¡¡

Jesusi.com Homepage

¡¡

¡¡

 °Ô½ÃÆÇ  °Ë»ö  ÀÚ·á½Ç  »çÀÌÆ®¸Ê  ¿¹¼ö¿Í³ª?

¡¡
Philosophy 

öÇÐ - ÁöÇýÀÇ Å½±¸

Marx, Karl

¸¶¸£Å©½º

¡¡

  • °ü·ÃµÈ »ç¶÷
    • ¹ÙÄí´Ñ
    • ¿¨°Ö½º
    • ÇÁ¶óÀϸ®±×¶óÆ®
    • ÇÁ·çµ¿
    • ÇÏÀ̳×
    • ÇÏÀεå¸Õ
    • Ç콺
  • ÀÌ·Ð
    • °æÁ¦ÇÐ
      • °¡Ä¡Çм³
      • °æÁ¦»çÇÐ
      • °æÁ¦ÀÌ·Ð
      • ³ëµ¿°¡Ä¡¼³
      • ÀÌÀÚÀÌ·Ð
      • ÀÓ±ÝÀÌ·Ð
      • À׿©°¡Ä¡·Ð
      • ÀÚº»ÀÌ·Ð
      • ÅäÁö±¹À¯È­·Ð
    • °æÇâ¹®ÇÐÀÇ ¿ËÈ£
    • ±³À°
      • ³ëÀÛ±³À°
      • »çȸÁÖÀÇ ±³À°
    • »çȸ°úÇÐÀû¡¤Ã¶ÇÐÀû ÀÌ·Ð
      • °æÁ¦Ã¶ÇÐ
      • °è±Þ °³³ä
      • °è±Þ ¾ø´Â »çȸ
      • °ø»êÁÖÀÇ ÀÌ·Ð
      • °ø»óÀû »çȸÁÖÀÇ
      • ±¹°¡
      • ±Ù´ëÈ­
      • ´ë»óÈ­
      • µµ½Ãºó¹Î
      • ¸ð¼ø
      • ¹«½Å·Ð
      • ¹Ý¿µ·Ð
      • º¯Áõ¹ýÀû À¯¹°·Ð
      • »çȸ±¸Á¶
      • »çȸ»ç»ó
      • »çȸÁÖÀÇ
      • ¼Ò¿Ü°³³ä
      • ½Çõ
      • ¿ª»çÀû À¯¹°·Ð
      • À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â
      • Àΰ£ 
      • ÀüÀï
      • Á¤Ä¡
      • Á¾±³
      • ÃÑü¼º
      • Çì°ÖÀÇ ¹ýöÇÐ
      • Çõ¸í
  • Ȱµ¿
    • °íŸ °­·É
    • <ÀÚº»·Ð>
    • Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î

1 Introduction

Karl Marx, revolutionary, sociologist, historian, and economist, was the author (with Friedrich Engels) of Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei (1848), commonly known as The Communist Manifesto, the most celebrated pamphlet in the history of the socialist movement, as well as of its most important book, Das Kapital. These writings and others by Marx and Engels form the basis of the body of thought and belief known as Marxism.

This article deals with Marx's life, his thinking, his accomplishments, and the development of Marxist theory. See the articles SOCIALISM and COMMUNISM for full treatment of those ideologies.

2 Life and works of Marx

 

2.1 EARLY YEARS

Karl Heinrich Marx was born on May 5, 1818, in the city of Trier in the Rhine province of Prussia, now in Germany. He was the oldest surviving boy of nine children. His father, Heinrich, a successful lawyer, was a man of the Enlightenment, devoted to Kant and Voltaire, who took part in agitations for a constitution in Prussia. His mother, born Henrietta Pressburg, was from Holland. Both parents were Jewish and were descended from a long line of rabbis, but, a year or so before Karl was born, his father--probably because his professional career required it--was baptized in the Evangelical Established Church. Karl was baptized when he was six years old. Although as a youth Karl was influenced less by religion than by the critical, sometimes radical social policies of the Enlightenment, his Jewish background exposed him to prejudice and discrimination that may have led him to question the role of religion in society and contributed to his desire for social change.

Marx was educated from 1830 to 1835 at the high school in Trier. Suspected of harbouring liberal teachers and pupils, the school was under police surveillance. Marx's writings during this period exhibited a spirit of Christian devotion and a longing for self-sacrifice on behalf of humanity. In October 1835 he matriculated at the University of Bonn. The courses he attended were exclusively in the humanities, in such subjects as Greek and Roman mythology and the history of art. He participated in customary student activities, fought a duel, and spent a day in jail for being drunk and disorderly. He presided at the Tavern Club, which was at odds with the more aristocratic student associations, and joined a poets' club that included some political activists. A politically rebellious student culture was, indeed, part of life at Bonn. Many students had been arrested; some were still being expelled in Marx's time, particularly as a result of an effort by students to disrupt a session of the Federal Diet at Frankfurt. Marx, however, left Bonn after a year and in October 1836 enrolled at the University of Berlin to study law and philosophy.

Marx's crucial experience at Berlin was his introduction to Hegel's philosophy, regnant there, and his adherence to the Young Hegelians. At first he felt a repugnance toward Hegel's doctrines; when Marx fell sick it was partially, as he wrote his father, "from intense vexation at having to make an idol of a view I detested." The Hegelian pressure in the revolutionary student culture was powerful, however, and Marx joined a society called the Doctor Club, whose members were intensely involved in the new literary and philosophical movement. Their chief figure was Bruno Bauer, a young lecturer in theology, who was developing the idea that the Christian Gospels were a record not of history but of human fantasies arising from emotional needs and that Jesus had not been a historical person. Marx enrolled in a course of lectures given by Bauer on the prophet Isaiah. Bauer taught that a new social catastrophe "more tremendous" than that of the advent of Christianity was in the making. The Young Hegelians began moving rapidly toward atheism and also talked vaguely of political action.

The Prussian government, fearful of the subversion latent in the Young Hegelians, soon undertook to drive them from the universities. Bauer was dismissed from his post in 1839. Marx's "most intimate friend" of this period, Adolph Rutenberg, an older journalist who had served a prison sentence for his political radicalism, pressed for a deeper social involvement. By 1841 the Young Hegelians had become left republicans. Marx's studies, meanwhile, were lagging. Urged by his friends, he submitted a doctoral dissertation to the university at Jena, which was known to be lax in its academic requirements, and received his degree in April 1841. His thesis analyzed in a Hegelian fashion the difference between the natural philosophies of Democritus and Epicurus. More distinctively, it sounded a note of Promethean defiance: (see also Index: Hegelianism)

Philosophy makes no secret of it. Prometheus' admission: "In sooth all gods I hate," is its own admission, its own motto against all gods, . . . Prometheus is the noblest saint and martyr in the calendar of philosophy.

In 1841 Marx, together with other Young Hegelians, was much influenced by the publication of Das Wesen des Christentums (1841; The Essence of Christianity) by Ludwig Feuerbach. Its author, to Marx's mind, successfully criticized Hegel, an idealist who believed that matter or existence was inferior to and dependent upon mind or spirit, from the opposite, or materialist, standpoint, showing how the "Absolute Spirit" was a projection of "the real man standing on the foundation of nature." Henceforth Marx's philosophical efforts were toward a combination of Hegel's dialectic--the idea that all things are in a continual process of change resulting from the conflicts between their contradictory aspects--with Feuerbach's materialism, which placed material conditions above ideas. (see also Index: dialectical materialism)

In January 1842 Marx began contributing to a newspaper newly founded in Cologne, the Rheinische Zeitung. It was the liberal democratic organ of a group of young merchants, bankers, and industrialists; Cologne was the centre of the most industrially advanced section of Prussia. To this stage of Marx's life belongs an essay on the freedom of the press. Since he then took for granted the existence of absolute moral standards and universal principles of ethics, he condemned censorship as a moral evil that entailed spying into people's minds and hearts and assigned to weak and malevolent mortals powers that presupposed an omniscient mind. He believed that censorship could have only evil consequences.

On Oct. 15, 1842, Marx became editor of the Rheinische Zeitung. As such, he was obliged to write editorials on a variety of social and economic issues, ranging from the housing of the Berlin poor and the theft by peasants of wood from the forests to the new phenomenon of communism. He found Hegelian idealism of little use in these matters. At the same time he was becoming estranged from his Hegelian friends for whom shocking the bourgeois was a sufficient mode of social activity. Marx, friendly at this time to the "liberal-minded practical men" who were "struggling step-by-step for freedom within constitutional limits," succeeded in trebling his newspaper's circulation and making it a leading journal in Prussia. Nevertheless, Prussian authorities suspended it for being too outspoken, and Marx agreed to coedit with the liberal Hegelian Arnold Ruge a new review, the Deutsch-französische Jahrbücher ("German-French Yearbooks"), which was to be published in Paris.

First, however, in June 1843 Marx, after an engagement of seven years, married Jenny von Westphalen. Jenny was an attractive, intelligent, and much-admired woman, four years older than Karl; she came of a family of military and administrative distinction. Her half-brother later became a highly reactionary Prussian minister of the interior. Her father, a follower of the French socialist Saint-Simon, was fond of Karl, though others in her family opposed the marriage. Marx's father also feared that Jenny was destined to become a sacrifice to the demon that possessed his son.

Four months after their marriage, the young couple moved to Paris, which was then the centre of socialist thought and of the more extreme sects that went under the name of communism. There, Marx first became a revolutionary and a communist and began to associate with communist societies of French and German workingmen. Their ideas were, in his view, "utterly crude and unintelligent," but their character moved him: "The brotherhood of man is no mere phrase with them, but a fact of life, and the nobility of man shines upon us from their work-hardened bodies," he wrote in his so-called "Ökonomisch-philosophische Manuskripte aus dem Jahre 1844" (written in 1844; Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 [1959]). (These manuscripts were not published for some 100 years, but they are influential because they show the humanist background to Marx's later historical and economic theories.)

The "German-French Yearbooks" proved short-lived, but through their publication Marx befriended Friedrich Engels, a contributor who was to become his lifelong collaborator, and in their pages appeared Marx's article "Zur Kritik der Hegelschen Rechtsphilosophie" ( "Toward the Critique of the Hegelian Philosophy of Right") with its oft-quoted assertion that religion is the "opium of the people." It was there, too, that he first raised the call for an "uprising of the proletariat" to realize the conceptions of philosophy. Once more, however, the Prussian government intervened against Marx. He was expelled from France and left for Brussels--followed by Engels--in February 1845. That year in Belgium he renounced his Prussian nationality.

2.2 BRUSSELS PERIOD

The next two years in Brussels saw the deepening of Marx's collaboration with Engels. Engels had seen at firsthand in Manchester, Eng., where a branch factory of his father's textile firm was located, all the depressing aspects of the Industrial Revolution. He had also been a Young Hegelian and had been converted to communism by Moses Hess, who was called the "communist rabbi." In England he associated with the followers of Robert Owen. Now he and Marx, finding that they shared the same views, combined their intellectual resources and published Die heilige Familie (1845; The Holy Family), a prolix criticism of the Hegelian idealism of the theologian Bruno Bauer. Their next work, Die deutsche Ideologie (written 1845-46, published 1932; The German Ideology), contained the fullest exposition of their important materialistic conception of history, which set out to show how, historically, societies had been structured to promote the interests of the economically dominant class. But it found no publisher and remained unknown during its authors' lifetimes.

During his Brussels years, Marx developed his views and, through confrontations with the chief leaders of the working-class movement, established his intellectual standing. In 1846 he publicly excoriated the German leader Wilhelm Weitling for his moralistic appeals. Marx insisted that the stage of bourgeois society could not be skipped over; the proletariat could not just leap into communism; the workers' movement required a scientific basis, not moralistic phrases. He also polemicized against the French socialist thinker Pierre-Joseph Proudhon in Misère de la philosophie (1847; The Poverty of Philosophy), a mordant attack on Proudhon's book subtitled Philosophie de la misère (1846; The Philosophy of Poverty). Proudhon wanted to unite the best features of such contraries as competition and monopoly; he hoped to save the good features in economic institutions while eliminating the bad. Marx, however, declared that no equilibrium was possible between the antagonisms in any given economic system. Social structures were transient historic forms determined by the productive forces: "The handmill gives you society with the feudal lord; the steammill, society with the industrial capitalist." Proudhon's mode of reasoning, Marx wrote, was typical of the petty bourgeois, who failed to see the underlying laws of history.

An unusual sequence of events led Marx and Engels to write their pamphlet The Communist Manifesto. In June 1847 a secret society, the League of the Just, composed mainly of emigrant German handicraftsmen, met in London and decided to formulate a political program. They sent a representative to Marx to ask him to join the league; Marx overcame his doubts and, with Engels, joined the organization, which thereupon changed its name to the Communist League and enacted a democratic constitution. Entrusted with the task of composing their program, Marx and Engels worked from the middle of December 1847 to the end of January 1848. The London Communists were already impatiently threatening Marx with disciplinary action when he sent them the manuscript; they promptly adopted it as their manifesto. It enunciated the proposition that all history had hitherto been a history of class struggles, summarized in pithy form the materialist conception of history worked out in The German Ideology, and asserted that the forthcoming victory of the proletariat would put an end to class society forever. It mercilessly criticized all forms of socialism founded on philosophical "cobwebs" such as "alienation." It rejected the avenue of "social Utopias," small experiments in community, as deadening the class struggle and therefore as being "reactionary sects." It set forth 10 immediate measures as first steps toward communism, ranging from a progressive income tax and the abolition of inheritances to free education for all children. It closed with the words, "The proletarians have nothing to lose but their chains. They have a world to win. Workingmen of all countries, unite!"

Revolution suddenly erupted in Europe in the first months of 1848, in France, Italy, and Austria. Marx had been invited to Paris by a member of the provisional government just in time to avoid expulsion by the Belgian government. As the revolution gained in Austria and Germany, Marx returned to the Rhineland. In Cologne he advocated a policy of coalition between the working class and the democratic bourgeoisie, opposing for this reason the nomination of independent workers' candidates for the Frankfurt Assembly and arguing strenuously against the program for proletarian revolution advocated by the leaders of the Workers' Union. He concurred in Engels' judgment that The Communist Manifesto should be shelved and the Communist League disbanded. Marx pressed his policy through the pages of the Neue Rheinische Zeitung, newly founded in June 1849, urging a constitutional democracy and war with Russia. When the more revolutionary leader of the Workers' Union, Andreas Gottschalk, was arrested, Marx supplanted him and organized the first Rhineland Democratic Congress in August 1848. When the king of Prussia dissolved the Prussian Assembly in Berlin, Marx called for arms and men to help the resistance. Bourgeois liberals withdrew their support from Marx's newspaper, and he himself was indicted on several charges, including advocacy of the nonpayment of taxes. In his trial he defended himself with the argument that the crown was engaged in making an unlawful counterrevolution. The jury acquitted him unanimously and with thanks. Nevertheless, as the last hopeless fighting flared in Dresden and Baden, Marx was ordered banished as an alien on May 16, 1849. The final issue of his newspaper, printed in red, caused a great sensation. (see also Index: "Neue Rheinische Zeitung")

2.3 EARLY YEARS IN LONDON

Expelled once more from Paris, Marx went to London in August 1849. It was to be his home for the rest of his life. Chagrined by the failure of his own tactics of collaboration with the liberal bourgeoisie, he rejoined the Communist League in London and for about a year advocated a bolder revolutionary policy. An "Address of the Central Committee to the Communist League," written with Engels in March 1850, urged that in future revolutionary situations they struggle to make the revolution "permanent" by avoiding subservience to the bourgeois party and by setting up "their own revolutionary workers' governments" alongside any new bourgeois one. Marx hoped that the economic crisis would shortly lead to a revival of the revolutionary movement; when this hope faded, he came into conflict once more with those whom he called "the alchemists of the revolution," such as August von Willich, a communist who proposed to hasten the advent of revolution by undertaking direct revolutionary ventures. Such persons, Marx wrote in September 1850, substitute "idealism for materialism" and regard

pure will as the motive power of revolution instead of actual conditions. While we say to the workers: "You have got to go through fifteen, twenty, fifty years of civil wars and national wars not merely in order to change your conditions but in order to change yourselves and become qualified for political power," you on the contrary tell them, "We must achieve power immediately."

The militant faction in turn ridiculed Marx for being a revolutionary who limited his activity to lectures on political economy to the Communist Workers' Educational Union. The upshot was that Marx gradually stopped attending meetings of the London Communists. In 1852 he devoted himself intensely to working for the defense of 11 communists arrested and tried in Cologne on charges of revolutionary conspiracy and wrote a pamphlet on their behalf. The same year he also published, in a German-American periodical, his essay "Der Achtzehnte Brumaire des Louis Napoleon" (The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte), with its acute analysis of the formation of a bureaucratic absolutist state with the support of the peasant class. In other respects the next 12 years were, in Marx's words, years of "isolation" both for him and for Engels in his Manchester factory.

From 1850 to 1864 Marx lived in material misery and spiritual pain. His funds were gone, and except on one occasion he could not bring himself to seek paid employment. In March 1850 he and his wife and four small children were evicted and their belongings seized. Several of his children died--including a son Guido, "a sacrifice to bourgeois misery," and a daughter Franziska, for whom his wife rushed about frantically trying to borrow money for a coffin. For six years the family lived in two small rooms in Soho, often subsisting on bread and potatoes. The children learned to lie to the creditors: "Mr. Marx ain't upstairs." Once he had to escape them by fleeing to Manchester. His wife suffered breakdowns.

During all these years Engels loyally contributed to Marx's financial support. The sums were not large at first, for Engels was only a clerk in the firm of Ermen and Engels at Manchester. Later, however, in 1864, when he became a partner, his subventions were generous. Marx was proud of Engels' friendship and would tolerate no criticism of him. Bequests from the relatives of Marx's wife and from Marx's friend Wilhelm Wolff also helped to alleviate their economic distress.

Marx had one relatively steady source of earned income in the United States. On the invitation of Charles A. Dana, managing editor of The New York Tribune, he became in 1851 its European correspondent. The newspaper, edited by Horace Greeley, had sympathies for Fourierism, a Utopian socialist system developed by the French theorist Charles Fourier. From 1851 to 1862 Marx contributed close to 500 articles and editorials (Engels providing about a fourth of them). He ranged over the whole political universe, analyzing social movements and agitations from India and China to Britain and Spain.

In 1859 Marx published his first book on economic theory, Zur Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy). In its preface he again summarized his materialistic conception of history, his theory that the course of history is dependent on economic developments. At this time, however, Marx regarded his studies in economic and social history at the British Museum as his main task. He was busy producing the drafts of his magnum opus, which was to be published later as Das Kapital. Some of these drafts, including the Outlines and the Theories of Surplus Value, are important in their own right and were published after Marx's death.

2.4 ROLE IN THE FIRST INTERNATIONAL

Marx's political isolation ended in 1864 with the founding of the International Working Men's Association. Although he was neither its founder nor its head, he soon became its leading spirit. Its first public meeting, called by English trade union leaders and French workers' representatives, took place at St. Martin's Hall in London on Sept. 28, 1864. Marx, who had been invited through a French intermediary to attend as a representative of the German workers, sat silently on the platform. A committee was set up to produce a program and a constitution for the new organization. After various drafts had been submitted that were felt to be unsatisfactory, Marx, serving on a subcommittee, drew upon his immense journalistic experience. His "Address and the Provisional Rules of the International Working Men's Association," unlike his other writings, stressed the positive achievements of the cooperative movement and of parliamentary legislation; the gradual conquest of political power would enable the British proletariat to extend these achievements on a national scale.

As a member of the organization's General Council, and corresponding secretary for Germany, Marx was henceforth assiduous in attendance at its meetings, which were sometimes held several times a week. For several years he showed a rare diplomatic tact in composing differences among various parties, factions, and tendencies. The International grew in prestige and membership, its numbers reaching perhaps 800,000 in 1869. It was successful in several interventions on behalf of European trade unions engaged in struggles with employers.

In 1870, however, Marx was still unknown as a European political personality; it was the Paris Commune that made him into an international figure, "the best calumniated and most menaced man of London," as he wrote. When the Franco-German War broke out in 1870, Marx and Engels disagreed with followers in Germany who refused to vote in the Reichstag in favour of the war. The General Council declared that "on the German side the war was a war of defence." After the defeat of the French armies, however, they felt that the German terms amounted to aggrandizement at the expense of the French people. When an insurrection broke out in Paris and the Paris Commune was proclaimed, Marx gave it his unswerving support. On May 30, 1871, after the Commune had been crushed, he hailed it in a famous address entitled Civil War in France:

History has no comparable example of such greatness. . . . Its martyrs are enshrined forever in the great heart of the working class.

