºÐ¼®¾ç½Ä¿¡
ÀÇÁ¸Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ±×ÀÇ »ç°í¾ç½ÄÀ» °ÅºÎÇØ¿Â ÇÐÀÚµé·Î´Â
°æÇèÁÖÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ °èÅëÀÇ ¹öÆ®·±µå ·¯¼¿,
Á¸ µàÀÌ,
±×¸®°í Ä«¸¦ Æ÷ÆÛ°¡
ÀÖ´Ù.¡æ °ø»êÁÖÀÇ
L.
S. Feuer ±Û
¡¡
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ (¦¡¦¡ ñ«ëù, Marxism)
19¼¼±â Áß¹Ý Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í
ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½º°¡
¹ßÀü½ÃŲ ÀÏ´ÜÀÇ Çм³Ã¼°è.
Àΰ£ÇÐ, ¿ª»çöÇÐ, Á¤Ä¡¡¤°æÁ¦ ÀÌ·ÐÀÇ 3ºÎºÐÀÌ »óÈ£¿¬°üÀ»
¸Î°í ÀÖ´Ù. À̵éÀ» °áÇÕ½ÃÄÑ ÀϰüµÈ ³í¸®Ã¼°è¸¦ Çü¼ºÇÏ·Á´Â
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ³ë·Â¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í ¸»³â, ƯÈ÷ »çÈÄ¿¡ ³»·ÁÁø
´Ù¾çÇÑ ÇØ¼®°ú ¼Ò·ÃÀÇ °ø½Ä À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â·Î¼ äÅõÈ(1917)
ÀÌÈÄÀÇ Á¤Ä¡Àû ¿äûÀ¸·Î ¸»¹Ì¾Ï¾Æ ¸¹Àº ŸÇù°ú ÀýÃæÀÌ
ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù. ¿À´Ã³¯ '¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ'´Â °ø»êÁÖÀÇ¡¤»çȸÁÖÀÇ
Á¦Á¤´çÀÇ À̳ä°ú ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÞÀº ¿©·¯ »ç»ó°¡µéÀÇ
Á¤Ä¡¡¤»çȸ¡¤°æÁ¦ ÀÌ·ÐÀ» Æ÷°ýÇÏ°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ´Â Àΰ£ÀÇ Ã¢Á¶·Â¿¡¼ Àΰ£¸¸ÀÌ °¡Áö´Â
°íÀ¯ÇÑ Æ¯¼ºÀ» ¹ß°ßÇÑ´Ù. âÁ¶·ÂÀ̶õ ÇÊ¿äÀÇ ÃæÁ·À» À§ÇØ
ÀÚ¿¬À̶ó´Â ´ë»ó¿¡ ½ñ´Â Àΰ£ÀÇ ³ë·Â°ú ³ëµ¿·ÂÀ̸ç, ¿©±â¼
³ëµ¿Àº °³ÀÎÀûÀÎ °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó Àηù¶ó°í ÇÏ´Â ÇϳªÀÇ Á¾(ðú)À»
À§ÇÑ ³ë·ÂÀÌ´Ù. Àΰ£ÀÇ ÅëÁ¦¹üÀ§¸¦ ¹þ¾î³ª±âµµ ÇÏ´Â
º¹Àâ´Ù´ÜÇÑ ¿ª»çÀû »ç°Çµé·Î ÀÎÇØ ÀÌ¿Í °°Àº ÀÌ»óÀº ¾ÆÁ÷
½ÇÇöµÇÁö ¸øÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ¿¹ÄÁ´ë ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ Ã¼Á¦¿¡¼´Â
âÁ¶ÀûÀÎ ¿¡³ÊÁö ȤÀº ³ëµ¿·ÂÀ» Åõ¿©ÇÏ´Â °³Àαº(ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®)°ú
ÀÓ±ÝÀ» ÁÖ°í ÀÌ ³ëµ¿ÀÇ »ê¹°À» µµ¿ëÇÏ´Â °è±Þ(ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾ÆÁö)ÀÌ
µû·Î Á¸ÀçÇϸç, ÀÌ´Â ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®¿¡ ÀÇÇØ âÁ¶µÈ ¼¼°è°¡
½ÇÁ¦·Î ³ëµ¿¿¡ Âü¿©ÇÏÁö ¾ÊÀº ÀÚº»°¡ °è±Þ¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ¼ÒÀ¯µÇ°í
ÀÖÀ½À» ÀǹÌÇÑ´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ Çö½ÇÀÇ ¸ð¼øÀ» '
¼Ò¿Ü'¶ó´Â ¸»·Î Ç¥ÇöÇß´Ù.