In Engels' judgment, the Paris Commune was history's first example of the "dictatorship of the proletariat." Marx's name, as the leader of The First International and author of the notorious Civil War, became synonymous throughout Europe with the revolutionary spirit symbolized by the Paris Commune.

The advent of the Commune, however, exacerbated the antagonisms within the International Working Men's Association and thus brought about its downfall. English trade unionists such as George Odger, former president of the General Council, opposed Marx's support of the Paris Commune. The Reform Bill of 1867, which had enfranchised the British working class, had opened vast opportunities for political action by the trade unions. English labour leaders found they could make many practical advances by cooperating with the Liberal Party and, regarding Marx's rhetoric as an encumbrance, resented his charge that they had "sold themselves" to the Liberals.

A left opposition also developed under the leadership of the famed Russian revolutionary Mikhail Alexandrovich Bakunin. A veteran of tsarist prisons and Siberian exile, Bakunin could move men by his oratory, which one listener compared to "a raging storm with lightning, flashes and thunderclaps, and a roaring as of lions." Bakunin admired Marx's intellect but could hardly forget that Marx had published a report in 1848 charging him with being a Russian agent. He felt that Marx was a German authoritarian and an arrogant Jew who wanted to transform the General Council into a personal dictatorship over the workers. He strongly opposed several of Marx's theories, especially Marx's support of the centralized structure of the International, Marx's view that the proletariat class should act as a political party against prevailing parties but within the existing parliamentary system, and Marx's belief that the proletariat, after it had overthrown the bourgeois state, should establish its own regime. To Bakunin, the mission of the revolutionary was destruction; he looked to the Russian peasantry, with its propensities for violence and its uncurbed revolutionary instincts, rather than to the effete, civilized workers of the industrial countries. The students, he hoped, would be the officers of the revolution. He acquired followers, mostly young men, in Italy, Switzerland, and France, and he organized a secret society, the International Alliance of Social Democracy, which in 1869 challenged the hegemony of the General Council at the congress in Basel, Switz. Marx, however, had already succeeded in preventing its admission as an organized body into the International.

To the Bakuninists, the Paris Commune was a model of revolutionary direct action and a refutation of what they considered to be Marx's "authoritarian communism." Bakunin began organizing sections of the International for an attack on the alleged dictatorship of Marx and the General Council. Marx in reply publicized Bakunin's embroilment with an unscrupulous Russian student leader, Sergey Gennadiyevich Nechayev, who had practiced blackmail and murder.

Without a supporting right wing and with the anarchist left against him, Marx feared losing control of the International to Bakunin. He also wanted to return to his studies and to finish Das Kapital. At the congress of the International at The Hague in 1872, the only one he ever attended, Marx managed to defeat the Bakuninists. Then, to the consternation of the delegates, Engels moved that the seat of the General Council be transferred from London to New York City. The Bakuninists were expelled, but the International languished and was finally disbanded in Philadelphia in 1876.

2.5 LAST YEARS

During the next and last decade of his life, Marx's creative energies declined. He was beset by what he called "chronic mental depression," and his life turned inward toward his family. He was unable to complete any substantial work, though he still read widely and undertook to learn Russian. He became crotchety in his political opinions. When his own followers and those of the German revolutionary Ferdinand Lassalle, a rival who believed that socialist goals should be achieved through cooperation with the state, coalesced in 1875 to found the German Social Democratic Party, Marx wrote a caustic criticism of their program (the so-called Gotha Program), claiming that it made too many compromises with the status quo. The German leaders put his objections aside and tried to mollify him personally. Increasingly, he looked to a European war for the overthrow of Russian tsarism, the mainstay of reaction, hoping that this would revive the political energies of the working classes. He was moved by what he considered to be the selfless courage of the Russian terrorists who assassinated the tsar, Alexander II, in 1881; he felt this to be "a historically inevitable means of action."

Despite Marx's withdrawal from active politics, he still retained what Engels called his "peculiar influence" on the leaders of working-class and socialist movements. In 1879, when the French Socialist Workers' Federation was founded, its leader Jules Guesde went to London to consult with Marx, who dictated the preamble of its program and shaped much of its content. In 1881 Henry Mayers Hyndman in his England for All drew heavily on his conversations with Marx but angered him by being afraid to acknowledge him by name.

During his last years Marx spent much time at health resorts and even traveled to Algiers. He was broken by the death of his wife on Dec. 2, 1881, and of his eldest daughter, Jenny Longuet, on Jan. 11, 1883. He died in London, evidently of a lung abscess, on March 14, 1883.

2.6 CHARACTER AND SIGNIFICANCE

At Marx's funeral in Highgate Cemetery, Engels declared that Marx had made two great discoveries, the law of development of human history and the law of motion of bourgeois society. But "Marx was before all else a revolutionist." He was "the best-hated and most-calumniated man of his time," yet he also died "beloved, revered and mourned by millions of revolutionary fellow-workers."

The contradictory emotions Marx engendered are reflected in the sometimes conflicting aspects of his character. Marx was a combination of the Promethean rebel and the rigorous intellectual. He gave most persons an impression of intellectual arrogance. A Russian writer, Pavel Annenkov, who observed Marx in debate in 1846 recalled that "he spoke only in the imperative, brooking no contradiction," and seemed to be "the personification of a democratic dictator such as might appear before one in moments of fantasy." But Marx obviously felt uneasy before mass audiences and avoided the atmosphere of factional controversies at congresses. He went to no demonstrations, his wife remarked, and rarely spoke at public meetings. He kept away from the congresses of the International where the rival socialist groups debated important resolutions. He was a "small groups" man, most at home in the atmosphere of the General Council or on the staff of a newspaper, where his character could impress itself forcefully on a small body of coworkers. At the same time he avoided meeting distinguished scholars with whom he might have discussed questions of economics and sociology on a footing of intellectual equality. Despite his broad intellectual sweep, he was prey to obsessive ideas such as that the British foreign minister, Lord Palmerston, was an agent of the Russian government. He was determined not to let bourgeois society make "a money-making machine" out of him, yet he submitted to living on the largess of Engels and the bequests of relatives. He remained the eternal student in his personal habits and way of life, even to the point of joining two friends in a students' prank during which they systematically broke four or five streetlamps in a London street and then fled from the police. He was a great reader of novels, especially those of Sir Walter Scott and Balzac; and the family made a cult of Shakespeare. He was an affectionate father, saying that he admired Jesus for his love of children, but sacrificed the lives and health of his own. Of his seven children, three daughters grew to maturity. His favourite daughter, Eleanor, worried him with her nervous, brooding, emotional character and her desire to be an actress. Another shadow was cast on Marx's domestic life by the birth to their loyal servant, Helene Demuth, of an illegitimate son, Frederick; Engels as he was dying disclosed to Eleanor that Marx had been the father. Above all, Marx was a fighter, willing to sacrifice anything in the battle for his conception of a better society. He regarded struggle as the law of life and existence.

The influence of Marx's ideas has been enormous. Marx's masterpiece, Das Kapital, the "Bible of the working class," as it was officially described in a resolution of the International Working Men's Association, was published in 1867 in Berlin and received a second edition in 1873. Only the first volume was completed and published in Marx's lifetime. The second and third volumes, unfinished by Marx, were edited by Engels and published in 1885 and 1894. The economic categories he employed were those of the classical British economics of David Ricardo; but Marx used them in accordance with his dialectical method to argue that bourgeois society, like every social organism, must follow its inevitable path of development. Through the working of such immanent tendencies as the declining rate of profit, capitalism would die and be replaced by another, higher, society. The most memorable pages in Das Kapital are the descriptive passages, culled from Parliamentary Blue Books, on the misery of the English working class. Marx believed that this misery would increase, while at the same time the monopoly of capital would become a fetter upon production until finally "the knell of capitalist private property sounds. The expropriators are expropriated."

Marx never claimed to have discovered the existence of classes and class struggles in modern society. "Bourgeois" historians, he acknowledged, had described them long before he had. He did claim, however, to have proved that each phase in the development of production was associated with a corresponding class structure and that the struggle of classes led necessarily to the dictatorship of the proletariat, ushering in the advent of a classless society. Marx took up the very different versions of socialism current in the early 19th century and welded them together into a doctrine that continued to be the dominant version of socialism for half a century after his death. His emphasis on the influence of economic structure on historical development has proved to be of lasting significance.

Although Marx stressed economic issues in his writings, his major impact has been in the fields of sociology and history. Marx's most important contribution to sociological theory was his general mode of analysis, the "dialectical" model, which regards every social system as having within it immanent forces that give rise to "contradictions" (disequilibria) that can be resolved only by a new social system. Neo-Marxists, who no longer accept the economic reasoning in Das Kapital, are still guided by this model in their approach to capitalist society. In this sense, Marx's mode of analysis, like those of Thomas Malthus, Herbert Spencer, or Vilfredo Pareto, has become one of the theoretical structures that are the heritage of the social scientist. (L.S.F./D.T.McL.)

3 Marxism

The term Marxism is used in a number of different ways. In its most essential meaning it refers to the thought of Karl Marx but is usually extended to include that of his friend and collaborator Friedrich Engels. There is also Marxism as it has been understood and practiced by the various socialist movements, particularly before 1914. Then there is Soviet Marxism as worked out by Lenin and modified by Stalin, which under the name of Marxism-Leninism became the doctrine of the communist parties set up after the Russian Revolution. Offshoots of this include Marxism as interpreted by the anti-Stalinist Leon Trotsky and his followers, Mao Zedong's (Mao Tse-tung's) Chinese variant of Marxism-Leninism, and various Third World Marxisms. There are also the post-World War II nondogmatic Marxisms that have modified Marx's thought with borrowings from modern philosophies, principally from those of Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger but also from Sigmund Freud and others.

3.1 THE THOUGHT OF KARL MARX

The written work of Marx cannot be reduced to a philosophy, much less to a philosophical system. The whole of his work is a radical critique of philosophy, especially of Hegel's idealist system and of the philosophies of the left and right post-Hegelians. It is not, however, a mere denial of those philosophies. Marx declared that philosophy must become reality. One could no longer be content with interpreting the world; one must be concerned with transforming it, which meant transforming both the world itself and men's consciousness of it. This, in turn, required a critique of experience together with a critique of ideas. In fact, Marx believed that all knowledge involved a critique of ideas. He was not an empiricist. Rather, his work teems with concepts (appropriation, alienation, praxis, creative labour, value, etc.) that he had inherited from earlier philosophers and economists, including Hegel, Johann Fichte, Kant, Adam Smith, David Ricardo, and John Stuart Mill. What uniquely characterizes the thought of Marx is that, instead of making abstract affirmations about a whole group of problems such as man, knowledge, matter, and nature, he examines each problem in its dynamic relation to the others and, above all, tries to relate them to historical, social, political, and economic realities. (see also Index: Hegelianism)

3.1.1 Historical materialism.

In 1859, in the preface to his Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, Marx wrote that the hypothesis that had served him as the basis for his analysis of society could be briefly formulated as follows:

In the social production that men carry on, they enter into definite relations that are indispensable and independent of their will, relations of production which correspond to a definite stage of development of their material forces of production. The sum total of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political superstructure, and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production in material life determines the general character of the social, political, and intellectual processes of life. It is not the consciousness of men which determines their existence; it is on the contrary their social existence which determines their consciousness.

Raised to the level of historical law, this hypothesis was subsequently called historical materialism. Marx applied it to capitalist society, both in The Communist Manifesto and Das Kapital and in other writings. Although Marx reflected upon his working hypothesis for many years, he did not formulate it in a very exact manner: different expressions served him for identical realities. If one takes the text literally, social reality is structured in the following way:

1. Underlying everything as the real basis of society is the economic structure (what in late 20th-century language is sometimes called the infrastructure). This structure includes (a) the "material forces of production," that is, the labour and means of production, and (b) the overall "relations of production," or the social and political arrangements that regulate production and distribution. Although Marx stated that there is a correspondence between the "material forces" of production and the indispensable "relations" of production, he never made himself clear on the nature of the correspondence, a fact that was to be the source of differing interpretations among his later followers.

2. Above the economic structure rises the superstructure consisting of legal and political "forms of social consciousness" that correspond to the economic structure. Marx says nothing about the nature of this correspondence between ideological forms and economic structure, except that through the ideological forms men become conscious of the conflict within the economic structure between the material forces of production and the existing relations of production expressed in the legal property relations. In other words, "The sum total of the forces of production accessible to men determines the condition of society" and is at the base of society. "The social structure and the state issue continually from the life processes of definite individuals . . . as they are in reality, that is acting and materially producing." The political relations that men establish among themselves are dependent on material production, as are the legal relations. This foundation of the social on the economic is not an incidental point: it colours Marx's whole analysis. It is found in Das Kapital as well as in The German Ideology and the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844.

3.1.2 Analysis of society.

To go directly to the heart of the work of Marx, one must focus on his concrete program for man. This is just as important for an understanding of Marx as are The Communist Manifesto and Das Kapital. Marx's interpretation of man begins with human need. "Man," he wrote in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844,

is first of all a natural being. As a natural being and a living natural being, he is endowed on the one hand with natural powers, vital powers . . . ; these powers exist in him as aptitudes, instincts. On the other hand, as an objective, natural, physical, sensitive being, he is a suffering, dependent and limited being . . . , that is, the objects of his instincts exist outside him, independent of him, but are the objects of his need, indispensable and essential for the realization and confirmation of his substantial powers.

The point of departure of human history is therefore living man, who seeks to satisfy certain primary needs. "The first historical fact is the production of the means to satisfy these needs." This satisfaction, in turn, opens the way for new needs. Human activity is thus essentially a struggle with nature that must furnish man with the means of satisfying his needs: drink, food, clothing, the development of his powers and then of his intellectual and artistic abilities. In this undertaking, man discovers himself as a productive being who humanizes himself by his labour. Furthermore, man humanizes nature while he naturalizes himself. By his creative activity, by his labour, he realizes his identity with the nature that he masters, while at the same time he achieves free consciousness. Born of nature man becomes fully human by opposing it. Becoming aware in his struggle against nature of what separates him from it, man finds the conditions of his fulfillment, of the realization of his true stature. The dawning of consciousness is inseparable from struggle. By appropriating all the creative energies, he discovers that "all that is called history is nothing else than the process of creating man through human labour, the becoming of nature for man. Man has thus evident and irrefutable proof of his own creation by himself." Understood in its universal dimension, human activity reveals that "for man, man is the supreme being." It is thus vain to speak of God, creation, and metaphysical problems. Fully naturalized, man is sufficient unto himself: he has recaptured the fullness of man in his full liberty.

Living in a capitalist society, however, man is not truly free. He is an alienated being; he is not at home in his world. The idea of alienation, which Marx takes from Hegel and Feuerbach, plays a fundamental role in the whole of his written work, starting with the writings of his youth and continuing through Das Kapital. In the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts the alienation of labour is seen to spring from the fact that the more the worker produces the less he has to consume, and the more values he creates the more he devalues himself, because his product and his labour are estranged from him. The life of the worker depends on things that he has created but that are not his, so that, instead of finding his rightful existence through his labour, he loses it in this world of things that are external to him: no work, no pay. Under these conditions, labour denies the fullness of concrete man. "The generic being (Gattungwesen) of man, nature as well as his intellectual faculties, is transformed into a being which is alien to him, into a means of his individual existence." Nature, his body, his spiritual essence become alien to him. "Man is made alien to man." When carried to its highest stage of development, private property becomes "the product of alienated labour . . . the means by which labour alienates itself (and) the realization of this alienation." It is also at the same time "the tangible material expression of alienated human life." (see also Index: production)

Although there is no evidence that Marx ever disclaimed this anthropological analysis of alienated labour, starting with The German Ideology, the historical, social, and economic causes of the alienation of labour are given increasing emphasis, especially in Das Kapital. Alienated labour is seen as the consequence of market product, the division of labour, and the division of society into antagonistic classes. As producers in society, men create goods only by their labour. These goods are exchangeable. Their value is the average amount of social labour spent to produce them. The alienation of the worker takes on its full dimension in that system of market production in which part of the value of the goods produced by the worker is taken away from him and transformed into surplus value, which the capitalist privately appropriates. Market production also intensifies the alienation of labour by encouraging specialization, piecework, and the setting up of large enterprises. Thus the labour power of the worker is used along with that of others in a combination whose significance he is ignorant of, both individually and socially. In thus losing their quality as human products, the products of labour become fetishes, that is, alien and oppressive realities to which both the man who possesses them privately and the man who is deprived of them submit themselves. In the market economy, this submission to things is obscured by the fact that the exchange of goods is expressed in money. (see also Index: labour theory of value)

This fundamental economic alienation is accompanied by secondary political and ideological alienations, which offer a distorted representation of and an illusory justification of a world in which the relations of men with one another are also distorted. The ideas that men form are closely bound up with their material activity and their material relations: "The act of making representations, of thinking, the spiritual intercourse of men, seem to be the direct emanation of their material relations." This is true of all human activity: political, intellectual, or spiritual. "Men produce their representations and their ideas, but it is as living men, men acting as they are determined by a definite development of their powers of production." Law, morality, metaphysics, and religion do not have a history of their own. "Men developing their material production modify together with their real existence their ways of thinking and the products of their ways of thinking." In other words, "It is not consciousness which determines existence, it is existence which determines consciousness."

In bourgeois, capitalist society man is divided into political citizen and economic man. This duality represents man's political alienation, which is further intensified by the functioning of the bourgeois state. From this study of society at the beginning of the 19th century, Marx came to see the state as the instrument through which the propertied class dominated other classes.

Ideological alienation, for Marx, takes different forms, appearing in economic, philosophical, and legal theories. Marx undertook a lengthy critique of the first in Das Kapital and of the second in The German Ideology. But ideological alienation expresses itself supremely in religion. Taking up the ideas about religion that were current in left post-Hegelian circles, together with the thought of Feuerbach, Marx considered religion to be a product of man's consciousness. It is a reflection of the situation of a man who "either has not conquered himself or has already lost himself again" (man in the world of private property). It is "an opium for the people." Unlike Feuerbach, Marx believed that religion would disappear only with changes in society.

3.1.3 Analysis of the economy.

Marx analyzed the market economy system in Das Kapital. In this work he borrows most of the categories of the classical English economists Smith and Ricardo but adapts them and introduces new concepts such as that of surplus value. One of the distinguishing marks of Das Kapital is that in it Marx studies the economy as a whole and not in one or another of its aspects. His analysis is based on the idea that man is a productive being and that all economic value comes from human labour. The system he analyzes is principally that of mid-19th-century England. It is a system of private enterprise and competition that arose in the 16th century from the development of sea routes, international trade, and colonialism. Its rise had been facilitated by changes in the forces of production (the division of labour and the concentration of workshops), the adoption of mechanization, and technical progress. The wealth of the societies that brought this economy into play had been acquired through an "enormous accumulation of commodities." Marx therefore begins with the study of this accumulation, analyzing the unequal exchanges that take place in the market. (see also Index: wealth and income, distribution of)

According to Marx, if the capitalist advances funds to buy cotton yarn with which to produce fabrics and sells the product for a larger sum than he paid, he is able to invest the difference in additional production. "Not only is the value advance kept in circulation, but it changes in its magnitude, adds a plus to itself, makes itself worth more, and it is this movement that transforms it into capital." The transformation, to Marx, is possible only because the capitalist has appropriated the means of production, including the labour power of the worker. Now labour power produces more than it is worth. The value of labour power is determined by the amount of labour necessary for its reproduction or, in other words, by the amount needed for the worker to subsist and beget children. But in the hands of the capitalist the labour power employed in the course of a day produces more than the value of the sustenance required by the worker and his family. The difference between the two values is appropriated by the capitalist, and it corresponds exactly to the surplus value realized by capitalists in the market. Marx is not concerned with whether in capitalist society there are sources of surplus value other than the exploitation of human labour--a fact pointed out by Joseph Schumpeter (Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy). He remains content with emphasizing this primary source:

Surplus value is produced by the employment of labour power. Capital buys the labour power and pays the wages for it. By means of his work the labourer creates new value which does not belong to him, but to the capitalist. He must work a certain time merely in order to reproduce the equivalent value of his wages. But when this equivalent value has been returned, he does not cease work, but continues to do so for some further hours. The new value which he produces during this extra time, and which exceeds in consequence the amount of his wage, constitutes surplus value.

Throughout his analysis, Marx argues that the development of capitalism is accompanied by increasing contradictions. For example, the introduction of machinery is profitable to the individual capitalist because it enables him to produce more goods at a lower cost, but new techniques are soon taken up by his competitors. The outlay for machinery grows faster than the outlay for wages. Since only labour can produce the surplus value from which profit is derived, this means that the capitalist's rate of profit on his total outlay tends to decline. Along with the declining rate of profit goes an increase in unemployment. Thus, the equilibrium of the system is precarious, subject as it is to the internal pressures resulting from its own development. Crises shake it at regular intervals, preludes to the general crisis that will sweep it away. This instability is increased by the formation of a reserve army of workers, both factory workers and peasants, whose pauperization keeps increasing. "Capitalist production develops the technique and the combination of the process of social production only by exhausting at the same time the two sources from which all wealth springs: the earth and the worker." According to the Marxist dialectic, these fundamental contradictions can only be resolved by a change from capitalism to a new system.

3.1.4 Class struggle.

Marx inherited the ideas of class and class struggle from Utopian socialism and the theories of Saint-Simon. These had been given substance by the writings of French historians such as Adolphe Thiers and François Guizot on the French Revolution of 1789. But unlike the French historians, Marx made class struggle the central fact of social evolution. "The history of all hitherto existing human society is the history of class struggles."

In Marx's view, the dialectical nature of history is expressed in class struggle. With the development of capitalism, the class struggle takes an acute form. Two basic classes, around which other less important classes are grouped, oppose each other in the capitalist system: the owners of the means of production, or bourgeoisie, and the workers, or proletariat. "The bourgeoisie produces its own grave-diggers. The fall of the bourgeoisie and the victory of the proletariat are equally inevitable" (The Communist Manifesto) because

the bourgeois relations of production are the last contradictory form of the process of social production, contradictory not in the sense of an individual contradiction, but of a contradiction that is born of the conditions of social existence of individuals; however, the forces of production which develop in the midst of bourgeois society create at the same time the material conditions for resolving this contradiction. With this social development the prehistory of human society ends.

When man has become aware of his loss, of his alienation, as a universal nonhuman situation, it will be possible for him to proceed to a radical transformation of his situation by a revolution. This revolution will be the prelude to the establishment of communism and the reign of liberty reconquered. "In the place of the old bourgeois society with its classes and its class antagonisms, there will be an association in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all."

But for Marx there are two views of revolution. One is that of a final conflagration, "a violent suppression of the old conditions of production," which occurs when the opposition between bourgeoisie and proletariat has been carried to its extreme point. This conception is set forth in a manner inspired by the Hegelian dialectic of the master and the slave, in The Holy Family. The other conception is that of a permanent revolution involving a provisional coalition between the proletariat and the petty bourgeoisie rebelling against a capitalism that is only superficially united. Once a majority has been won to the coalition, an unofficial proletarian authority constitutes itself alongside the revolutionary bourgeois authority. Its mission is the political and revolutionary education of the proletariat, gradually assuring the transfer of legal power from the revolutionary bourgeoisie to the revolutionary proletariat.

If one reads The Communist Manifesto carefully one discovers inconsistencies that indicate that Marx had not reconciled the concepts of catastrophic and of permanent revolution. Moreover, Marx never analyzed classes as specific groups of men opposing other groups of men. Depending on the writings and the periods, the number of classes varies; and unfortunately the pen fell from Marx's hand at the moment when, in Das Kapital (vol. 3), he was about to take up the question. Reading Das Kapital, one is furthermore left with an ambiguous impression with regard to the destruction of capitalism: will it be the result of the "general crisis" that Marx expects, or of the action of the conscious proletariat, or of both at once?

3.1.5 The contributions of Engels.

Engels became a communist in 1842 and discovered the proletariat of England when he took over the management of the Manchester factory belonging to his father's cotton firm. In 1844, the year he began his close association and friendship with Marx, Engels was finishing his "Umrisse zu einer Kritik der Nationalökonomie" ("Outline of a Critique of Political Economy")--a critique of Smith, Ricardo, Mill, and J.B. Say. This remarkable study contained in seminal form the critique that Marx was to make of bourgeois political economy in Das Kapital. During the first years of his stay in Manchester, Engels observed carefully the life of the workers of that great industrial centre and described it in Die Lage der arbeitenden Klassen in England (The Condition of the Working Class in England), published in 1845 in Leipzig. This work was an analysis of the evolution of industrial capitalism and its social consequences. He collaborated with Marx in the writing of The Holy Family, The German Ideology, and The Communist Manifesto. The correspondence between them is of fundamental importance for the student of Das Kapital, for it shows how Engels contributed by furnishing Marx with a great amount of technical and economic data and by criticizing the successive drafts. This collaboration lasted until Marx's death and was carried on posthumously with the publication of the manuscripts left by Marx, which Engels edited, forming volumes 2 and 3 of Das Kapital. He also wrote various articles on Marx's work.

In response to criticism of Marx's ideas by a socialist named Eugen Dühring, Engels published several articles that were collected under the title Herr Eugen Dührings Umwälzung der Wissenschaft, which appeared in 1878 (Herr Eugen Dühring's Revolution in Science [Anti-Dühring]), and an unfinished work, Dialektik und Natur (1927; Dialectics of Nature), which he had begun around 1875-76. The importance of these writings to the subsequent development of Marxism can be seen from Lenin's observation that Engels "developed, in a clear and often polemical style, the most general scientific questions and the different phenomena of the past and present according to the materialist understanding of history and the economic theory of Karl Marx." But Engels was driven to simplify problems with a view to being pedagogical; he tended to schematize and systematize things as if the fundamental questions were settled. The connections that he thus established between some of Marx's governing ideas and some of the scientific ideas of his age gave rise to the notion that there is a complete Marxist philosophy. The idea was to play a significant role in the transition of Marxism from a "critique of daily life" to an integrated doctrine in which philosophy, history, and the sciences are fused.

Anti-Dühring is of fundamental importance for it constitutes the link between Marx and certain forms of modern Marxism. It contains three parts: Philosophy, Political Economy, and Socialism. In the first, Engels attempts to establish that the natural sciences and even mathematics are dialectical, in the sense that observable reality is dialectical: the dialectical method of analysis and thought is imposed on men by the material forces with which they deal. It is thus rightly applied to the study of history and human society. "Motion, in effect, is the mode of existence of matter," Engels writes. In using materialistic dialectic to make a critique of Dühring's thesis, according to which political forces prevail over all the rest in the molding of history, Engels provides a good illustration of the materialistic idea of history, which puts the stress on the prime role of economic factors as driving forces in history. The other chapters of the section Political Economy form a very readable introduction to the principal economic ideas of Marx: value (simple and complex), labour, capital, and surplus value. The section Socialism starts by formulating anew the critique of the capitalist system as it was made in Das Kapital. At the end of the chapters devoted to production, distribution, the state, the family, and education, Engels outlines what the socialist society will be like, a society in which the notion of value has no longer anything to do with the distribution of the goods produced because all labour "becomes at once and directly social labour," and the amount of social labour that every product contains no longer needs to be ascertained by "a detour." A production plan will coordinate the economy. The division of labour and the separation of town and country will disappear with the "suppression of the capitalist character of modern industry." Thanks to the plan, industry will be located throughout the country in the collective interest, and thus the opposition between town and country will disappear--to the profit of both industry and agriculture. Finally, after the liberation of man from the condition of servitude in which the capitalist mode of production holds him, the state will also be abolished and religion will disappear by "natural death."

One of the most remarkable features of Anti-Dühring is the insistence with which Engels refuses to base socialism on absolute values. He admits only relative values, linked to historical, economic, and social conditions. Socialism cannot possibly be based on ethical principles: each epoch can only successfully carry out that of which it is capable. Marx had written this in his preface of 1859.

Karl Marx and Marxism

3.2 GERMAN MARXISM AFTER ENGELS

 

3.2.1 The work of Kautsky and Bernstein.

The theoretical leadership after Engels was taken by Karl Kautsky, editor of the official organ of the German Social Democratic Party, Die Neue Zeit. He wrote Karl Marx' ökonomische Lehren (1887; The Economic Doctrines of Karl Marx), in which the work of Marx is presented as essentially an economic theory. Kautsky reduced the ideas of Marx and Marxist historical dialectic to a kind of evolutionism. He laid stress on the increasing pauperization of the working class and on the increasing degree of capitalist concentration. While opposing all compromise with the bourgeois state, he accepted the contention that the socialist movement should support laws benefiting the workers provided that they did not reinforce the power of the state. Rejecting the idea of an alliance between the working class and the peasantry, he believed that the overthrow of the capitalist state and the acquisition of political power by the working class could be realized in a peaceful way, without upsetting the existing structures. As an internationalist he supported peace, rejecting war and violence. For him, war was a product of capitalism. Such were the main features of "orthodox" German Marxism at the time when the "revisionist" theories of Eduard Bernstein appeared.

Bernstein created a great controversy with articles that he wrote in 1896 for Die Neue Zeit, arguing that Marxism needed to be revised. His divergence widened with the publication in 1899 of Die Voraussetzungen des Sozialismus und die Aufgaben der Sozialdemokratie ( Evolutionary Socialism), to which rejoinders were made by Kautsky in Bernstein und das Sozialdemokratische Programm: Eine Antikritik (1899; "Bernstein and the Social Democratic Program") and the Polish-born Marxist Rosa Luxemburg in Sozialreform oder Revolution ( Reform or Revolution), both in 1899. Bernstein focused first of all upon the labour theory of value. Along with the economists of his time he considered it outdated, both in the form expounded by British classical economists and as set forth in Das Kapital. He argued, moreover, that class struggle was becoming less rather than more intense, for concentration was not accelerating in industry as Marx had forecast, and in agriculture it was not increasing at all. Bernstein demonstrated this on the basis of German, Dutch, and English statistical data. He also argued that cartels and business syndicates were smoothing the evolution of capitalism, a fact that cast doubt on the validity of Marx's theory of capitalistic crises. Arguing that quite a few of Marx's theories were not scientifically based, Bernstein blamed the Hegelian and Ricardian structure of Marx's work for his failure to take sufficient account of observable reality. (see also Index: value)

To this, Kautsky replied that, with the development of capitalism, agriculture was becoming a sector more and more dependent on industry, and that in addition an industrialization of agriculture was taking place. Luxemburg took the position that the contradictions of capitalism did not cease to grow with the progress of finance capitalism and the exploitation of the colonies, and that these contradictions were leading to a war that would give the proletariat its opportunity to assume power by revolutionary means.

3.2.2 The radicals.

One of the most divisive questions was that of war and peace. This was brought to the fore at the outbreak of World War I, when Social Democratic deputies in the German Reichstag voted for the financing of the war. Among German Marxists who opposed the war were Karl Liebknecht and Luxemburg. Liebknecht was imprisoned in 1916 for agitating against the war. On his release in 1918 he took the leadership of the Spartacist movement, which was later to become the Communist Party of Germany. Luxemburg had also been arrested for her antimilitary activities. In addition to her articles, signed Junius, in which she debated with Lenin on the subject of World War I and the attitude of the Marxists toward it (published in 1916 as Die Krise der Sozialdemokratie [The Crisis in the German Social-Democracy]), she is known for her book Die Akkumulation des Kapitals (1913; The Accumulation of Capital). In this work she returned to Marx's economic analysis of capitalism, in particular the accumulation of capital as expounded in volume 2 of Das Kapital. There she found a contradiction that had until then been unnoticed: Marx's scheme seems to imply that the development of capitalism can be indefinite, though elsewhere he sees the contradictions of the system as bringing about increasingly violent economic crises that will inevitably sweep capitalism away. Luxemburg concluded that Marx's scheme is oversimplified and assumes a universe made up entirely of capitalists and workers. If increases in productivity are taken into account, she asserted, balance between the two sectors becomes impossible; in order to keep expanding, capitalists must find new markets in noncapitalist spheres, either among peasants and artisans or in colonies and underdeveloped countries. Capitalism will collapse only when exploitation of the world outside it (the peasantry, colonies, etc.) has reached a limit. This conclusion has been the subject of passionate controversies. (see also Index: "Crisis in the German Social- Democracy, The," )

3.2.3 The Austrians.

The Austrian school came into being when Austrian socialists started publishing their works independently of the Germans; it can be dated from either 1904 (beginning of the Marx-Studien collection) or 1907 (publication of the magazine Der Kampf ). The most important members of the school were Max Adler, Karl Renner, Rudolf Hilferding, Gustav Eckstein, Friedrich Adler, and Otto Bauer. The most eminent was Bauer, a brilliant theoretician whose Die Nationalitätenfrage und die Sozialdemokratie (1906; "The Nationalities Question and the Social Democracy") was critically reviewed by Lenin. In this work he dealt with the problem of nationalities in the light of the experience of the Austro-Hungarian Empire. He favoured the self-determination of peoples and emphasized the cultural elements in the concept of nationhood. Hilferding was finance minister of the German Republic after World War I in the Cabinets of the Social Democrats Gustav Stresemann (1923) and Hermann Müller (1928). He is known especially for his work Das Finanzkapital (1910), in which he maintained that capitalism had come under the control of banks and industrial monopolies. The growth of national competition and tariff barriers, he believed, had led to economic warfare abroad. Hilferding's ideas strongly influenced Lenin, who analyzed them in Imperialism, the Highest Stage of Capitalism (1916).

3.3 RUSSIAN AND SOVIET MARXISM

Das Kapital was translated into Russian in 1872. Marx kept up more or less steady relations with the Russian socialists and took an interest in the economic and social conditions of the tsarist empire. The man who originally introduced Marxism into Russia was Georgi Plekhanov, but the man who adapted Marxism to Russian conditions was Lenin. (see also Index: Leninism)

3.3.1 Lenin.

Vladimir Ilich Ulyanov, or Lenin, was born in 1870 at Simbirsk (now Ulyanovsk). He entered the University of Kazan to study law but was expelled the same year for participating in student agitation. In 1893 he settled in St. Petersburg and became actively involved with the revolutionary workers. With his pamphlet What Is To Be Done? (1902), he specified the theoretical principles and organization of a Marxist party as he thought it should be constituted. He took part in the second Congress of the Russian Social-Democratic Workers' Party, which was held in Brussels and London (1903), and induced the majority of the Congress members to adopt his views. Two factions formed at the Congress: the Bolshevik (from the Russian word for "larger") with Lenin as the leader and the Menshevik (from the Russian word for "smaller") with Julius Martov at the head. The former wanted a restricted party of militants and advocated the dictatorship of the proletariat. The latter wanted a wide-open proletarian party, collaboration with the liberals, and a democratic constitution for Russia. In his pamphlet One Step Forward, Two Steps Back (1904), Lenin compared the organizational principles of the Bolsheviks to those of the Mensheviks. After the failure of the 1905 Russian revolution, he drew positive lessons for the future in Two Tactics of Social Democracy in the Democratic Revolution. He fiercely attacked the influence of Kantian philosophy on German and Russian Marxism in Materialism and Empirio-criticism (1908). In 1912 at the Prague Conference the Bolsheviks constituted themselves as an independent party. During World War I Lenin resided in Switzerland, where he studied Hegel's Science of Logic and the development of capitalism and carried on debates with Marxists like Rosa Luxemburg on the meaning of the war and the right of nations to self-determination. In 1915 at Zimmerwald, and in 1916 at Kiental, he organized two international socialist conferences to fight against the war. Immediately after the February 1917 revolution he returned to Russia, and in October the Bolshevik coup brought him to power.

The situation of Russia and the Russian revolutionary movement at the end of the 19th century and the beginning of the 20th led Lenin to diverge, in the course of his development and his analyses, from the positions both of "orthodox Marxism" and of "revisionism." He rediscovered the original thought of Marx by a careful study of his works, in particular Das Kapital and The Holy Family. He saw Marxism as a practical affair and tried to go beyond the accepted formulas to plan political action that would come to grips with the surrounding world.

As early as 1894, in his populist study The Friends of the People, Lenin took up Marx's distinction between the "material social relations" of men and their "ideological social relations." In Lenin's eyes the importance of Das Kapital was that "while explaining the structure and the development of the social formation seen exclusively in terms of its relations of production, (Marx) has nevertheless everywhere and always analyzed the superstructure which corresponds to these relations of production." In The Development of Russian Capitalism (1897-99) Lenin sought to apply Marx's analysis by showing the growing role of capital, in particular commercial capital, in the exploitation of the workers in the factories and the large-scale expropriation of the peasants. It was thus possible to apply to Russia the models developed by Marx for western Europe. At the same time Lenin did not lose sight of the importance of the peasant in Russian society. Although a disciple of Marx, he did not believe that he had only to repeat Marx's conclusions. He wrote:

We do not consider the theory of Marx to be a complete, immutable whole. We think on the contrary that this theory has only laid the cornerstone of the science, a science which socialists must further develop in all directions if they do not want to let themselves be overtaken by life. We think that, for the Russian socialists, an independent elaboration of the theory is particularly necessary.

Lenin laid great stress upon the dialectical method. In his early writings he defined the dialectic as "nothing more nor less than the method of sociology, which sees society as a living organism, in perpetual development (and not as something mechanically assembled and thus allowing all sorts of arbitrary combinations of the various social elements) . . . " (The Friends of the People, 1894). After having studied Hegel toward the end of 1914, he took a more activist view. Dialectic is not only evolution; it is praxis, leading from activity to reflection and from reflection to action.

3.3.2 The dictatorship of the proletariat.

Lenin also put much emphasis on the leading role of the party. As early as 1902 he was concerned with the need for a cohesive party with a correct doctrine, adapted to the exigencies of the period, which would be a motive force among the masses, helping to bring them to an awareness of their real situation. In What Is To Be Done? he called for a party of professional revolutionaries, disciplined and directed, capable of defeating the police; its aim should be to establish the dictatorship of the proletariat. In order to do this, he wrote in Two Tactics of Social-Democracy in the Democratic Revolution, it was necessary "to subject the insurrection of the proletarian and non-proletarian masses to our influence, to our direction, to use it in our best interests." But this was not possible without a doctrine: "Without revolutionary theory, no revolutionary movement." On the eve of the revolution of October 1917, in The State and Revolution he set forth the conditions for the dictatorship of the proletariat and the suppression of the capitalist state.

Lenin assigned major importance to the peasantry in formulating his program. It would be a serious error, he held, for the Russian revolutionary workers' movement to neglect the peasants. Even though it was clear that the industrial proletariat constituted the vanguard of the revolution, the discontent of the peasantry could be oriented in a direction favourable to the revolution by placing among the goals of the party the seizure of privately owned land. As early as 1903, at the third congress of the party, he secured a resolution to this effect. Thereafter, the dictatorship of the proletariat became the dictatorship of the proletariat and the peasantry. In 1917 he encouraged the peasants to seize land long before the approval of agrarian reform by the Constituent Assembly.

Among Lenin's legacies to Soviet Marxism was one that proved to be injurious to the party. This was the decision taken at his behest by the 10th congress of the party in the spring of 1921, while the sailors were rebelling at Kronstadt and the peasants were growing restless in the countryside, to forbid all factions, all factional activity, and all opposition political platforms within the party. This decision had grave consequences in later years when Stalin used it against his opponents. (see also Index: Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, )

3.3.3 Stalin.

It is Joseph Stalin who codified the body of ideas that, under the name of Marxism-Leninism, has constituted the official doctrine of the Soviet and eastern European communist parties. Stalin was a man of action in a slightly different sense than was Lenin. Gradually taking over power after Lenin's death in 1924, he pursued the development of the Soviet Union with great vigour. By practicing Marxism, he assimilated it, at the same time simplifying it. Stalin's Marxism-Leninism rests on the dialectic of Hegel, as set forth in A Short History of the Communist Party of the Soviet Union (1938), and on a materialism that can be considered roughly identical to that of Feuerbach. His work Problems of Leninism, which appeared in 11 editions during his lifetime, sets forth an ideology of power and activism that rides roughshod over the more nuanced approach of Lenin. (see also Index: Stalinism)

Soviet dialectical materialism can be reduced to four laws: (1) History is a dialectical development. It proceeds by successive phases that supersede one another. These phases are not separate, any more than birth, growth, and death are separate. Though it is true that phase B necessarily negates phase A, it remains that phase B was already contained in phase A and was initiated by it. The dialectic does not regard nature as an accidental accumulation of objects, of isolated and independent phenomena, but as a unified, coherent whole. Furthermore, nature is perpetually in movement, in a state of unceasing renewal and development, in which there is always something being born and developing and something disintegrating and disappearing. (2) Evolution takes place in leaps, not gradually. (3) Contradictions must be made manifest. All phenomena contain in themselves contradictory elements. "Dialectic starts from the point of view that objects and natural phenomena imply internal contradictions, because they all have a positive and a negative side." These contradictory elements are in perpetual struggle: it is this struggle that is the "internal content of the process of development," according to Stalin. (4) The law of this development is economic. All other contradictions are rooted in the basic economic relationship. A given epoch is entirely determined by the relations of production existing among men. They are social relations; relations of collaboration or mutual aid, relations of domination or submission; and finally, transitory relations that characterize a period of passage from one system to another. "The history of the development of society is, above all, the history of the development of production, the history of the modes of production which succeed one another through the centuries." (see also Index: social evolution)

From these principles may be drawn the following inferences, essential for penetrating the workings of Marxist-Leninist thought and its application. No natural phenomenon, no historical or social situation, no political fact, can be considered independently of the other facts or phenomena that surround it; it is set within a whole. Since movement is the essential fact, one must distinguish between what is beginning to decay and what is being born and developing. Since the process of development takes place by leaps, one passes suddenly from a succession of slow quantitative changes to a radical qualitative change. In the social or political realm, these sudden qualitative changes are revolutions, carried out by the oppressed classes. One must follow a frankly proletarian-class policy that exposes the contradictions of the capitalist system. A reformist policy makes no sense. Consequently (1) nothing can be judged from the point of view of "eternal justice" or any other preconceived notion and (2) no social system is immutable. To be effective, one must not base one's action on social strata that are no longer developing, even if they represent for the moment the dominant force, but on those that are developing.