³ëµ¿ÀÚ °è±ÞÀÌ ³ëµ¿ÀÇ °á½ÇÀ» ȸº¹ÇÏ°Ô µÇ´Â ±×³¯ÀÌ µµ·¡ÇÒ
¶§, ¼Ò¿Ü´Â ±Øº¹µÇ°í ¸ðµç °è±ÞÀÇ ±¸ºÐµéÀº »ç¶óÁö°Ô µÉ
°ÍÀÌ´Ù.
°è±ÞÅõÀï°ú °è±Þ ¾ø´Â »çȸÀÇ À̳äÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½º ÀÌÀü¿¡
ÀÌ¹Ì Á¦Ã¢µÇ°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. °øµ¿Ã¼ ³»ÀÇ °æÁ¦Àû ÀÌÇØ°ü°è°¡
°¥µîÀ» À¯¹ßÇÑ´Ù´Â Âø»óÀº ¸Ö¸® ÅõŰµðµ¥½ºÀÇ ÀúÀÛ¿¡±îÁö
¼Ò±ÞµÇ¸ç, ±âÁ¸ °æÁ¦Ã¼Á¦ÀÇ ºñÆÇ À§¿¡ °è±Þ¾ø´Â ÀÌ»ó»çȸ¸¦
°Ç¼³ÇÏ·Á´Â °®°¡Áö »ç»óµéÀÌ 19¼¼±âÀÇ Ã¹ 10³â µ¿¾È ²ÉÀ»
ÇÇ¿ü´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÌ 2°¡Áö À̳äÀ» »ö´Ù¸¥ ¹æ½ÄÀ¸·Î
°áÇÕ½ÃÄ×´Ù. °ø»óÀû »çȸÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀÇ °úÁ¦´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÌ
»ý°¢ÇÏ´Â À¯ÅäÇǾư¡ ¾î¶°ÇÑ °ÍÀΰ¡¿¡ ÀÖ´Â °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó
±×°Í¿¡ µµ´ÞÇÏ´Â ¹æ¹ýÀ» Á¦½ÃÇÏ´Â µ¥ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
°è±ÞÅõÀïÀ» ¿ª»çÀÇ ÃßÁø·ÂÀ¸·Î °£ÁÖÇÑ µÚ ÀηùÀÇ ¿ª»ç´Â
°è±Þ ¾ø´Â »çȸÀÇ ÃâÇöÀ¸·Î Á¤Á¡¿¡ ¿À¸¦ °ÍÀ̶ó°í
³»´Ùº¸¾Ò´Ù. "Áö±Ý±îÁöÀÇ ¿ª»ç´Â °è±ÞÅõÀïÀÇ ¿ª»çÀÌ´Ù"¶ó°í
½ÃÀ۵Ǵ ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð
Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei¡µÀÇ Ã¹ ±¸ÀýÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½º
¿ª»ç°üÀÇ °¡Àå °·ÂÇÑ Ç¥ÇöÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º¿¡°Ô
¸ðµç ¿ª»ç´Â ÂøÃë°è±Þ°ú ÇÇÂøÃë°è±Þ »çÀÌÀÇ ÅõÀïÀÇ
¿¬¼ÓÀ¸·Î ºñÃÆ´Ù. ¿ª»ç´Â ÀüÀ¹ß°ß¡¤¹ß¸í¡¤Á¶¾à¡¤À½¸ð
µîÀ¸·Î Àü°³µÈ´Ù´Â °ÍÀÌ Á¾ÀüÀÇ °ßÇØ¿´´Ù¸é ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â
À̵éÀÌ ¹ÛÀ¸·Î µå·¯³ª´Â Çã»ó¿¡ ºÒ°úÇÏ´Ù°í ´Ü¾ðÇß´Ù.
¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô ¿ª»çÀÇ µ¿ÀÎÀº Àΰ£ÀÇ ÀÇ¡¤½Ä¡¤ÁÖ ¹®Á¦¸¦
ÇØ°áÇÏ´Â '»ý»ê¼ö´Ü'ÀÇ ¹ßÀü¿¡ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.