Stalin's materialist and historical dialectic differs sharply from the perspective of Karl Marx. In The Communist Manifesto Marx applied the materialist dialectic to the social and political life of his time. In the chapter entitled "Bourgeois and Proletarians," he studied the process of the growth of the revolutionary bourgeoisie within feudal society, then the genesis and the growth of the proletariat within capitalism, placing the emphasis on the struggle between antagonistic classes. To be sure, he connected social evolution with the development of the forces of production. What counted for him, however, was not only the struggle but also the birth of consciousness among the proletariat. "As to the final victory of the propositions put forth in the Manifesto, Marx expected it to come primarily from the intellectual development of the working class, necessarily the result of common action and discussion" (Engels, preface to the republication of The Communist Manifesto, May 1, 1890).

The result of Stalin's dialectic, however, was what he called revolution from above, a dictatorial policy to increase industrialization and collectivize agriculture based upon ruthless repression and a strong centralization of power. For Stalin what counted was the immediate goal, the practical result. The move was from a dialectic that emphasized both the objective and the subjective to one purely objective, or more exactly, objectivist. Human actions are to be judged not by taking account of the intentions of the actor and their place in a given historical web but only in terms of what they signify objectively at the end of the period considered.

3.3.4 Trotskyism.

Alongside Marxism-Leninism as expounded in the former Soviet Union, there arose another point of view expressed by Stalin's opponent Leon Trotsky and his followers. Trotsky played a leading role in both the Russian Revolution of 1905 and that of 1917. After Lenin's death he fell out with Stalin. Their conflict turned largely upon questions of policy, both domestic and foreign. In the realm of ideas, Trotsky held that a revolution in a backward, rural country could be carried out only by the proletariat. Once in power the proletariat must carry out agrarian reform and undertake the accelerated development of the economy. The revolution must be a socialist one, involving the abolition of the private ownership of the means of production, or else it will fail. But the revolution cannot be carried out in isolation, as Stalin maintained it could. The capitalist countries will try to destroy it; moreover, to succeed the revolution must be able to draw upon the industrial techniques of the developed countries. For these reasons the revolution must be worldwide and permanent, directed against the liberal and nationalist bourgeoisie of all countries and using local victories to advance the international struggle.

Tactically, Trotsky emphasized the necessity of finding or creating a revolutionary situation, of educating the working class in order to revolutionize it, of seeing that the party remained open to the various revolutionary tendencies and avoided becoming bureaucratized, and finally, when the time for insurrection comes, of organizing it according to a detailed plan.

3.4 VARIANTS OF MARXISM

 

3.4.1 Maoism.

When the Chinese Communists took power in 1948, they brought with them a new kind of Marxism that came to be called Maoism after their leader Mao Zedong. The thought of Mao must always be seen against the changing revolutionary reality of China from 1930 onward. His thought was complex, a Marxist type of analysis combined with the permanent fundamentals of Chinese thought and culture.

One of its central elements has to do with the nature and role of contradictions in socialist society. For Mao, every society, including socialist (communist) society, contained "two different types of contradictions": (1) antagonistic contradictions--contradictions between us (the people) and our enemies (the Chinese bourgeoisie faithful), between the imperialist camp and the socialist camp, and so forth--which are resolved by revolution, and (2) nonantagonistic contradictions--between the government and the people under a socialist regime, between two groups within the Communist Party, between one section of the people and another under a communist regime, and so forth--which are resolved by vigorous fraternal criticism and self-criticism.

The notion of contradiction is specific to Mao's thought in that it differs from the conceptions of Marx or Lenin. For Mao, in effect, contradictions were at the same time universal and particular. In their universality, one must seek and discover what constitutes their particularity: every contradiction displays a particular character, depending on the nature of things and phenomena. Contradictions have alternating aspects--sometimes strongly marked, sometimes blurred. Some of these aspects are primary, others secondary. It is important to define them well, for if one fails to do so, the analysis of the social reality and the actions that follow from it will be mistaken. This is quite far from Stalinism and dogmatic Marxism-Leninism.

Another essential element of Mao's thought, which must be seen in the context of revolutionary China, is the notion of permanent revolution. It is an old idea advocated in different contexts by Marx, Lenin, and Trotsky but lacking, in Mao's formulation, the international dimension espoused by his predecessors. For Mao it followed from his ideas about the struggle of man against nature (held from 1938, at least); the campaigns for the rectification of thought (1942, 1951, 1952); and the necessity of struggling against bureaucracy, wastage, and corruption in a country of 600,000,000 to 700,000,000 inhabitants, where very old civilizations and cultures still permeated both the bourgeois classes and the peasantry, where bureaucracy was thoroughly entrenched, and where the previous society was extremely corrupt. It arose from Mao's conviction that the rhythm of the revolution must be accelerated. This conviction appeared in 1957 in his speeches and became manifest in 1958 in the "Great Leap Forward," followed in 1966 by the Cultural Revolution.

Mao's concept of permanent revolution rests upon the existence of nonantagonistic contradictions in the China of today and of tomorrow. Men must be mobilized into a permanent movement in order to carry forward the revolution and to prevent the ruling group from turning bourgeois (as he perceived it had in the Soviet Union). It is necessary to shape among the masses a new vision of the world by tearing them from their passivity and their century-old habits. This is the background of the Cultural Revolution that began in 1966, following previous campaigns but differing from them in its magnitude and, it would seem, in the mobilization of youth against the cadres of the party. In these campaigns Mao drew upon his past as a revolutionary Marxist peasant leader, from his life in the red military and peasant bases and among the Red Guards of Yen-an, seeking in his past experience ways to mobilize the whole Chinese population against the dangers--internal and external--that confronted it in the present.

The distinguishing characteristic of Maoism is that it represents a peasant type of Marxism, with a principally rural and military outlook. While basing himself on Marxism-Leninism, adapted to Chinese requirements, Mao was rooted in the peasant life from which he himself came, in the revolts against the warlords and the bureaucrats that have filled the history of China. By integrating this experience into a universal vision of history, Mao gave it a significance that flows beyond the provincial limits of China.

In his effort to remain close to the Chinese peasant masses, Mao drew upon an idea of nature and a symbolism found in popular Chinese Taoism, though transformed by his Marxism. It can be seen in his many poems, which were written in the classical Chinese style. This idea of nature is accompanied in his written political works by the Promethean idea of man struggling in a war against nature, a conception in his thought that goes back at least to 1938 and became more important after 1955 as the rhythm of the revolution accelerated.

3.4.2 Marxism in Cuba.

The Marxism of Fidel Castro expresses itself as a rejection of injustice in any form--political, economic, or social. In this sense it is related to the liberal democracy and Pan-Americanism of Simón Bolívar in Latin America during the 19th century. In its liberalism, Castro's early socialism resembled the various French socialisms of the first half of the 19th century. Only gradually did Castroism come to identify itself with Marxism-Leninism, although from the very beginning of the Cuban revolution Castro revealed his attachment to certain of Marx's ideas. Castro's Marxism rejects some of the tenets and practices of official Marxism-Leninism: it is outspoken against dogmatism, bureaucracy, and sectarianism. In one sense, Castroism is a Marxist-Leninist "heresy." It exalts the ethos of guerrilla revolution over party politics. At the same time it aims to apply a purer Marxism to the conditions of Cuba: alleged American imperialism, a single-crop economy, a low initial level of political and economic development. One may call it an attempt to realize a synthesis of Marxist ideas and the ideas of Bolívar.

In the ideological and political conflicts that divide the communist world, Castroism takes a more or less unengaged position. Castro is above all a nationalist and only after that a Marxist.

3.4.3 Marxism in the Third World.

The development of Marxist variants in the Third World has been primarily influenced by the undeveloped industrial state and the former colonial status of the nations in question. In the traditional Marxist view the growth of capitalism is seen as a step necessary for the breakup of precapitalist peasant society and for the rise of the revolutionary proletariat class. Some theorists believe, however, that capitalism introduced by imperialist rather than indigenous powers sustains rather than destroys the feudal structure of peasant society and promotes underdevelopment because resources and surplus are usurped by the colonial powers. Furthermore, the revolutionary socialist movement becomes subordinate to that of national liberation, which violates Marx's theory of class struggle by uniting all indigenous classes in the common cause of anti-imperialism. For these reasons, many Third World countries have chosen to follow the Maoist model, with its emphasis on agrarian revolution against feudalism and imperialism, rather than the old Soviet one. Another alternative, one specific to the Third World, also exists. This policy bypasses capitalism and depends upon the established strength of other communist countries for support against imperialism.

3.4.4 Marxism in the West.

There are two main forms of Marxism in the West: that of the traditional communist parties and the more diffuse "New Left" form, which has come to be known as "Western Marxism." In general, the success of western European communist parties had been hindered by their perceived allegiance to the old Soviet authority rather than their own countries; the secretive, bureaucratic form of organization they inherited from Lenin; the ease with which they became integrated into capitalist society; and their consequent fear of compromising their principles by sharing power with bourgeois parties. The Western parties basically adhered to the policies of Soviet Marxism until the 1970s, when they began to advocate Eurocommunism, a moderate version of communism that they felt would broaden their base of appeal beyond the working class and thus improve their chances for political success. As described by Enrico Berlinguer, Georges Marchais, and Santiago Carrillo, the leaders of the Italian, French, and Spanish communist parties, respectively, Eurocommunism favoured a peaceful, democratic approach to achieving socialism, encouraged making alliances with other political parties, guaranteed civil liberties, and renounced the central authority of the Soviet party. By the 1980s Eurocommunism had largely been abandoned as unsuccessful, and communist parties in advanced capitalist nations returned to orthodox Marxism-Leninism despite the concomitant problems.

Western Marxism, however, can be seen as a repudiation of Marxism-Leninism, although, when it was first formulated in the 1920s, its proponents believed they were loyal to the dominant Soviet Communist Party. Prominent figures in the evolution of Western Marxism include the central Europeans György Lukács, Karl Korsch, and Lucien Goldmann; Antonio Gramsci of Italy; the German theorists who constituted the Frankfurt school, especially Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, and Jürgen Habermas; and Henri Lefebvre, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty of France.

Western Marxism has been shaped primarily by the failure of the socialist revolution in the Western world. Western Marxists were concerned less with the actual political or economic practice of Marxism than with its philosophical interpretation, especially in relation to cultural and historical studies. In order to explain the inarguable success of capitalist society, they felt they needed to explore and understand non-Marxist approaches and all aspects of bourgeois culture. Eventually, they came to believe that traditional Marxism was not relevant to the reality of modern Western society.

Marx had predicted that revolution would succeed in Europe first, but, in fact, the Third World has proved more responsive. Orthodox Marxism also championed the technological achievements associated with capitalism, viewing them as essential to the progress of socialism. Experience showed the Western Marxists, however, that technology did not necessarily produce the crises Marx described and did not lead inevitably to revolution. In particular they disagreed with the idea, originally emphasized by Engels, that Marxism is an integrated, scientific doctrine that can be applied universally to nature; they viewed it as a critique of human life, not an objective, general science. Disillusioned by the terrorism of the Stalin era and the bureaucracy of the Communist Party system, they advocated the idea of government by workers' councils, which they believed would eliminate professional politicians and would more truly represent the interests of the working class. Later, when the working class appeared to them to be too well integrated into the capitalist system, the Western Marxists supported more anarchistic tactics. In general, their views are more in accord with those found in Marx's early, humanist writings rather than with his later, dogmatic interpretations.

Western Marxism has found support primarily among intellectuals rather than the working class, and orthodox Marxists have judged it impractical. Nevertheless, the Western Marxists' emphasis on Marx's social theory and their critical assessment of Marxist methodology and ideas have coloured the way even non-Marxists view the world.

(H.C./ D.T.McL./Ed.)

¸¶¸£Å©½º (Karl (Heinrich) Marx). 1818. 5. 5 ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ¶óÀÎ Æ®¸®¾î~1883. 3. 14 ·±´ø. µ¶ÀÏÀÇ »çȸÇÐÀÚ¡¤°æÁ¦ÇÐÀÚ¡¤Á¤Ä¡À̷а¡. 

¸¶¸£Å©½º

'¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ'(°ø»êÁÖÀÇ)ÀÇ Ã¢½ÃÀڷμ­ ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í ÇÔ²² ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei¡µ(1848)¡¤¡´ÀÚº»·Ð Das Kapital¡µ(1867, 1885, 1894)À» ÁýÇÊÇß´Ù.

Ãʱâ»ý¾Ö

Ä«¸¦ ÇÏÀθ®È÷ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â 1818³â 5¿ù 5ÀÏ ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ ¶óÀÎ ÁÖ Æ®¸®¾î ½Ã¿¡¼­ 7³²¸Å Áß Ã¹Â°·Î ž´Ù. ¸í¸ÁÀÖ´Â º¯È£»ç¿´´ø ¾Æ¹öÁö´Â Ä­Æ®¿Í º¼Å׸£ÀÇ °è¸ùÁÖÀÇ »ç»ó¿¡ ½ÉÃëÇØ ÀÖ¾ú°í ¾Æ¸íÀÌ Ç¿¡Å¸ ÇÁ·¹½ººÎ¸£Å©¿´´ø ¾î¸Ó´Ï´Â ³×´ú¶õµå Ãâ½ÅÀ̾ú´Ù. ¾çÄ£ ¸ðµÎ À¯´ë Ç÷ÅëÀ̾úÀ¸³ª ¾Æ¹öÁö´Â Ä«¸¦ÀÌ Å¾±â 1³â ÀüÂë(¾Æ¸¶µµ Çö½ÇÀûÀÎ Çʿ信¼­) º¹À½ÁÖÀÇ ±¹±³È¸ÀÇ ¼¼·Ê¸¦ ¹Þ¾Ò°í, Ä«¸¦ ¿ª½Ã 6¼¼°¡ µÇ´ø ÇØ¿¡ ¼¼·Ê¸¦ ¹Þ¾Ò´Ù. À¯´ëÀÎÀÌ °¨´çÇØ¾ß ÇÏ´Â »çȸÀû Æí°ß°ú Â÷º°Àº ¾î¸° ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô Á¾±³ÀÇ ¿ªÇÒ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÀDZ¸½É°ú »çȸ°³ÇõÀÇ ¿­¸ÁÀ» ºÒ·¯ÀÏÀ¸Ä×´Ù.

1830³â Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Æ®¸®¾î ±è³ªÁö¿ò¿¡ ÀÔÇÐÇß´Ù. Çб³´Â ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇ ±³»ç¿Í ÇлýµéÀÇ Àº½Åó°¡ µÇ¾ú°í, °æÂûÀÇ °¨½Ã°¡ ²÷ÀÌÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. û³â ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ±Û ¼Ó¿¡´Â ±×¸®½ºµµ±³Àû ºÀ»ç¿Í ÀÚ±âÈñ»ýÀÇ ÀÇÁö°¡ ¿ª·ÂÈ÷ µå·¯³ª ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. 1835³â 10¿ù Ä«¸¦Àº º»´ëÇб³·ÎºÎÅÍ ÀÔÇÐÅëÁö¸¦ ¹Þ¾Ò´Ù. ±×°¡ ¼ö°­ÇÑ °ú¸ñµéÀº ±×¸®½º¾î¿Í ·Î¸¶ ½ÅÈ­, ¹Ì¼ú»ç¿Í °°Àº ¿À·ÎÁö Àι®ÁÖÀÇÀûÀÎ °ÍµéÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Åë»óÀûÀÎ ÇлýȰµ¿¿¡ Âü°¡Çß°í °áÅõ¸¦ ¹ú¿´À¸¸ç ¼ú¿¡ ÃëÇØ ¼Ò¶õÀ» ÀÏÀ¸ÄÑ °¨¹æ¿¡¼­ ÇϷ縦 º¸³½ Àûµµ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ±×ÀÇ »ý¾Ö¸¦ ÅëÆ²¾î ´Ü ÇѹøÀÇ °¨±ÝÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¼úÁý¸ðÀÓÀ» ÁÖ°üÇß°í Á÷Á¢ÇൿÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀÌ Æ÷ÇÔµÈ ½ÃÀΠŬ·´¿¡ ÃâÀÔÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ½Ç·Î ¹Ýµ¿ÀûÀÎ ´ëÇй®È­°¡ º» »ýȰÀÇ ÁÖ·ù¸¦ ÀÌ·ç°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ±¹¹ÎÀÇȸ(ÇÁ¶ûũǪ¸£Æ®)¸¦ °ÅºÎÇß´ø ÇлýµéÀÌ °Ë°ÅµÇ°í ±× °¡¿îµ¥ ÀϺδ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Àü»ý¾Ö µ¿¾È Ãß¹æ´çÇØ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. 1³â ÈÄ Ä«¸¦Àº ¹ý·ü°ú öÇÐÀ» °øºÎÇϱâ À§ÇØ º£¸¦¸°À¸·Î ¶°³µ´Ù.

Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ º£¸¦¸°´ëÇб³¸¦ ÈÛ¾µ°í ÀÖ´ø Çì°ÖöÇаú ¸¸³ª û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¸¦ ÃßÁ¾ÇÏ°Ô µÈ »ç½ÇÀº ¸Å¿ì Áß´ëÇÑ Àǹ̸¦ °®´Â´Ù. óÀ½¿¡ Ä«¸¦Àº G.W. F. Çì°Ö¿¡ ´ëÇØ Àû´ë°¨À» ´À²¼À¸¸ç, ±×¹«·Æ ¸öÁ® ´¯°Ô µÈ ¾ó¸¶°£ÀÇ ÀÌÀ¯´Â ¾Æ¹öÁö¿¡°Ô ½èµíÀÌ "Çø¿ÀÇØ¿Â °ßÇØ¸¦ ¼þ¹èÇØ¾ß ÇÏ´Â µ¥¼­ ¿À´Â È¥¶õ½º·¯¿ò" ¶§¹®À̾ú´Ù. ±×·¯³ª º£¸¦¸° Çõ¸í¹®È­¿¡¼­ Çì°ÖÀÌ Â÷ÁöÇÏ´Â ºñÁßÀº ¾ÐµµÀûÀÎ °ÍÀ̾ú°í Ä«¸¦Àº »õ·Î¿î ¹®¿¹¡¤Ã¶ÇÐ ¿îµ¿À» Àü°³Çϰí ÀÖ´ø '¹Ú»ç Ŭ·´'¿¡ °¡ÀÔÇß´Ù. Ŭ·´ÀÇ Áß½ÉÀι°Àº ÀþÀº ½ÅÇа­»ç ºê·ç³ë ¹Ù¿ì¾î¿´´Âµ¥, º¹À½¼­´Â ½ÇÁ¦¿ª»çÀÇ ±â·ÏÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó °¨¼ºÀû Çʿ信 ±âÀÎÇϴ ȯ»óÀÇ ±â·ÏÀÌ¸ç ¿¹¼ö ¶ÇÇÑ ¿ª»ç»óÀÇ ½ÇÁ¸Àι°ÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó´Â ȹ±âÀûÀÎ °¡¼³À» Àü°³½Ã۰í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿¹¾ðÀÚ ÀÌ»ç¾ß¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ¹Ù¿ì¾îÀÇ °­Á¿¡ µî·ÏÇß´Ù. ºê·ç³ë ¹Ù¿ì¾î´Â »õ·Î¿î »çȸÀû ÆÄ±¹, Áï ¿¹¼öÀÇ À縲½Ã¿¡ ´ÚÄ¥ ½Ã·Ãº¸´Ù ´õ¿í ¹«½Ã¹«½ÃÇÑ ÆÄ±¹ÀÌ ´Ù°¡¿À°í ÀÖ´Ù°í ¼³ÆÄÇß´Ù. û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ´Â ±Þ¼Óµµ·Î ¹«½Å·Ð¿¡ °¡±î¿öÁö°í ¾î·ÅDzÀÌ Á¤Ä¡Àû Çൿµéµµ °Å·ÐµÇ±â ½ÃÀÛÇß´Ù.