Àΰ£ÀÌ »ýÁ¸Çϱâ À§Çؼ´Â ¹°Áú¿¡ÀÇ ÀÇÁ¸ÀÌ ºÒ°¡ÇÇÇÏ´Ù´Â
°ÍÀÌ ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ Á¦Ã¢ÇÑ ' ¿ª»çÀû
À¯¹°·Ð'ÀÇ ÇÙ½ÉÀ̾ú´Ù. ¹°ÁúÀûÀÎ »ýȰÀ» À¯ÁöÇϱâ À§ÇØ
Àΰ£Àº »ý»ê¼ö´ÜÀ̶ó´Â ÀÏ´ÜÀÇ °ü°è¸¦ ÅëÇØ ÀÚ¿¬°ú
±³·ùÇØ¾ß¸¸ ÇÑ´Ù. Àηù´Â ¿ª»çÀÇ ¸Å´Ü°è¸¶´Ù µ¶Æ¯ÇÑ
»ý»ê¼ö´ÜÀ» ¹ßÀü½ÃÄѿԴÙ. 14¼¼±âÀÇ ÀÚº»°¡ °è±ÞÀ̶õ »ó»óÇÒ
¼ö ¾øÀ¸¸ç, 20¼¼±âÀÇ ºÀ°Ç¿µÁÖ¶õ Á¸ÀçÇÏÁö ¾Ê´Â´Ù. ¿ª»ç´Â
º¯Áõ¹ýÀÇ ¿ø¸®¿¡ µû¶ó ½º½º·Î ÁøÈÇØ°£´Ù. ¸Å´Ü°è´Â
»ó¹ÝµÇ´Â ´Ü°è¿¡ ÀÇÇØ °è½ÂµÇ¸ç ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ 2´Ü°èÀÇ »óÈ£ÀÛ¿ëÀÌ
Á¾ÇÕÀ» ÀÌ·ç´Â °úÁ¤¿¡¼ »õ·Î¿î ¿ª»ç´Ü°è°¡ ´ëµÎÇÑ´Ù. ¾î´À
´Ü°è¿¡¼³ª »ý»ê¼ö´ÜÀÇ ÀüÁ¦°¡ µÇ´Â °ÍÀº Àΰ£°ú ÀÚ¿¬,
±×¸®°í Àΰ£°ú Àΰ£ »çÀÌÀÇ °ü°èÀε¥ Àΰ£Àº ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ °ü°èµé
¼Ó¿¡¼ ½º½º·ÎÀÇ Àΰ£¼ºÀ» »ó½ÇÇØ°£´Ù.
ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ
°æÁ¦Ã¼Á¦´Â °¡Àå ÃÖ±ÙÀÇ ¿ª»ç´Ü°èÀÌ´Ù. ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇÀÇ ¹ø¿µÀº
»ý»ê·Â ±Ô¸ðÀÇ ¼¼°èÀûÀÎ È®´ë¿Í ¾öû³ ¾çÀÇ À׿©°¡Ä¡
âÃâ¿¡ ±âÃÊÇϰí ÀÖÀ¸¸ç À׿©°¡Ä¡´Â °í½º¶õÈ÷ ÀÚº»°¡ÀÇ
¸òÀ¸·Î µÈ´Ù. ³»ÀçÀûÀÎ ¸ð¼ø¿¡ ½Ã´Þ¸®°í ÀÖ´Â ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ´Â
±×·¯³ª ¹ø¿µÀ» Áö¼ÓÇÒ ¼ö´Â ¾ø´Ù. °¡Àå Áß¿äÇÑ »ç½ÇÀº
ÀÚº»ÁÖÀǰ¡ ¸ðµç Àΰ£µéÀ» »óǰÈÇÔÀ¸·Î½á °³¼ºÀ»
¸»»ì½ÃŲ´Ù´Â Á¡ÀÌ´Ù. ÀÌ·± ½ÄÀ¸·Î ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ´Â ÀÚ¸êÀ»
ÃÊ·¡ÇÑ´Ù. ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ·Î ¸»¹Ì¾Ï¾Æ °è±ÞÅõÀïÀº °áÁ¤ÀûÀÎ
±¹¸éÀ» ¸ÂÀÌÇϸç, ¸í¹éÇÑ ÂøÃë·Î ÀÎÇØ ¿ÏÀüÈ÷ Àΰ£¼ºÀ»
»ó½ÇÇÏ°Ô µÈ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â ¸¶Ä§³» °øµ¿¸ñÇ¥¸¦ ÇâÇØ
´ÜÇÕÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ°Ô µÈ´Ù. ±×¸®ÇÏ¿© ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ½Â¸®°¡
ÀÓ¹ÚÇÏ°í °è±Þ ¾ø´Â ÀÌ»ó»çȸ°¡ ½ÇÇöµÇ±â¿¡ À̸¥´Ù.
ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ÀÌÀÍÀº Àüü ÀηùÀÇ ÀÌÀÍÀ̸ç,
ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ½Â¸®´Â ³ëµ¿ÀÇ ºÐȰ¡ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁø ÀÌÈÄ
²÷ÀÓ¾øÀÌ °øµ¿Ã¼¸¦ ±«·ÓÇô¿Â °è±ÞÀÇ ºÐȸ¦ ºÒ½Ä½Ãų
°ÍÀÌ´Ù.
1848³â Çõ¸íÀÌ ½ÇÆÐ·Î µ¹¾Æ°¡°í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ºÐ¼®Æ²ÀÌ
º¹À⼺À» ´õÇØ°¡´Â »çȸ±¸Á¶ÀÇ ÇØ¸í¿¡ ÇѰ踦 µå·¯³»ÀÚ,
ƯÈ÷ ¸¶¸£Å©½º »çÈÄ¿¡ À̷п¡ ´ëÇÑ ¼öÁ¤°ú º¸¿ÏÀÛ¾÷ÀÌ
ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù. ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í Ä«¸¦ Ä«¿ìÃ÷۵î
Á¤Åë ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀº ƯÁ¤ »óȲÀ» °Ü³ÉÇÑ
Çõ¸í°·ÉÀ¸·ÎºÎÅÍ ¿ª»çÀÇ ÁøÈ¿¡ µû¸¥ ±Ã±ØÀûÀÎ ½Â¸®¶ó°í
ÇÏ´Â ÆòÈÀûÀÎ ±â´ë ÂÊÀ¸·Î ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÇ ¼º°ÝÀ»
º¯È½ÃÄ×´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ´Â ºí¶óµð¹Ì¸£ Àϸ®Ä¡ ·¹´Ñ¿¡
ÀÇÇØ º¸´Ù ½É°¢ÇÑ º¯ÁúÀ» °Þ°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù. ·¹´ÑÀº ³ëµ¿ÀÚ
°è±ÞÀÇ ÀÚ¹ßÀûÀÎ Çõ¸í¼öÇà´É·ÂÀ» ºÎÀÎÇϰí Á÷¾÷Çõ¸í°¡¿¡
ÀÇÇÑ Ã¼°èÀûÀÎ Áöµµ¸¦ ¿ª¼³ÇßÀ¸¸ç, ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿ª»çÀÌ·ÐÀ»
»õ·ÎÀÌ ÇØ¼®ÇØ Àü±Ù´ë»çȸ¿¡¼ÀÇ Çõ¸í °¡´É¼ºÀ» ¹Þ¾Æµé¿´´Ù.
'¸¶¸£Å©½º-·¹´ÑÁÖÀÇ'¶õ ÀüÅë ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ¿Í È¿À²ÀûÀÎ
´çÁ¶Á÷ÀÇ °áÇÕÀ» ÀǹÌÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ÇÑÆí ¿ÀÅä ¹Ù¿ì¾î°¡
ÁÖµµÇÏ´Â ¿À½ºÆ®¸®¾Æ ÇÐÆÄ´Â ±Ø´ÜÀûÀÎ °è±ÞÅõÀïÀ» °í¼öÇÏ´Â
±ÞÁø Çõ¸í¼¼·ÂÀÇ ºñÀ±¸®¼º¿¡ ¹Ý±â¸¦ µé°í »çȸÀû ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀÇ
º»¿¬ÀÇ Àΰ£ÁÖÀÇÀû Åä´ë·Î µÇµ¹¾Æ°¥ °ÍÀ» ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¼¼°è
°¢±¹ °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÇ ½Ç»óÀº Á¤Åë ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ¿¡¼ ¹þ¾î³
¿¹°¡ ¸¹À¸¸ç Áö½ÄÀεéÀº Çö´ëÀÇ ±â°è¹®¸íÀ» ºñÆÇÇÏ´Â
µµ±¸·Î¼ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀû ½Ã°¢µéÀ» ÀÀ¿ëÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù.
½ÇÁ¸ÁÖÀÇ Ã¶Çп¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ÀÌ·ÐÀ» À¶ÇÕ½ÃŲ »ç¸£Æ®¸£ÀÇ
¡´º¯Áõ¹ý ºñÆÇ Critique de la raison dialectique¡µ(1960)Àº ÈÄÀÚÀÇ
´ëÇ¥ÀûÀÎ ¿¹°¡ µÉ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù.
¡¡ |