û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¿¡ ÀáÀçµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Â Á¤ºÎÀüº¹ ºÐÀ§±â¿¡ °øÆ÷¸¦ ´À³¤ ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ Á¤ºÎ´Â À̵鿡 ´ëÇÑ »öÃâÀÛ¾÷¿¡ Âø¼öÇß°í 1839³â ºê·ç³ë ¹Ù¿ì¾î´Â °­»çÁ÷À» ¹ÚÅ»´çÇß´Ù. ÀÌ ½ÃÀý °¡Àå ÀýÄ£ÇÑ Ä£±¸·Î¼­ Åõ¿Á»ýȰÀ» Çϱ⵵ Çß´ø Àú³Î¸®½ºÆ® ¾Æµ¹ÇÁ ·çÅÙº£¸£Å©´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô º¸´Ù ´Éµ¿ÀûÀÎ »çȸÂü¿©¸¦ ±ÇÀ¯Çß´Ù. ±× »çÀÌ ±×ÀÇ ¿¬±¸´Â ÁöüµÇ°í ÀÖ¾ú°í, ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Ä£±¸µéÀÇ ÀçÃË¿¡ ¸øÀÌ°Ü ¿¹³ª´ëÇб³¿¡ ¹Ú»ç³í¹®À» Á¦ÃâÇß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ³í¹®Àº Çй®ÀûÀÎ ¸é¿¡¼­ º°·Î ¿ì¼öÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´ø °ÍÀ¸·Î ¾Ë·ÁÁ³À¸³ª 1841³â 4¿ù ¹Ú»çÇÐÀ§¸¦ ÃëµæÇÏ´Â µ¥ ¼º°øÇß´Ù. ³í¹®Àº Çì°ÖÁÖÀÇÀÚÀÇ °üÁ¡¿¡¼­ µ¥¸ðÅ©¸®Å佺¿Í ¿¡ÇÇÄí·Î½ºÀÚ¿¬Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ Â÷ÀÌÁ¡À» ºÐ¼®ÇÑ °ÍÀ̾úÁö¸¸, ºÐ¸íÇÑ °ÍÀº ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺ÀûÀÎ µµÀüÀÇ ¼Ò¸®¸¦ ³»°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù´Â Á¡ÀÌ´Ù.

"öÇÐÀº ºñ¹ÐÀ» Áö´ÏÁö ¾Ê´Â´Ù. ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺ÀÇ 'Áø½Ç·Î ³ª´Â ¸ðµç ½ÅµéÀ» ½È¾îÇÑ´Ù'´Â °í¹éÀº ¹Ù·Î öÇÐ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ °í¹éÀÌ¸ç ¸ðµç ½Åµé¿¡ ´ëÇ×Çϴ öÇÐÀÇ ½ÅÁ¶ÀÌ´Ù¡¦¡¦ ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺´Â öÇÐÀÇ ÃàÀÏÇ¥¿¡ À־ °¡Àå °í±ÍÇÑ ¼ºÀÚÀÌÀÚ ¼ø±³ÀÚÀÌ´Ù."

1841³â Ãâ°£µÈ ·çÆ®ºñÈ÷ Æ÷À̾î¹ÙÈåÀÇ ¡´±×¸®½ºµµ±³ÀÇ º»Áú Das Wesen des Christentums¡µÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¿¡ Ä¿´Ù¶õ ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÌÃÆ´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ »ý°¢Çϱ⿡ Æ÷À̾î¹ÙÈå´Â, ÀÚ¿¬¿¡ ¹ßÀ» ºÙÀÌ°í »ç´Â Çö½Ç Àΰ£À¸·ÎºÎÅÍ Àý´ëÁ¤½ÅÀ» ÃßÃâÇØ³½ Çì°ÖÀÇ ³í¸®Ã¼°è¸¦ ÇØºÎÇÔÀ¸·Î½á ±×ÀÇ °ü³ä·ÐÀû ÀÌ»óÁÖÀǸ¦ È¿°úÀûÀ¸·Î ºñÆÇÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ÀÌÈÄ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀû ³ë·ÂÀº ¸ðµç »ç¹°Àº ¸ð¼øÀûÀÎ ±¹¸éÀÇ Ãæµ¹¿¡ µû¶ó Áö¼ÓÀûÀÎ º¯È­¸¦ °Þ°Ô µÈ´Ù´Â Çì°ÖÀÇ º¯Áõ¹ý°ú ¹°¸®ÀûÀÎ Á¶°ÇµéÀ» °ü³äÀÇ »óÀ§¿¡ µÎ´Â Æ÷À̾î¹ÙÈåÀÇ À¯¹°·ÐÀ» °áÇÕ½ÃŰ´Â ¹æÇâÀ¸·Î ÀÌ·ç¾îÁö°Ô µÈ´Ù.

1842³â 1¿ù ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Ä븥¿¡¼­ â°£µÈ ¡´¶óÀÎ ½Å¹® Rheinische Zeitung¡µÀÇ ±â°í°¡°¡ µÇ¾ú´Ù. Ä븥Àº ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ »ê¾÷ Áß½ÉÁö¿´°í ½Å¹®»ç´Â »óÀΡ¤ÀºÇà°¡¡¤»ê¾÷°¡ µéÀÌ ¸ð¿© ¸¸µç ¹ÎÁÖÀûÀ̰í ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀûÀÎ ±â°üÀ̾ú´Ù. ÀÌÁîÀ½ ¾ð·ÐÀÇ ÀÚÀ¯¿¡ °üÇÑ ¼Ò³í¹® Çϳª°¡ ¹ßÇ¥µÇ´Âµ¥, ±×¶§±îÁö¸¸ ÇØµµ Àý´ëÀûÀÎ µµ´ö±âÁذú º¸ÆíÀûÀÎ À±¸®¿øÄ¢À» ´ç¿¬ÇÑ °ÍÀ¸·Î ¹Þ¾ÆµéÀ̰í ÀÖ´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¾ð·Ð¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ´ç±¹ÀÇ °Ë¿­À» ¹ÎÁßÀ» ¿°Å½ÇÏ°í ºñõÇÏ°í ¾ÇÀÇ¿¡ Âù ¼ÓÀε鿡°Ô ½Å°ú °°Àº ±Ç´ÉÀ» ºÎ¿©ÇÏ´Â Á˾ÇÀ¸·Î ´ÜÁ¤Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù. 1842³â 10¿ù 15ÀÏ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µÀÇ ÁÖÇÊÀÌ µÇ¾ú°í, º£¸¦¸° ºó¹ÎÀÇ ÁÖÅù®Á¦·ÎºÎÅÍ ³ó¹ÎµéÀÇ »ê¸²¹úä¿Í »õ·Î¿î °ø»êÁÖÀÇ Çö»ó¿¡ À̸£±â±îÁö °æÁ¦¡¤»çȸ ¹®Á¦¿¡ °üÇÑ ¼ö¾øÀÌ ¸¹Àº ³í¼³À» ÁýÇÊÇØ¾ß¸¸ Çß´Ù. ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ Çì°ÖÀÇ °ü³ä·ÐÀº ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ Çö½Ç°úÁ¦ÀÇ ÇØ°á¿¡ º°´Ù¸¥ µµ¿òÀÌ µÇÁö ¸øÇß°í, Ä«¸¦Àº ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ °è±Þ¿¡ Ãæ°ÝÀ» °¡ÇÏ´Â °Í¸¸À¸·Î »çȸȰµ¿ÀÌ ÃæºÐÈ÷ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù°í ¹Ï´Â Çì°ÖÆÄ µ¿·áµé·ÎºÎÅÍ ¸Ö¾îÁö°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù.

¹ý±Ô¹üÀÇ ÇÑ°è ³»¿¡¼­ Á¡ÁøÀûÀÎ º¯ÇõÀ» ÃßÁøÇÏ´Â ½ÇõÀû ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀ» °¡±îÀÌÇß´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µÀÇ ¹ßÇàºÎ¼ö¸¦ 3¹è·Î ´Ã¸®°í ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ ÁÖ¿äÀϰ£Áö·Î ºÎ°¢½ÃŰ´Â µ¥ ¼º°øÇß´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ¼ÖÁ÷Çϰí ÀÚÀ¯ºÐ¹æÇÑ ³íÁ¶¸¦ ¹®Á¦»ïÀº Á¤ºÎ´ç±¹Àº ½Å¹®À» Á¤°£½ÃÄ×°í, ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´µ¶ÀÏ-ÇÁ¶û½º ¿¬º¸ Deutsch-französische Jahrbücher¡µ¸¦ ¹ß°£ÇÏÀÚ´Â ÀÚÀ¯ Çì°ÖÆÄ ¾Æ¸£³îÆ® ·ç°ÔÀÇ Á¦ÀǸ¦ ¹Þ¾ÆµéÀÎ µÚ ÆÄ¸®·Î ÇâÇß´Ù.

Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¾àÈ¥ÇÑ Áö 7³âÀÌ Áö³­ 1843³â 6¿ù 4¼¼ ¿¬»óÀÎ ¿¹´Ï Æù º£½ºÆ®ÆÈ·»°ú °áÈ¥Çß´Ù. Áö¼º°ú ¸Å·ÂÀ» °âºñÇÑ ¿¹´Ï´Â ¶Ù¾î³­ ±ºÀΰú ÇàÁ¤°üµéÀ» ¹èÃâÇØ³½ ¸í¹®°¡ÀÇ µþ·Î¼­ ±×³àÀÇ À̺¹ÇüÁ¦´Â Èʳ¯ ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ÀÇ ³»¹«Àå°ü¿¡ ¿À¸£°Ô µÈ´Ù. »ý ½Ã¸ùÀÇ ÃßÁ¾ÀÚ¿´´ø ¿¹´ÏÀÇ ¾Æ¹öÁö´Â Ä«¸¦À» ÁÁ¾ÆÇÏ¿© °¡Á·µéÀÇ ¹Ý´ë¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í °áÈ¥À» ¼º»ç½ÃÄ×À¸³ª, Á¤ÀÛ Ä«¸¦ÀÇ ¾Æ¹öÁö ÇÏÀθ®È÷´Â ±×³à°¡ ¾Ç·É¿¡ »ç·ÎÀâÈù ¾ÆµéÀÇ Á¦¹°ÀÌ µÇÁö³ª ¾ÊÀ»±î °ÆÁ¤½º·¯¿öÇß´Ù.

¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ ÆÄ¸®·Î ÀÌÁÖÇÑ °ÍÀº °áÈ¥ ÈÄ 4³âÀÌ µÇ´ø ÇØ¿´´Ù. ´ç½ÃÀÇ ÆÄ¸®´Â »çȸÁÖÀÇ ¼¼·Â°ú º¸´Ù ±ÞÁøÀûÀÎ °ø»êÁÖÀÇ Çõ¸í¿îµ¿ÀÌ ²ÉÀ» ÇÇ¿ì°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. Çõ¸í°¡°¡ µÈ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÇÁ¶û½º¡¤µ¶ÀÏ ³ëµ¿ÀÚµéÀÇ °ø»êÁÖÀÇ Á¶Á÷µé°ú ½ÇÁ¦ÀûÀÎ °ü·ÃÀ» ¸Î±â ½ÃÀÛÇß´Ù. ±×µéÀÇ »ç»óÀº ³Ê¹«³ªµµ Á¶ÀâÇÏ°í ¹«ÁöÇÑ °ÍÀ̾úÁö¸¸ ±×µéÀÇ ÀμºÀº ±×¸¦ °¨µ¿½ÃŰ±â¿¡ ÃæºÐÇß´Ù. ¡´ 1844³âÀÇ °æÁ¦ÇÐ-öÇÐ Ãʰí Ökonomisch-philosophische Manuskripte aus dem Jahre 1844¡µ¿¡¼­ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â "ÇüÁ¦¾Ö´Â ±×µé¿¡°Ô À־ ´Ü¼øÇÑ ±¸È£¸¸ÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï°í »îÀÇ Áø½ÇÀÌ´Ù. ³ëµ¿À¸·Î ´Ü·ÃµÈ ±×µéÀÇ À°Ã¼´Â ¿ì¸®¿¡°Ô Àΰ£ÀÇ °í±ÍÇÔÀ» Àϱú¿öÁØ´Ù"¶ó°í ¾²°í ÀÖ´Ù. ¡´1844³âÀÇ °æÁ¦ÇÐ-öÇÐ ÃÊ°í¡µ´Â ÀÌÈÄ 100³â µ¿¾È ºûÀ» ¹ßÇÏÁö ¸øÇßÁö¸¸ ¸¶¸£Å©½º ¿ª»ç¡¤°æÁ¦ ÀÌ·ÐÀÇ ¹ÙÅÁÀ» ÀÌ·ç´Â ÈÞ¸Ó´ÏÁòÀÌ ¼³¸íµÇ°í ÀÖ´Â Á¡¿¡¼­ °¡Ä¡¸¦ ÀÒÁö ¾Ê°í ÀÖ´Ù.

´Ü¸íÀ¸·Î ³¡³­ ¡´µ¶ÀÏ-ÇÁ¶û½º ¿¬º¸¡µ°¡ ÇØ¸¶´Ù ÃâÆÇÀ» °ÅµìÇÏ´Â »çÀÌ¿¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ±â°í°¡¿´´ø ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½º¿ÍÀÇ °ü°è´Â ±Þ¼Óµµ·Î ¹ßÀüµÇ¾ú´Ù. ¡´µ¶ÀÏ-ÇÁ¶û½º¿¬º¸¡µ¿¡ ½Ç¸° ¡´¿ìÀÍ Çì°ÖÆÄ öÇÐ ºñÆÇ¡µ¿¡´Â "Á¾±³´Â ¹ÎÁßÀÇ ¾ÆÆí"À̶ó´Â À¯¸íÇÑ ¹®±¸¿Í ÇÔ²² öÇÐÀÇ ½ÇÇöÀ» À§ÇÑ 'ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ ºÀ±â'°¡ Á¦Ã¢µÇ°í ÀÖ´Ù. ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ Á¤ºÎ´Â ´Ù½Ã Çѹø Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Á¦Àç¿¡ ³ª¼¹°í 1845³â 2¿ù Ä«¸¦Àº ÆÄ¸®¸¦ ¶°³ª ºê·ò¼¿·Î ÇâÇß´Ù. Ä«¸¦Àº º§±â¿¡¿¡¼­ ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í ȸµ¿ÇÑ µÚ ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ±¹ÀûÀ» Æ÷±âÇß´Ù.

ºê·ò¼¿ ½Ã´ë

ºê·ò¼¿¿¡¼­ÀÇ ´ÙÀ½ 2³â°£Àº ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ °øµ¿ÀÛ¾÷ÀÌ ½ÉÈ­µÇ´ø ½Ã±â¿´´Ù. ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ¾Æ¹öÁöÀÇ Á÷¹°°øÀåÀÌ À§Ä¡ÇØ ÀÖ´ø ¸Çü½ºÅÍ¿¡¼­ »ê¾÷Çõ¸íÀÇ ¾Ï¿ïÇÑ Çö½ÇµéÀ» óÀ½ Á¢Çß´Ù. û³â Çì°Ö ÇÐÆÄ¿¡ ¼ÓÇß´ø ±×´Â °ø»êÁÖÀÇ ¶øºñ¶ó ºÒ·È´ø ¸ðÁ¦½º Ç콺ÀÇ ¿µÇâÀ» ¹Þ¾Æ °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ°¡ µÇ¾úÀ¸¸ç ¿µ±¹¿¡¼­´Â ·Î¹öÆ® ¿À¾ðÀÇ ÃßÁ¾ÀÚµé°ú ±³·ùÇß´Ù. ÀÌÁ¦ ±×µé »çÀÌÀÇ °øÅëµÈ °ßÇØ¸¦ È®ÀÎÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º´Â µÎ »ç¶÷ÀÇ ÁöÀû ÀÚ¿øÀ» °áÇÕ½ÃÄÑ ½ÅÇÐÀÚ ºê·ç³ë ¹Ù¿ì¾îÀÇ Çì°ÖÁÖÀÇÀû °ü³ä·Ð¿¡ ´ëÇÑ Àå¹®ÀÇ ºñÆò ¡´½Å¼º°¡Á· Die heilige Familie¡µ(1845)À» Æì³Â´Ù. ±×µéÀÇ ´ÙÀ½ Àú¼­ ¡´µ¶ÀÏ À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â Die deutsche Ideologie¡µ´Â ¿ª»çÀÇ °¢ ´Ü°è¿¡¼­ Áö¹è°è±ÞÀÌ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ °æÁ¦Àû ÀÌÀÍÀ» µµ¸ðÇϱâ À§ÇØ »çȸ°øµ¿Ã¼¸¦ ±¸Á¶È­ÇÑ ¹æ½ÄµéÀ» ±Ô¸íÇÔÀ¸·Î½á ¿ª»çÀû À¯¹°·ÐÀ» óÀ½À¸·Î ¿ÏÀüÇÏ°Ô Á¦½ÃÇϰí ÀÖÁö¸¸, ¾î¶² ÃâÆÇ¾÷ÀÚµµ ¼±¶æ ³ª¼­Áö ¾Ê¾Æ µÎ »ç¶÷ÀÇ ÀÏ»ý ³»³» ºûÀ» º¸Áö ¸øÇß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÁÖ¿ä ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿ÁöµµÀÚµé°úÀÇ ´ë°áÀ» ÅëÇØ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ °ø»êÁÖÀÇ »ç»óÀ» È®¸³½ÃÄѳª°¬´Ù. 1846³â ±×´Â ºôÇ︧ ¹ÙÀÌÆ²¸µÀÇ µµ´öÁÖÀÇÀû ŵµ¸¦ ȤÆòÇϸ鼭 ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸ¸¦ ¶Ù¾î³Ñ¾î °ø»êÁÖÀÇ ´Ü°è·Î °ðÀå ºñ¾àÇÒ ¼ö ¾øÀ¸¸ç, ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿Àº À±¸®Àû ±¸È£°¡ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó °úÇÐÀûÀÎ ±Ù°Å¸¦ ÇÊ¿ä·Î ÇÑ´Ù°í ¿ª¼³Çß´Ù.

¡´Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ ºó°ï Das Elend der Philosophie¡µ(1847)Àº ÇÇ¿¡¸£ Á¶Á¦ÇÁ ÇÁ·çµ¿ÀÇ ¡´ºó°ïÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ Philosophie de la misère¡µ(1846)À» ³í¹ÚÇÑ °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ÇÁ·çµ¿ÀÌ °æÁ¦Ã¼Á¦ÀÇ ´ë¸³°³³äµé·ÎºÎÅÍ ´ÜÁ¡À» Áö¾çÇϰí ÀåÁ¡À» µÇ»ì¸®·Á ³ë·ÂÇß´ø ¹Ý¸é, ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â °è±ÞÅõÀï¿¡ »óÈ£ ÃæÁ·Àû Ÿ°áÁ¡Àº ÀÖÀ» ¼ö ¾øÀ¸¸ç »çȸ°øµ¿Ã¼ÀÇ ±¸Á¶´Â »ý»ê·Â°ú »ý»ê°ü°è¿¡ ÀÇÇØ °áÁ¤µÇ´Â ¿ª»çÀÇ ÀϽÃÀûÀÎ Çö»óÀÏ »ÓÀ̶ó°í ¹Ý¹ÚÇß´Ù. ¸Ëµ¹Àº ºÀ°Ç¿µÁÖÀÇ Áö¹è¸¦, Áõ±â±â°üÀº »ê¾÷ÀÚº»°¡ÀÇ Áö¹è¸¦ À̲ø¾î³Â´Ù´Â ¼³¸íÀ̾ú´Ù. ÇÁ·çµ¿ÀÇ Ã߷оç½ÄÀº ¿ª»çÀÇ ±âº»¹ýÄ¢À» ÆÄ¾ÇÇÏ´Â µ¥ ½ÇÆÐÇÑ ¼ÒºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾ÆÀû »çȸÀνÄÀ¸·Î ¿©°ÜÁ³´Ù.

»ç°ÇµéÀÇ ±âÀÌÇÑ ÀüÈİü°è°¡ ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀ» ź»ý½ÃÄ×´Ù. 1847³â 6¿ù µ¶Àϰè À̹Π¼ö°ø¾÷ÀÚµé·Î ±¸¼ºµÈ 'ÀÇÀε¿¸Í'(ëùìÑÔÒØï)ÀÌ ·±´ø¿¡¼­ ȸÇÕÀ» °®°í Á¤Ä¡Àû °­·É äÅÃÀ» °áÀÇÇß´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â À̵é·ÎºÎÅÍ Âü¿©ÀÇ ¿äûÀ» ¹Þ¾Ò°í ¼÷°í ³¡¿¡ µ¿·á ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í µ¿¸Í¿¡ °¡ÀÔÇß´Ù. ÀÇÀε¿¸ÍÀº '°ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ µ¿¸Í'À¸·Î ¸íĪÀ» º¯°æÇÑ µÚ ¹ÎÁÖÀû ÇåÀåÀ» Á¦Á¤Çß´Ù. Á¤°­ ÀÛ¼ºÀ» À§ÀÓ¹ÞÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º´Â 1847³â 12¿ù Áß¼øºÎÅÍ 1848³â 1¿ù±îÁö Á¤°­ÀÇ ÃʾÈÀÛ¾÷¿¡ ¸ôµÎÇß´Ù. ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀº "Áö±Ý±îÁöÀÇ ¸ðµç ¿ª»ç´Â °è±ÞÅõÀïÀÇ ¿ª»çÀÌ´Ù"¶ó´Â ¸íÁ¦¸¦ ÅëÇØ ¡´µ¶ÀÏ À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â¡µ¿¡¼­ Á¤¸³µÈ À¯¹°»ç°üÀ» ¿ä¾àÇÏ°í °è±Þ»çȸ´Â ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ½Â¸®¿¡ µû¶ó ¿ª»ç¿¡¼­ ÀÚÃ븦 °¨Ãß°Ô µÉ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¼±¾ðÀº '¼Ò¿Ü'·ùÀÇ ¹Ú¾àÇÑ Ã߷п¡ ±Ù°ÅÇÑ ¸ðµç »çȸÁÖÀÇ ÇüŸ¦ ºñÆÇÇϰí À¯ÅäÇÇ¾Æ »çȸ¸¦ ÁöÇâÇÑ °øµ¿Ã¼Àû ½ÇÇèµéÀ» °è±ÞÅõÀïÀ» ¹«¸¶½ÃŰ´Â '¹Ýµ¿Àû ºÐÆÄ'·Î °£ÁÖÇØ ´ÜÈ£È÷ °ÅºÎÇßÀ¸¸ç ´©Áø°ú¼¼, »ó¼ÓÀÇ ÆóÁö·ÎºÎÅÍ ¾Æµ¿ÀÇ ¹«»ó±³À°¿¡ À̸£±â±îÁö °ø»êÁÖÀÇ »çȸ·Î ³ª¾Æ°¡´Â ù ´Ü°è·Î¼­ 10°³ÀÇ Áï°¢ÀûÀÎ Á¶Ä¡¸¦ Á¦½ÃÇß´Ù. ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀº "ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ°¡ ÀÒÀ» °ÍÀº ¼Ó¹ÚÀÇ »ç½½¹Û¿¡´Â ¾ø´Ù. ±×µéÀº ¼¼°è¸¦ ¾òÀ» °ÍÀÌ´Ù. ¸¸±¹ÀÇ ³ëµ¿ÀÚ¿© ´Ü°áÇ϶ó"´Â ¸»·Î ³¡À» ¸Î´Â´Ù.

1848³âÃÊÀÇ ¸î °³¿ù µ¿¾È ÇÁ¶û½º¡¤ÀÌÅ»¸®¾Æ¡¤¿À½ºÆ®¸®¾Æ¿¡¼­ µ¹¿¬È÷ Çõ¸íÀÌ Ã˹ߵǾú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÓ½ÃÁ¤ºÎÀÇ ÃÊûÀ» ¹Þ¾Æ ÆÄ¸®·Î ¶°³µ´Âµ¥ º§±â¿¡ ´ç±¹À¸·ÎºÎÅÍ Ãß¹æ·ÉÀÌ ³»·ÁÁö±â ÀüÀÇ ½Ã±âÀûÀýÇÑ °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ±×·¯³ª µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ¸Á¸íÀÚµéÀº ¹«·ÂÀ¸·Î Á¶±¹À» ÇØ¹æ½ÃŰÀÚ´Â °Ô¿À¸£Å© Ç츣º£Å©ÀÇ ¼±µ¿¿¡ ¹Ý´ëÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º·ÎºÎÅÍ ¸Ö¾îÁ®°¬´Ù. ¿À½ºÆ®¸®¾Æ¿Í µ¶ÀÏ¿¡¼­ Çõ¸íÀÌ °¡¿­µÇ°í ÀÖÀ» ¶§ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¶óÀζõÆ®·Î µÇµ¹¾Æ¿Ô´Ù. Ä븥¿¡¼­ ±×´Â ³ëµ¿ÀÚ°è±ÞÀÌ ¹ÎÁÖÀû ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾ÆÁö¿Í ¿¬ÇÕÀ» ÀÌ·ç¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ±×´Â ³ëµ¿ÀÚµ¿¸Í ÁöµµÀÚµéÀÇ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ Çõ¸í³ë¼±¿¡ Á¦µ¿À» °¡ÇÏ°í ³ëµ¿ÀÚ°è±ÞÀº ÇÁ¶ûũǪ¸£Æ® ÀÇȸ¿¡ ´ëÇ¥¸¦ ÆÄ°ßÇÏÁö ¸»¾Æ¾ß ÇÒ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ¿ª¼³Çß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °ßÇØ´Â ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð¡µÀÌ À¯º¸µÇ¾î¾ß ÇÏ¸ç °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ µ¿¸ÍÀº ÇØÃ¼µÇ¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ °ßÇØ¿Í ÀÏÄ¡Çß´Ù. 1849³â 6¿ù Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â »õ·ÎÀÌ Ã¢°£µÈ ¡´½Å(ãæ)¶óÀÎ ½Å¹® Neue Rheinische Zeitung¡µÀ» ÅëÇØ ÀÔÇåÀû ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀÇ¿Í ·¯½Ã¾Æ¿ÍÀÇ °³ÀüÀ» Ã˱¸Çß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ³ëµ¿ÀÚµ¿¸ÍÀÇ ±ÞÁøÆÄ ÁöµµÀÚ ¾Èµå·¹¾Æ½º °íÆ®¼£Å©°¡ üÆ÷µÇ¾úÀ» ¶§ ±×¸¦ ´ë½ÅÇØ ¶óÀζõÆ® ¹ÎÁÖÀÇȸ¸¦ â¼³ÇßÀ¸¸ç(1848. 8), ±¹¿ÕÀÌ º£¸¦¸°ÀÇ ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ÀÇȸ¸¦ ÇØ»ê½ÃŰÀÚ ÁöÇÏÀúÇ׿À» µ½±â À§ÇØ ¹«±â¿Í º´·ÂÀ» ²ø¾î¸ð¾Ò´Ù.

ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀû ºÎ¸£Á־ƵéÀº ¡´½Å¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÈÄ¿øÀ» Áß´ÜÇß°í Ä«¸¦ ÀÚ½ÅÀº ³³¼¼°ÅºÎÀÇ Á¶ÀåÀ» ºñ·ÔÇÑ ¿©·¯ ÇøÀǸ¦ ¹Þ¾Æ ±â¼ÒµÇ¾ú´Ù. ¹ýÁ¤¿¡¼­ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ¿ÕÀÌ ºÒ¹ýÀûÀÎ ¹ÝÇõ¸í¿îµ¿¿¡ °ü¿©Çß´Ù´Â ¿äÁö·Î ÀÚ½ÅÀ» º¯È£ÇßÀ¸¸ç ¹è½É¿ø´ÜÀº È£ÀǸ¦ °¡Áö°í ¸¸ÀåÀÏÄ¡·Î ±×¸¦ ¹æ¸é½ÃÄ×´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ÃÖÈÄÀÇ Èñ¸Á ¾ø´Â ½Î¿òÀÌ ¹Ùµ§°ú µå·¹½ºµ§¿¡¼­ Ÿ¿Ã¶ú°í, 1849³â 5¿ù 16ÀÏ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô Ãß¹æ·ÉÀÌ ³»·ÁÁ³´Ù. ºÓ°Ô ÀμâµÈ ¡´½Å¶óÀÎ ½Å¹®¡µÀÇ Æó°£È£´Â ¼¾¼¼À̼ÇÀ» ºÒ·¯ÀÏÀ¸Ä×´Ù.

Ãʱ⠷±´ø ½Ã´ë

ÆÄ¸®·ÎºÎÅÍ ´Ù½Ã Çѹø Ãß¹æµÈ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â 1847³â 8¿ù ·±´øÀ¸·Î ÇâÇß°í ·±´øÀº ±×ÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· Á¤ÂøÁö°¡ µÇ¾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀû ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ¿Í Á¦ÈÞÇÏ·Á´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ °èȹÀÌ ¹«À§·Î µ¹¾Æ°£ °ÍÀ» ¸ø³» ¾Æ½¬¿öÇϸ鼭 ÀçÂ÷ ·±´øÀÇ °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ µ¿¸Í¿¡ ÇÕ·ùÇß°í, ¾à 1³â µ¿¾È º¸´Ù ´ë´ãÇÑ Çõ¸íÁ¤Ã¥À» ÃßÁøÇÏ°Ô µÈ´Ù. ±×´Â °æÁ¦ÀûÀÎ À§±â°¡ °ð Çõ¸í¿îµ¿À» ¼Ò»ý½Ã۸®¶ó°í ±â´ëÇßÀ¸³ª ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ±â´ë°¡ ½Ãµé¾îÁöÀÚ ½º½º·Î 'Çõ¸íÀÇ ¿¬±Ý¼ú»ç'¶ó°í ºÒ·¶´ø »ç¶÷µé, Áï Á÷Á¢ÇൿÀ» ÅëÇØ Çõ¸íÀÇ µµ·¡¸¦ ¾Õ´ç±æ °ÍÀ» ÁÖÀåÇß´ø ¾Æ¿ì±¸½ºÆ® Æù ºô¸®È÷¿Í °°Àº °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚµé°ú ´Ù½Ã Çѹø ´ëÄ¡ÇÏ°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â 1850³â 9¿ù À̵éÀÌ À¯¹°·ÐÀ» ÀÌ»óÁÖÀÇ·Î ´ëüÇß´Ù°í ºñÆÇÇϸ鼭 ´ÙÀ½°ú °°ÀÌ ±â¼úÇß´Ù.

"±×µéÀº ½ÇÁ¦ÀûÀÎ Á¶°ÇµéÀ» µµ¿Ü½ÃÇÑ Ã¤ ¼ø¼öÀÇÁö¸¦ Çõ¸íÀÇ ¿øµ¿·ÂÀ¸·Î °£ÁÖÇÑ´Ù. ¿ì¸®°¡ ³ëµ¿Àڵ鿡°Ô '¿©·¯ºÐµéÀº ´Ü¼øÈ÷ ¿©·¯ºÐµéÀÇ ¿©°ÇÀ» °³¼±½Ã۱â À§Çؼ­°¡ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ½º½º·Î¸¦ º¯È­½Ã۰í Á¤Ä¡Àû ±Ç·ÂÀ» ºÐ´ãÇϱâ À§ÇØ ¼ö½Ê ³â °£ÀÇ ³»¶õ°ú ±¹Á¦ÀüÀïÀ» °Þ¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù'°í ¸»ÇÏ´Â ¹Ý¸é ±×µéÀº ÀÌ¿Í ´ëÁ¶ÀûÀ¸·Î '¿ì¸®´Â Áï½Ã ±Ç·ÂÀ» ÀïÃëÇØ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù'°í ºÎÃß±â°í ÀÖ´Ù."

±ÞÁøÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ ³ëµ¿ÀÚ ±³À°µ¿¸ÍÀÇ Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐ °­»ç°¡ µÇ±â¸¦ ÀÚóÇß´Ù¸ç ±×¸¦ ºñ²¿¾Ò°í, ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚ ¸ðÀÓ Ãâ¼® Ƚ¼ö´Â Á¡Â÷ ÁÙ¾îµé¾ú´Ù. 1852³â¿¡ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â Ä븥¿¡¼­ Á¤ºÎÀüº¹ ÇøÀǷΠüÆ÷µÈ 11¸íÀÇ °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀ» º¯È£ÇÏ´Â µ¥ È¥½ÅÀÇ ÈûÀ» ±â¿ï¿´À¸¸ç À̸¦ À§ÇÏ¿© ÆÊÇ÷¿À» ÀÛ¼ºÇÏ ±âµµ Çß´Ù. ¡´·çÀÌ º¸³ªÆÄ¸£Æ®ÀÇ ºê·ò¸Þ¸£ 18ÀÏ Der Achtzehnte Brumaire des Louis Bonaparte¡µÀÌ ¾º¾îÁø °Íµµ À̹«·ÆÀε¥ ¿©±â¼­ ±×´Â ³ó¹Î°è±ÞÀÇ ÁöÁö¸¦ ¹ÙÅÁÀ¸·Î °ü·áÁÖÀÇÀû Àý´ë±¹°¡°¡ Çü¼ºµÇ´Â °úÁ¤À» ³¯Ä«·Ó°Ô ºÐ¼®Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌÈÄÀÇ 12³â°£Àº ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ç¥Çö¿¡ µû¸£ÀÚ¸é µÎ »ç¶÷¿¡°Ô '°í¸³'ÀÇ ½Ã°£ÀÌ µÇ¾ú´Ù. 1850~64³â ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¹°ÁúÀûÀÎ ±ÃÇ̰ú Á¤½ÅÀûÀÎ °íÅë ¼Ó¿¡¼­ »ì¾Ò´Ù. Àç¿øÀº °í°¥µÇ°í ´Ü ÇѹøÀ» »©°í´Â ¼öÀÔÀÌ ÀÖ´Â Á÷¾÷À» °¡ÁöÁö ¸øÇß´Ù. 1850³â 3¿ù Ä«¸¦°ú ¿¹´Ï, ±×¸®°í 4¸íÀÇ ÀÚ³àµé¿¡°Ô °­Á¦Åð°Å¸í·ÉÀÌ ³»·ÁÁ³°í ÀÚ»êÀº ¾Ð·ùµÇ¾ú´Ù. ÀÚ³àµé Áß ¸î¸îÀº Á×¾ú´Ù. ±×Áß¿¡´Â ±×°¡ 'ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸÀÇ Èñ»ýÀÚ'¶ó°í À̾߱âÇÑ ¾Æµé ±Íµµ¿Í µþ ÇÁ¶õÄ¡½ºÄ«°¡ Æ÷ÇԵǾî ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ¿¹´Ï´Â ¾ÆÀ̵éÀÇ °üÀ» »ì µ·À» ¸¶·ÃÇÏ·Á°í °ÅÀÇ ¹ÌÄ£ µíÀÌ ¶Ù¾î´Ù³æ´Ù. 6³âÀ» ´ëºÎºÐ »§°ú °¨ÀÚ·Î ¿¬¸íÇÏ¸ç °¡Á·Àº ¼ÒÈ£ÀÇ ¹æ 2Ä­¿¡¼­ »îÀ» ²Ù·Á³ª°¬°í, ¾ÆÀ̵éÀº ¸ô·Á¿Â ä±ÇÀڵ鿡°Ô "¸¶¸£Å©½º ¼±»ý´ÔÀº 2Ãþ¿¡ °è½ÃÁö ¾Ê¾Æ¿ä"¶ó´Â °ÅÁþ¸»À» ÇØ¾ß¸¸ Çß´Ù. ºúÀïÀ̵éÀ» ÇÇÇØ Ä«¸¦Àº ¸Çü½ºÅÍ·Î µµ¸ÁÇØ¾ß Çß°í ¾Æ³» ¿¹´Ï´Â ½Å°æ¼è¾à¿¡ ½Ã´Þ·È´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ¿ª°æÀÇ ½Ã°£À» ÅëÇØ ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÀçÁ¤ÀûÀÎ ÈÄ¿øÀ» ¾Æ³¢Áö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. óÀ½¿¡´Â ¸Çü½ºÅÍ ¼ÒÀç ¾î¸Õ¾Øµå¿¨°Ö½º»ç(Þä)ÀÇ Æò»ç¹«¿ø¿¡ ºÒ°úÇßÀ¸¹Ç·Î µ·ÀÇ ¾×¼ö°¡ ¸¹Áö ¾Ê¾ÒÁö¸¸ 1864³â ±×°¡ µ¿¾÷ÀÚ°¡ µÇ¾úÀ» ¶§´Â Áö¿ø±ÝÀÇ ±Ô¸ðµµ Ä¿Á³´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿¨°Ö½º¿ÍÀÇ ¿ìÁ¤À» ÀÚ¶ûÀ¸·Î ¿©°å°í ±×¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ¾î¶°ÇÑ ºñÆÇµµ ¿ë³³ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. ¾Æ³»ÀÇ Ä£Áöµé°ú Ä£±¸ ºôÇ︧ º¼ÇÁÀÇ À¯»êÀ¸·Î ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °æÁ¦Àû °íÅëÀº Å©°Ô °æ°¨µÇ¾ú´Ù.

¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¹Ì±¹¿¡ ºñ±³Àû Áö¼ÓÀûÀÎ ¼öÀÔ¿øÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ¾ú´Âµ¥, Ǫ¸®¿¡ÁÖÀÇ¿¡ °ø°¨Çϰí ÀÖ´ø ¡´´º¿å Æ®¸®ºå The New York Tribune¡µÀÇ À¯·´ Åë½Å¿øÀÌ µÈ °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. 1851~62³â Ä«¸¦Àº 500Æí¿¡ °¡±î¿î ±â»ç¿Í ³í¼³µéÀ» ±â°íÇϸ鼭(±×Áß 1/4Àº ¿¨°Ö½º Á¦°ø) Àεµ¿Í Áß±¹, ¿µ±¹°ú ½ºÆäÀÎÀÇ »çȸ¿îµ¿°ú ¼Ò¿äµéÀ» ºÐ¼®¡¤°ËÅäÇß´Ù. 1859³â ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â °æÁ¦À̷п¡ °üÇÑ ÃÖÃÊÀÇ Àú¼úÀÎ ¡´Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐ ºñÆÇ Zur Kritik der politischen Okonomie¡µÀ» ¿Ï¼ºÇß´Ù. ¡´Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐ ºñÆÇ¡µÀÇ ¼­¹®¿¡´Â À¯¹°»ç°ü¿¡ µµ´ÞÇÏ°Ô µÈ ³í¸®°úÁ¤ÀÌ »ó¼¼ÇÏ°Ô ¼³¸íµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù. "¹°ÁúÀûÀÎ »ý»ê¾ç½ÄÀº »îÀÇ »çȸÀû¡¤Á¤Ä¡Àû¡¤Á¤½ÅÀû Â÷¿øµéÀ» °áÁ¤ÇÑ´Ù. Àΰ£ÀÇ ÀǽÄÀÌ ±×µéÀÇ Á¸À縦 ±ÔÁ¤Áþ´Â °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ¹Ý´ë·Î ±×µéÀÇ »çȸÀû »ýȰÀÌ ÀǽÄÀ» Á¿ìÇÑ´Ù."

Ä«¸¦Àº ´ë¿µ¹Ú¹°°ü¿¡¼­ °æÁ¦¡¤»çȸ»ç ¿¬±¸¿¡ ¸ôµÎÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ» ÁÖ¿äÀϰú·Î »ï¾ÒÀ¸¸ç µ¶ÀÏÀÇ »õ·Î¿î ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿¿¡ µ¿ÂüÇØ´Þ¶ó´Â Æä¸£µð³­Æ® ¶ó»ìÀÇ ±ÇÀ¯¸¦ °ÅºÎÇß´Ù. ¶ó»ìÀº È¥ÀÚ¼­ 'Àü(îï)µ¶ÀÏ ³ëµ¿ÀÚµ¿¸Í'ÀÇ °á¼º¿¡ Âø¼öÇß´Ù.

Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î

1864³â Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î(±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸ)ÀÇ Ã¢¼³°ú ´õºÒ¾î ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Á¤Ä¡Àû °í¸³µµ ³¡ÀÌ ³µ´Ù. ±×´Â ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ Ã¢¼³ÀÚµµ ȸÀåµµ ¾Æ´Ï¾úÁö¸¸ °ð ÇùȸÀÇ Á¤½ÅÀûÀÎ ÁöÁÖ°¡ µÇ¾ú´Ù. ÃÖÃÊÀÇ °ø½ÄȸÀÇ´Â 1864³â 9¿ù 28ÀÏ ·±´øÀÇ ¼¼ÀÎÆ® ¸¶Æ¾ Ȧ¿¡¼­ ¿µ±¹ ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕÀÇ ÁöµµÀÚµé°ú ÇÁ¶û½º ³ëµ¿ÀÚ ´ëÇ¥µé¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ¼ÒÁýµÇ¾ú´Ù. ÇÁ¶û½ºÀÇ Áß°³ÀÎÀ» ÅëÇØ µ¶ÀÏ ´ëÇ¥ ÀÚ°ÝÀ¸·Î ÃÊûµÇ¾ú´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ħ¹¬À» ÁöŰ¸ç ¿¬´Ü¿¡ ÀÚ¸®Çϰí ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. °­·É°ú ÇåÀåÀ» äÅÃÇϱâ À§ÇÑ À§¿øÈ¸°¡ ¼³Ä¡µÇ°í ¸¸Á·½º·´Áö ¸øÇÑ ¸¹Àº ÃʾȵéÀÌ Á¦ÃâµÈ ÈÄ ºÐ°úÀ§¿øÈ¸¿¡ ¸ö´ã°í ÀÖ´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â dzºÎÇÑ ¾ð·Ð°èÀÇ °æÇèÀ» ¹ÙÅÁÀ¸·Î °­·É°ú ÇåÀåÀ» ±âÃÊÇß´Ù. ±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸÀÇ ÀӽñÔÄ¢Àº ±×ÀÇ ´Ù¸¥ Àú¼úµé°ú´Â ´Þ¸® °è±Þ°£ÀÇ Á¦ÈÞÁ¤Ã¥°ú ÀÇȸÀÔ¹ýÀÇ ±àÁ¤ÀûÀÎ Ãø¸éÀ» °­Á¶Çß´Ù. ¿µ±¹ÀÇ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â Á¡ÁøÀûÀÎ ³ë·ÂÀ» ÅëÇØ ±¹°¡Àû Â÷¿øÀÇ Á¤Ä¡±Ç·ÂÀ» ȹµæÇÏ°Ô µÉ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ³»´Ùº¸¾Ò´Ù. ÇùȸÀÇ È°µ¿Àº 1ÁÖÀÏ¿¡µµ ¸î ¹ø¾¿ ȸÇÕÀÌ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁö´Â µî Å©°Ô Ȱ¼ºÈ­µÇ¾ú°í, ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÃÑȸÀÇ È¸¿øÀÌÀÚ µ¶ÀÏ Áö¿ªÀÇ Åë½Å°£»ç·Î¼­ ´Ù¾çÇÑ ÆÄ¹ú°ú °æÇâµéÀÇ È­ÇÕÀ» ÀÌ·ç¾î³»´Â º¸±â µå¹® ÀÚÁúÀ» ¹ßÈÖÇß´Ù. ³¯·Î ³ô¾ÆÁ®°¡´Â ¸í¼º°ú ÇÔ²² 1869³â Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ ±Ô¸ð´Â ¾à 80¸¸ ȸ¿øÀ¸·Î È®ÀåµÇ¾ú°í °¢ Áö¿ª ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕÀ» À§ÇÑ ºÐ±ÔÁ¶Á¤¿¡ °ü¿©ÇÔÀ¸·Î½á »ó´çÇÑ ¼º°øÀ» °ÅµÎ±âµµ Çß´Ù.

ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀº Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¸¦ ±¹Á¦ÀûÀÎ Àι°·Î ¸¸µç »ç°ÇÀ̾ú´Ù. 1870³â ÇÁ¶û½º-ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ÀüÀïÀÌ ¹ß¹ßÇÏÀÚ µ¶ÀÏ ÀÇȸÀÇ »çȸÁÖÀÇ ¼¼·ÂÀº ÀüÀï°øÃ¤¾È ÅõÇ¥¸¦ °ÅºÎÇß´Ù. óÀ½¿¡ Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ´Â ÇÁ¶û½º-ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ÀüÀïÀ» µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ¹æ¾îÀüÀïÀ¸·Î ±ÔÁ¤ÇßÀ¸³ª ÆÄ¸®°¡ ÇÔ¶ôµÈ ÈÄ µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ¹è»ó¿ä±¸°¡ Áö³ªÄ£ ¼öÁØ¿¡ À̸£ÀÚ ºÐÀ§±â´Â ¹ÝÀüµÇ¾ú´Ù. ÆÄ¸®¿¡¼­ Æøµ¿ÀÌ ÀϾ°í ÄÚ¹ÀÀÌ ¼±Æ÷µÇ¾úÀ» ¶§ ÀüÆøÀûÀÎ ÁöÁö¸¦ Ç¥¸íÇß´ø ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â À̵ëÇØ 5¿ù 30ÀÏ ÄÚ¹ÀÀÌ ºÐ¼âµÇÀÚ 'ÇÁ¶û½º ³»Àü'À̶ó´Â Á¦¸íÀ¸·Î ¼º¸í¼­¸¦ ¹ßÇ¥ÇÑ´Ù.

"¿ª»ç´Â ÀÌÅä·Ï À§´ëÇÑ °Í¿¡ ÇÊÀûÇÒ ¸¸ÇÑ »ç·Ê¸¦ °¡Áö°í ÀÖÁö ¾Ê´Ù¡¦¡¦ ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀÇ ¼ø±³ÀÚµéÀº ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÀÇ °¡½¿ ¼Ó¿¡ ¿µ¿øÈ÷ »ì¾Æ ÀÖÀ» °ÍÀÌ´Ù."

¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀ» Àηù ÃÖÃÊÀÇ 'ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾Æ µ¶Àç'·Î Æò°¡ÇßÀ¸¸ç ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ À̸§Àº ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀÇ Çõ¸íÁ¤½Å°ú µ¿ÀǾ µÇ¾ú´Ù.

ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀº ±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸÀÇ ³»ºÎ°¥µîÀ» ÁõÆø½ÃÄÑ °á±¹ ºØ±«¸¦ ÃÊ·¡ÇÏ´Â °è±â·Î ÀÛ¿ëÇß´Ù. °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ ÀÇÀåÀ» Áö³Â´ø ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕÁÖÀÇÀÚ Á¶Áö ¿ÀÀú´Â ÄÚ¹À¿¡ °¥Ã¤¸¦ º¸³½ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã³½ÅÀ» ºÒ¸¸½º·¯¿öÇß°í 1867³âÀÇ ¼±°Å¹ý °³Á¤¾ÈÀ¸·Î Á¤Ä¡Âü¿©ÀÇ ÆøÀÌ ³Ð¾îÁø ¿µ±¹ÀÇ ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕµéÀº ÀÚÀ¯´ç°úÀÇ Çù·ÂÀ» ÅëÇØ ½ÇÁúÀûÀÎ ¼º°ú¸¦ ¾ò¾î³»±â¸¦ Èñ¸ÁÇß´Ù. ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕ ÁöµµÀÚµéÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ´Éº¯À» °ÅÃßÀ彺·¯¿î °É¸²µ¹·Î »ý°¢Çß°í ÀÚÀ¯ÁÖÀÇÀڵ鿡°Ô ¸Å¼öµÇ¾ú´Ù´Â ±×ÀÇ ºñ³­¿¡ ´ëÇØ ºÐ°³Çß´Ù.

Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î ³» ÁÂÆÄÀÇ µµÀüÀº ·¯½Ã¾ÆÀÇ ¹«Á¤ºÎÁÖÀÇÀÚ ¹ÌÇÏÀÏ ¾Ë·º»êµå·ÎºñÄ¡ ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀÇ ÁÖµµÇÏ¿¡ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù (¡æ »öÀÎ : ¹ÙÄí´Ñ). ½Ãº£¸®¾Æ À¯Çü°ú ½¢ÇÑ °¨¿Á»ýȰÀ» °æÇèÇÑ Çõ¸í°¡·Î¼­ '³ëÈ£ÇÏ´Â ÆøÇ³¿ì¿Í »çÀÚÀÇ Æ÷È¿'·Î ºñÀ¯µÇ´Â ¿õº¯ÀÇ ´ë°¡À̱⵵ Çß´ø ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº ¹µ»ç¶÷µéÀ» »ç·ÎÀâÀ» ¸¸ÇÑ ¸Å·ÂÀ» °¡Áø Àι°À̾ú´Ù. ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Áö¼º¿¡ Âù»ç¸¦ º¸³»±â´Â ÇßÀ¸³ª ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ ÀÚ½ÅÀ» ·¯½Ã¾Æ ½ºÆÄÀÌ·Î ¸ÅµµÇß´ø »ç½ÇÀ» ÀØÀ» ¼ö´Â ¾ø¾ú´Ù. ±×°¡ º¸±â¿¡ Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ±ÇÀ§ÁÖÀÇÀÚÀÌÀÚ ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î ÃÑȸ¸¦ ³ëµ¿ÀÚ Áö¹è¸¦ À§ÇÑ °³ÀÎÀÇ ÅÍÀüÀ¸·Î Å»¹Ù²Þ½ÃŰ·Á´Â ±³¸¸ÇÑ À¯´ëÀÎÀ̾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ Áß¾ÓÁý±ÇÈ­¸¦ ºñ·ÔÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿©·¯ À̷п¡ ¹Ý¹ßÇß°í ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â ±âÁ¸ ÀÇȸÁ¦µµ ³»¿¡¼­ ÇϳªÀÇ Á¤´çÀ¸·Î ±â´ÉÇØ¾ß Çϸç ÀÏ´Ü ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ ±¹°¡°¡ Àüº¹µÈ ´ÙÀ½¿¡ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ® ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ Á¤±ÇÀ» ¼ö¸³ÇØ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â ½Å³ä¿¡µµ ºÎÁ¤ÀûÀ̾ú´Ù.

¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº Çõ¸í°¡µéÀÇ ÀÓ¹«´Â 'ÆÄ±«'¿¡ ÀÖ´Ù°í »ý°¢Çß´Ù. ±×´Â ¼±Áø»ê¾÷±¹°¡ÀÇ ³ª¾àÇÑ ³ëµ¿Àڵ麸´Ù ·¯½Ã¾Æ ³ó¹ÎÀÇ Á¦¾îÇϱâ Èûµç Çõ¸íÀû º»´É¿¡ ±â´ë¸¦ °É°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ÇлýµéÀÌ Çõ¸íÀÇ ÁßÃß¼¼·ÂÀÌ µÇ±â¸¦ Èñ¸ÁÇß´ø ±×´Â ÀÌÅ»¸®¾Æ¡¤½ºÀ§½º¡¤ÇÁ¶û½º¿¡¼­ û³â Áö¼ºÀεéÀÇ ¸¹Àº È£ÀÀÀ» ¾ò¾ú°í ºñ¹Ð°á»çÀÎ '±¹Á¦»çȸ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀǵ¿¸Í'À» Á¶Á÷Çß´Ù. »çȸ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀǵ¿¸ÍÀº 1869³â ½ºÀ§½º ¹ÙÁ©¿¡¼­ Á¦1Â÷ ±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸ°¡ °³ÃֵǾúÀ» ¶§ °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸÀÇ Áö¹è±Ç¿¡ µµÀüÀåÀ» ³ÂÁö¸¸ À̵éÀÇ °¡ÀÔÀ» »çÀü ÀúÁö½ÃŰ·Á´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¼ÕÀÌ Á¶±Ý ´õ »¡¶ú´Ù. ¹ÙÄí´ÑÁÖÀÇÀڵ鿡°Ô ÆÄ¸® ÄÚ¹ÀÀº Çõ¸íÀû Á÷Á¢ÇൿÀÇ º»º¸±â¿Í °°¾Ò°í Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ±ÇÀ§ÁÖÀÇÀû °ø»êÁÖÀǸ¦ ¹Ý¹ÚÇÒ ¼ö Àִ ȣ±â¸¦ Á¦°øÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ¹ÌÇÏÀÏ ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀº ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î ³»ºÎ¿¡ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ Á¶Á÷À» ±¸ÃàÇØ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ¸¦ °ø°ÝÇϱ⠽ÃÀÛÇß°í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Æí¿¡¼­´Â ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀÌ Çù¹Ú°ú »ìÀÎÀ» ÀÏ»ï¾Æ¿Â ·¯½Ã¾ÆÀÇ Çлý Çõ¸í°¡ ¼¼¸£°ÔÀÌ ³×Â÷¿¹ÇÁ¿Í ¿¬·çµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù´Â »ç½ÇÀ» °øÇ¥Çß´Ù.

º°´Ù¸¥ ÁöÁö ±â¹Ýµµ ¾øÀÌ ¹«Á¤ºÎÁÖÀÇ ÁÂÆÄ¿¡ ´ëÇ×ÇØ ¼± ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¹ÙÄí´Ñ¿¡°Ô ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ ÁÖµµ±ÇÀ» »©¾Ñ±â°Ô µÇÁö³ª ¾ÊÀ»±î µÎ·Á¿öÇß´Ù. ÇÑÆíÀ¸·Î´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ¿¬±¸·Î µÇµ¹¾Æ°¡ ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀÇ ÁýÇÊÀ» ¸¶¹«¸®ÇÏ°í ½ÍÀº »ý°¢µµ °£ÀýÇß´Ù. 1872³â ³×´ú¶õµå ÇìÀ̱׿¡¼­ ÃÖÃÊ·Î ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î ÀüüȸÀÇ¿¡ Âü¼®ÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¹ÙÄí´ÑÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀ» ÆÐ¹è½ÃŰ´Â µ¥ ¼º°øÇßÀ¸¸ç ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÀÌ¿Í º¸Á¶¸¦ ¸ÂÃß¾î °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ¸¦ ·±´ø¿¡¼­ ´º¿åÀ¸·Î ÀÌÀü½ÃŰÀÚ´Â ÀǰßÀ» Á¦½ÃÇß´Ù. ¹ÙÄí´ÑÀÇ ÃßÁ¾ÀÚµéÀº ÃàÃâµÇ¾úÀ¸³ª Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ ¿µÇâ·ÂÀº ±â¿ï¾î°¬°í 1876³â Çʶóµ¨ÇǾƿ¡¼­ ¸¶Ä§³» ÇØÃ¼µÇ±â¿¡ À̸¥´Ù.

Á¦1ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³Î ÀÌÈÄÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· 10³â µ¿¾È ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã¢ÀÛ´É·ÂÀº ±Þ°ÝÈ÷ °¨¼ÒµÇ¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ½º½º·Î °í¹éÇßµíÀÌ ¸¸¼ºÀûÀÎ Á¤½ÅÀÇ Ä§Ã¼¿¡ »ç·ÎÀâÇû°í ³»¸éÈ­µÈ °ü½ÉÀº °¡Á·µé¿¡°Ô ÇâÇß´Ù. ¿©ÀüÈ÷ µ¶¼­·®ÀÌ ¸¹¾Ò°í ·¯½Ã¾Æ¾î ÇнÀ¿¡ Âø¼öÇϱ⵵ ÇßÁö¸¸ ½ÇÁúÀûÀ¸·Î ¾î¶°ÇÑ ÀÛ¾÷µµ ÀÌ·ç¾î³»Áö ¸øÇß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Á¤Ä¡Àû °ßÇØ´Â ±× º¯´ö½º·¯¿òÀ¸·Î ÀÎÇØ Á¾ÀâÀ» ¼ö°¡ ¾ø°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù. ½ÉÁö¾î ±×´Â ¼Ò³â³ëµ¿ÀÇ ÆóÁö¸¦ ¹Ý´ëÇϱâ±îÁö Çß´Ù. 1875³â ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÚµé°ú µ¶ÀÏÀÇ ¶ó»ìÆÄ°¡ µ¶ÀÏ »çȸ¹ÎÁÖ´çÀ» â¼³Çϱâ À§ÇØ °íŸ¿¡¼­ ȸµ¿Çß´Ù. Æä¸£µð³­Æ® ¶ó»ìÀº »çȸÁÖÀÇÀÇ ÀÌ»óÀÌ ±âÁ¸Ã¼Á¦¿ÍÀÇ Çù·Â ¼Ó¿¡¼­ ´Þ¼ºµÉ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù°í ¹Ï¾ú´ø Àι°À̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¡´°íŸ °­·É ºñÆÇ Kritik des Gothaer Programms¡µÀ» ÅëÇØ »çȸ¹ÎÁÖ´ç °­·ÉÀÇ Áö³ªÄ£ Çö½ÇŸÇù¼ºÀ» ³í¹ÚÇß°í µ¶ÀÏ ÁöµµÀÚµéÀº ±×ÀÇ ºÐ³ë¸¦ °¡¶ó¾ÉÈ÷±â À§ÇØ ¿­°ú ¼ºÀ» ´ÙÇß´Ù.

Á¡Â÷·Î ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â À¯·´¿¡¼­ ÀüÀïÀÌ ÀϾ º¸¼ö ¹Ýµ¿ÁÖÀÇÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· º¸·çÀÎ Â÷¸£ üÁ¦¸¦ ŸµµÇϱ⸦ ¹Ù¶ú´Ù. ÀÌ ÀüÀïÀ¸·Î ³ëµ¿ÀÚ °è±ÞÀÇ Çõ¸íÀû ¿¡³ÊÁö°¡ ´Ù½Ã ¼Ò»ýµÉÁöµµ ¸ð¸¥´Ù´Â ¸·¿¬ÇÑ ±â´ë°¨¿¡¼­¿´´Ù. 1881³â Â÷¸£ ¾Ë·º»êµå¸£ 2¼¼°¡ ¾Ï»ìµÇÀÚ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ·¯½Ã¾Æ ³ª·Îµå´ÏŰÀÇ »ç½É¾ø´Â ¿ë±â¿¡ ±íÀº °¨¸íÀ» ¹Þ¾Ò´Ù. Å×·¯´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô '»óȲÀûÀ¸·Î ºÒ°¡ÇÇÇÑ ¼ö´ÜÀÇ Çϳª'·Î ¿©°ÜÁ³´Ù. ºñ·Ï Çö½ÇÁ¤Ä¡¿¡¼­ ÇÑ °ÉÀ½ ¹°·¯¼± °ÍÀº »ç½ÇÀ̾úÁö¸¸ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿¨°Ö½º°¡ ¸»Çß´ø °Íó·³ »çȸÁÖÀÇÀû ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿¿¡ ´ëÇØ ¿©ÀüÈ÷ 'µ¶Æ¯ÇÑ ¿µÇâ·Â'À» Çà»çÇϰí ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. 1879³â Áæ °Ôµå°¡ ÇÁ¶û½º »çȸÁÖÀÇ ³ëµ¿ÀÚ¿¬¸ÍÀÇ Ã¢¼³¿¡ ÁîÀ½ÇÏ¿© ·±´øÀ» ¹æ¹®, ¸¶¸£Å©½º·ÎºÎÅÍ °­·ÉÀÇ Àü¹®°ú ³»¿ë¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÚ¹®À» ¾ò¾î°¬´Ù. 1881³â¿¡´Â ¡´À×±Û·£µå Æ÷ ¿Ã England for All¡µÁö(ò¼)ÀÇ Ç ¸ÞÀ̾ ÇÏÀεå¸ÕÀÌ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿ÍÀÇ ´ë´ãÀ» ºñÁßÀÖ°Ô ´Ù·ç¾úÁö¸¸ ±×ÀÇ À̸§À» ¹àÈ÷±â¸¦ ²¨·ÁÇÏ¿© ³ë¿©¿òÀ» »ò´Ù. ¸»³âÀÇ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ´ëºÎºÐÀÇ ½Ã°£À» ÈÞ¾çÁö¿¡¼­ º¸³Â°í ¾ËÁ¦¸®±îÁö ¿©ÇàÀ» ¶°³ª±âµµ Çß´Ù. Ä«¸¦Àº ¾Æ³»(1881.12.2)¿Í Àå³à ¿¹´Ï ·Õ±¸¿¡Æ®(1883.1.11)ÀÇ Á×À½À¸·Î ºñź¿¡ Á¥¾î »ì´Ù°¡ 1883³â 3¿ù ¿µ±¹ÀÇ ·±´ø¿¡¼­ ÆóÁ¾¾çÀ¸·Î »ç¸ÁÇß´Ù.

Æò°¡

ÇÏÀ̰ÔÀÌÆ® ÇÁ¶óÀÌÈ£ÇÁÀÇ Àå·Ê½Ä¿¡¼­ ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ 'Àηù¿ª»ç ¹ßÀüÀÇ ¹ýÄ¢'°ú 'ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ »çȸ¿îµ¿ÀÇ ¹ýÄ¢'À» ¹ß°ßÇØ³Â´Ù°í ¼±¾ðÇß´Ù. "¹«¾ùº¸´Ù Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â À§´ëÇÑ Çõ¸í°¡¿´´Ù. Áõ¿ÀÀÇ ´ë»óÀÌ µÇ¾î ±Ø´ÜÀûÀÎ ºñ¹æ°ú ¸ð·«¿¡ ½Ã´Þ·È´ø ±×´Â ÀÌÁ¦ ¼ö¹é¸¸ ³ëµ¿ÀÚµéÀÇ »ç¶û°ú Á¸°æ, ¾Öµµ ¼Ó¿¡¼­ ´«À» °¨´Â´Ù."

¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô´Â ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺ÀûÀÎ ¹ÝÇ×°ú ¹«·ÂÇÑ Áö¼ºÀÌ º¹ÇյǾî ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÁÖÀ§ »ç¶÷µé¿¡°Ô ÁöÀû ±³¸¸ÇÔÀÇ ÀλóÀ» ÀüÇØÁÖ¾ú´Ù. 1846³â ·¯½Ã¾ÆÀÇ ÀÛ°¡ ÆÄº§ ¾È³ÙÄÚÇÁ´Â Åä·Ð¿¡ Âü¿©ÇÑ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¸¦ °üÂûÇÑ µÚ ÀÌ·¸°Ô ȸ»óÇß´Ù. "±×ÀÇ ¸»Åõ´Â Ç×»ó ¸í·ÉÁ¶¿¡ °¡±î¿ü°í ¹Ý·ÐÀ» ¿ëÀÎÇÏ´Â ¹ýÀÌ ¾ø¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ¸¶Ä¡ ȯ»ó ¼Ó¿¡¼­³ª ³ªÅ¸³¯ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â ¹ÎÁÖÀû µ¶ÀçÀÚ¿Í °°¾Ò´Ù." ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ´Ù¼öÀÇ Ã»Áß ¾Õ¿¡ ³ª¼­´Â °Í¿¡ ºÒÆíÇÔÀ» ´À²¼°í ÆÄ¹ú³íÀïÀÇ ºÐÀ§±â¸¦ ÁÁ¾ÆÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. ¾Æ³» ¿¹´Ï ¿ª½Ã ±×°¡ ½ÃÀ§¿¡ Âü¿©ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾ÒÀ¸¸ç °ø°øÈ¸ÀÇ ¼®»ó¿¡¼­ °ÅÀÇ À̾߱⸦ ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù°í ¹àÈ÷°í ÀÖ´Ù. ±×´Â ÀÎÅͳ»¼Å³ÎÀÇ °øµ¿ÀÌ»çȸ³ª ½Å¹®»ç °£ºÎ¸ðÀÓ°ú °°Àº ¼Ò±Ô¸ð ºÐÀ§±â¸¦ °¡Àå Æí¾ÈÇÏ°Ô ´À²¼´Ù. ±×ÀÇ ¼º°ÝÀº ¼ÒÁý´ÜÀÇ µ¿·áµé¿¡°Ô °­·ÂÇÑ ÈûÀ» ¹ßÈÖÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. µ¿½Ã¿¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ´ëµîÇÑ À§Ä¡¿¡¼­ °æÁ¦Çаú »çȸÇÐÀÇ ¿©·¯ ¹®Á¦µéÀ» ³íÀÇÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â ¸í¸ÁÀÖ´Â ÇÐÀÚµé°úÀÇ È¸ÇÕÀ» ±âÇÇÇß´Ù. ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ³ÐÀº ½Ä°ß¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿µ±¹ÀÇ ¿Ü¹«Àå°ü ÆÄ¸Ó½ºÅÏ °æÀÌ ·¯½Ã¾Æ Á¤ºÎÀÇ Ã¸ÀÚ¶ó´Â ½ÄÀÇ °­¹Ú°ü³ä¿¡ »ç·ÎÀâÇô ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸ°¡ ÀÚ½ÅÀ» 'µ· ¸¸µå´Â ±â°è'·Î Àü¶ô½ÃŰÁö ¸øÇÏ°Ô ÇÏ°Ú´Ù°í °á½ÉÇϸ鼭µµ ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ Áõ¿©¿Í ģôµéÀÇ ¿©·¯ À¯»ê¿¡ »ý°è¸¦ ÀÇÁ¸Çß´Ù.

¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿¹¼ö°¡ ¾î¸°À̵éÀ» »ç¶ûÇ߱⠶§¹®¿¡ ¿¹¼ö¸¦ Âù¾çÇÑ´Ù°í ¸»ÇÒ Á¤µµ·Î ¾ÖÁ¤ÀÌ ³ÑÄ¡´Â ¾Æ¹öÁö¿´Áö¸¸ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ »ýȰÀ̳ª °Ç°­À» µ¹º¸Áö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. ±×´Â 'ÅõÀï'À» »î°ú Á¸ÀçÀÇ ¹ýÄ¢À¸·Î °£ÁÖÇßÀ¸¸ç ¾ð¾îÀÇ ½ÀµæÁ¶Â÷µµ »îÀÇ ÅõÀï¿¡¼­ »õ·Î¿î ¹«±â¸¦ ȹµæÇÏ´Â ÀÏÀ̶ó°í »ý°¢ÇÒ Á¤µµ¿´´Ù. °³ÀÎÀûÀÎ ½À¼ºÀ̳ª »ýȰ¹æ½Ä¿¡ À־ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ¿µ¿øÇÑ ÇлýÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â µÎ Ä£±¸¿Í ÇÔ²² °Å¸®ÀÇ °¡·ÎµîÀ» ±úºÎ¼ö°í °æÂûÀÌ ¸ô·Á¿ÀÀÚ ²Ç¹«´Ï¸¦ »©´Â ¾î¸®±¤½º·¯¿î Àå³­À» Çϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ±×´Â ´ë´ÜÇÑ ¼Ò¼³±¤À¸·Î¼­ ƯÈ÷ ¿ùÅÍ ½ºÄà °æ°ú ¹ßÀÚÅ©¿¡ Ž´ÐÇß°í °¡Á·Àº ¸ðµÎ ¼ÎÀͽºÇǾîÀÇ ¿¹Âù·ÐÀÚµéÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¹´Ï »çÀÌ¿¡´Â 7¸íÀÇ Àڳడ ÀÖ¾úÀ¸³ª ¼¼ µþ¸¸ ³²°í ³ª¸ÓÁö´Â À¯³â±â¿¡ ÀÒ°í ¸»¾Ò´Ù. °¡Àå ÃѾÖÇß´ø ¿¤·¹¾Æ³ë¸£´Â ½Å°æÁúÀûÀÌ°í °¨¼ºÀûÀÎ ¼º°ÝÀ» Áö³æÀ¸¸ç ¿©¹è¿ì°¡ µÇ·Á´Â ¼Ò¸ÁÀ¸·Î ÀÎÇØ ±×¸¦ ±Ù½ÉÇÏ°Ô Çß´Ù. ¶Ç´Ù¸¥ ±×¸²ÀÚ°¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °¡Á¤»ýȰÀ» ¾îµÓ°Ô ¸¸µé¾ú´Âµ¥ Çϳà Çï·¹³× µ¥¹«Æ®°¡ ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷¶ó´Â »ç»ý¾Æ¸¦ Ãâ»êÇ߱⠶§¹®À̾ú´Ù. ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ÀÓÁ¾½Ã¿¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ÀÇ ¾Æ¹öÁöÀÓÀ» ¿¤·¹¾Æ³ë¸£¿¡°Ô ÀÏ·¯ÁÖ¾ú´Ù.

±¹Á¦³ëµ¿ÀÚÇùȸÀÇ °áÀǼ­¿¡ '³ëµ¿°è±ÞÀÇ ¼º¼­'¶ó°í °ø½Ä ±â¼úµÈ ¹Ù ÀÖ´Â ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀº 1867³â º£¸¦¸°¿¡¼­ ÃâÆÇµÇ¾ú°í 1873³â ÀçÆÇµÇ¾ú´Ù. ¿ÀÁ÷ ù ±Ç¸¸ÀÌ »ýÁ¸½Ã¿¡ ¿Ï¼ºµÇ¾ú°í Á¦2±Ç°ú Á¦3±ÇÀº ¿¨°Ö½ºÀÇ ÆíÁý¿¡ ÀÇÇØ 1885³â°ú 1894³â Ãâ°£µÇ¾úÀ¸¸ç, óÀ½ Á¦4±ÇÀ¸·Î ±¸»óµÇ¾ú´ø ºÎºÐÀº 1905~10³â ¡´À׿©°¡Ä¡Çм³»ç¡µ¶ó´Â µ¶¸³µÈ ÇüÅ·Π Ä«¿ìÃ÷Ű¿¡ ÀÇÇØ Ãâ°£µÇ¾ú´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â µ¥À̺ñµå ¸®Ä«µµÀÇ °íÀü °æÁ¦ÇÐÀ» ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çȸ´Â ¸ðµç »çȸÀû À¯±âü¿Í ¸¶Âù°¡Áö·Î ºÒ°¡ÇÇÇÑ ¹ßÀüÀÇ °æ·Î¸¦ °ÅÃÄ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â À¯¹°º¯Áõ¹ý°ú °áÇÕ½ÃÄ×´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀ» ÁغñÇϸ鼭 ¼öÇàÇß´ø ÀÛ¾÷ÀÌ ¾ó¸¶³ª ±¤¹üÀ§Çߴ°¡¸¦ ¾Ë·Á¸é ¸ÕÀú ¸¹Àº ¾çÀÇ À¯°í(ë¶ÍÃ)¿Í ¼ö°í(â¢ÍÃ), ¹æÁÖ(Û¨ñÉ), ¼­½Å±³È¯ µîÀ» Á¶»çÇØº¸¾Æ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù. ±×ÀÇ ºÐ¼®´ë»óÀº ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ »ý»ê°úÁ¤ÀÇ º»Áú, ÀÚº»ÀÇ À¯Åë°úÁ¤, ÀÚº»ÀÇ ÃѰúÁ¤, Àΰ£°ú ÀÚ¿¬ÀÇ ¹°Áú´ë»ç, À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â ºñÆÇ, Àΰ£»ó, À׿©°¡Ä¡·Ð°ú ±× ¿ª»ç¿¡±îÁö À̸£·¶´Ù. »Ó¸¸ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ±×´Â »çȸÇС¤±â¼ú¡¤°øÇÐÀû ¹®Á¦µéÀ» ¿¬±¸Çß°í ¼öÇÐ ¹× ÀÚ¿¬°úÇÐÀ» ¿¬±¸ÇßÀ¸¸ç ¿ª»çÀû °úÁ¤°ú ³ó¾÷°æÁ¦¸¦ ºÐ¼®Çߴ°¡ Çϸé, Çì°ÖÀÇ ¡´³í¸®ÇÐ Wissenschaft der Logik¡µ¿¡ Ưº°È÷ ÁÖ¸ñÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ »çȸÀÇ ¹ýÄ¢¼º¿¡ °üÇÑ ¿¬±¸¸¦ ÀÚ¿¬»çÀû(í»æÔÞÈîÜ) °úÁ¤À̶ó´Â ¼º°ÝÀ» °®´Â »çȸ±¸¼ºÃ¼ ¹ßÀüÀÌ·ÐÀ¸·Î ÃѰýÇßÀ¸¸ç °æÁ¦Àû Åä´ë, À̵¥¿Ã·Î±âÀû »óºÎ±¸Á¶, »ý»ê·Â, »ý»ê°ü°è µî »çȸ±¸¼ºÃ¼ÀÇ »ý»ê°ü°è¸¦ ¹àÈ÷°í »çȸ±¸¼ºÃ¼ÀÇ ¿©·¯ ¿ä¼Òµé »çÀÌÀÇ »óÈ£°ü°è¸¦ ޱ¸Çß´Ù.

¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀº ÀÌÀ±ÀÇ °¨¼ÒÀ²°ú °°Àº ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇÀÇ ³»ÀçÀû ¸ð¼øµéÀÌ ÇöÀúÇØÁü¿¡ µû¶ó ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ´Â »ç¶óÁö°í ´õ ³ªÀº »çȸ·ÎÀÇ ÀÌÇàÀÌ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁú °ÍÀ̶ó°í ¿¹¾ðÇÑ´Ù. ±â¾ïÇÒ ¸¸ÇÑ ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀÇ ³»¿ë °¡¿îµ¥ ¿µ±¹ ÀÇȸÀÇ Ã»¼­(ôìßö)¿¡¼­ ¹ßÃéÇÑ °ÍÀ¸·Î ³ëµ¿°è±ÞÀÇ ºñÂüÇÑ »ýȰÀ» ¼­¼úÇÑ ÆäÀÌÁöµéÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÌ ºñÂüÇÔÀÌ Áõ°¡µÇ°í µ¿½Ã¿¡ ÀÚº»ÀÇ µ¶Á¡ÀÌ »ý»ê¿¡ ´ëÇÏ¿© ÂøÃë·Î ÀÛ¿ëÇÏ´Â °¡¿îµ¥ ¸¶Ä§³» ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ »çÀ¯Àç»êÀÇ Á¶Á¾(ðÀñ¤)ÀÌ ¿ï¸®°Ô µÇ°í ÂøÃëÀÚ°¡ ÇÇÂøÃëÀÚ·Î Àü¶ôÇÏ°Ô µÇ¸®¶ó°í ¹Ï¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â °è±Þ°ú °è±ÞÅõÀïÀÇ Á¸À縦 ÀÚ½ÅÀÌ ¹ß°ßÇÑ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇÏÁö´Â ¾Ê°í ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾Æ ¿ª»ç°¡µéÀÌ Àڱ⺸´Ù ÈξÀ ÀÌÀü¿¡ ÀÌ ¹®Á¦µéÀ» ´Ù·ç¾î¿ÔÀ½À» ÀÎÁ¤Çß´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ±×´Â »ý»ê¹ßÀüÀÇ °¢ ´Ü°è´Â ÀÌ¿¡ »óÀÀÇÏ´Â °è±Þ±¸Á¶¿Í ¿¬°üÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù´Â °Í°ú °è±ÞÅõÀïÀº ÇÊ¿¬ÀûÀ¸·Î ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ µ¶À縦 ³º¾Æ ¹«°è±Þ »çȸÀÇ µµ·¡°¡ ½ÇÇöµÉ °ÍÀÓÀ» ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¾î¶»°Ô ±×°¡ ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ÁÖÁ¦µé¿¡ °üÇÑ ¸î¸î ´Ü¶ôµéÀ» Çй®Àû Ç¥ÁØ¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁø ÇÙ½ÉÀûÀÎ Áõ°Å·Î °£ÁÖÇÏ°Ô µÇ¾ú´Â°¡¸¦ ÀÌÇØÇϱâ¶õ ½±Áö ¾ÊÀº ÀÏÀÌ´Ù.

²÷ÀÓ¾øÀÌ ¿Ï¼ºµÇ¾î°¡´Â Çõ¸í°úÁ¤ ¼Ó¿¡¼­ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º´Â ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ À¯´ÉÇÑ ÁöµµÀÚ¿Í À̷а¡¸¦ ÇÑ ¼¼´ë¿¡ °ÉÃÄ ±æ·¯³Â´Ù. º£º§, ºôÇ︧ ¸®ÇÁÅ©³×È÷Æ®, ¶ó ÆÄ¸£±×, ¸Þ¸µ, Ä«¿ìÃ÷Ű µîÀÌ ±×·¯ÇÑ Àι°µéÀÌ´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®¿¡°Ô ±×µéÀÇ Ã³Áö¿Í ¿å±¸¸¦ °úÇÐÀûÀ¸·Î ÀνÄÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ°Ô ÇØÁÖ¾ú´Ù. ³ëµ¿ÀÚ °è±ÞÀÇ ¿ª»çÀû »ç¸íÀ» ½ÇÇöÇÏ´Â µ¥ Çù·ÂÇÏ´Â °Í, À̰ÍÀÌ ±×ÀÇ ÁøÁ¤ÇÑ ÇÊ»ýÀÇ Á÷¹«¿´´Ù. ±×ÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀº °áÄÚ ÀÚ±â¸ñÀûÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¾ú°í Ç×»ó »çȸ¸¦ ÀνÄÇÏ°í º¯ÇõÇÏ´Â ¹«±â¿´´Ù. ±×°ÍÀº °æÁ¦»ýȰ°ú Á¤Ä¡Àû °è±ÞÅõÀï, °úÇаú ±â¼úÀÇ Çõ¸í, ±×¸®°í ÀιÎÀÇ ¹®È­Àû¡¤Á¤Ä¡Àû ¹ßÀü µî°úÀÇ °áÇÕ¿¡¼­ ¾ò¾îÁø °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀº °ÅÀÇ 150³â¿¡ °ÉÄ£ ¿ª»ç ¼Ó¿¡¼­ »ý¸í·ÂÀ» ÀÔÁõÇßÀ¸¸ç Çõ¸íÀû ³ëµ¿¿îµ¿°ú ½ÇÀçÇÏ´Â »çȸÁÖÀÇ ¼Ó¿¡¼­ ½ÇÇöµÇ¾ú´Ù. ±×°ÍÀº »çȸÁÖÀÇ »çȸÀÇ ÀÌ·ÐÀû¡¤½ÇõÀû ¹®Á¦Çذá°úÁ¤ ¼Ó¿¡ Áö¾çµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù. ±×°ÍÀº ºí¶óµð¹Ì¸£ Àϸ®Ä¡ ·¹´Ñ¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ´õ¿í ¹ßÀüµÇ¾úÀ¸¸ç °ø»ê´ç°ú ³ëµ¿ÀÚ´çÀÇ Á¤Ä¡¿¡ À־ ÀÌ·ÐÀû Åä´ë¸¦ Çü¼ºÇß´Ù.

»çȸÇÐ À̷п¡ ÀÖ¾î ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ °¡Àå Áö´ëÇÑ °øÇåÀº ±×ÀÇ ÀϹÝÀû ºÐ¼®¾ç½Ä, Áï 'º¯Áõ¹ýÀûÀÎ' ¾ç½Ä¿¡ ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ ¾ç½ÄÀº ¸ðµç »çȸü°è°¡ ³»ÀçÀû ¸ð¼ø(ºÒ¾ÈÁ¤)À» ¹ß»ý½Ã۸ç ÀÌ ¸ð¼øÀº »õ·Î¿î »çȸÀÇ µîÀå¿¡ ÀÇÇØ¼­¸¸ ÇØ°áµÉ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù°í °£ÁÖÇÑ´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ºÐ¼®¾ç½ÄÀº Åä¸Ó½º ¸È¼­½º, Çã¹öÆ® ½ºÆæ¼­, ºôÇÁ·¹µµ ÆÄ·¹ÅäÀÇ ¾ç½Ä°ú ´õºÒ¾î »çȸ°úÇÐÀÇ ´ëÇ¥ÀûÀÎ À̷б¸Á¶ÀÇ Çϳª·Î Á¤¸³µÇ¾ú°í, ´õÀÌ»ó ¡´ÀÚº»·Ð¡µÀÇ °æÁ¦ÇÐÀû Ãß·ÐÀ» ¹Þ¾ÆµéÀÌÁö ¾Ê´Â ½Å¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀڵ鵵 ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ »çȸüÁ¦ÀÇ ºÐ¼®¿¡ À־´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ºÐ¼®¾ç½Ä¿¡ ÀÇÁ¸Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ±×ÀÇ »ç°í¾ç½ÄÀ» °ÅºÎÇØ¿Â ÇÐÀÚµé·Î´Â °æÇèÁÖÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ °èÅëÀÇ ¹öÆ®·±µå ·¯¼¿, Á¸ µàÀÌ, ±×¸®°í Ä«¸¦ Æ÷ÆÛ°¡ ÀÖ´Ù.¡æ °ø»êÁÖÀÇ

L. S. Feuer ±Û

¡¡

¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ (¦¡¦¡ ñ«ëù, Marxism)

19¼¼±â Áß¹Ý Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ÇÁ¸®µå¸®È÷ ¿¨°Ö½º°¡ ¹ßÀü½ÃŲ ÀÏ´ÜÀÇ Çм³Ã¼°è.

Àΰ£ÇÐ, ¿ª»çöÇÐ, Á¤Ä¡¡¤°æÁ¦ ÀÌ·ÐÀÇ 3ºÎºÐÀÌ »óÈ£¿¬°üÀ» ¸Î°í ÀÖ´Ù. À̵éÀ» °áÇÕ½ÃÄÑ ÀϰüµÈ ³í¸®Ã¼°è¸¦ Çü¼ºÇÏ·Á´Â ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ³ë·Â¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í ¸»³â, ƯÈ÷ »çÈÄ¿¡ ³»·ÁÁø ´Ù¾çÇÑ ÇØ¼®°ú ¼Ò·ÃÀÇ °ø½Ä À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â·Î¼­ äÅõÈ(1917) ÀÌÈÄÀÇ Á¤Ä¡Àû ¿äûÀ¸·Î ¸»¹Ì¾Ï¾Æ ¸¹Àº ŸÇù°ú ÀýÃæÀÌ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù. ¿À´Ã³¯ '¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ'´Â °ø»êÁÖÀÇ¡¤»çȸÁÖÀÇ Á¦Á¤´çÀÇ À̳ä°ú ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÞÀº ¿©·¯ »ç»ó°¡µéÀÇ Á¤Ä¡¡¤»çȸ¡¤°æÁ¦ ÀÌ·ÐÀ» Æ÷°ýÇÏ°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù.

¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ´Â Àΰ£ÀÇ Ã¢Á¶·Â¿¡¼­ Àΰ£¸¸ÀÌ °¡Áö´Â °íÀ¯ÇÑ Æ¯¼ºÀ» ¹ß°ßÇÑ´Ù. âÁ¶·ÂÀ̶õ ÇÊ¿äÀÇ ÃæÁ·À» À§ÇØ ÀÚ¿¬À̶ó´Â ´ë»ó¿¡ ½ñ´Â Àΰ£ÀÇ ³ë·Â°ú ³ëµ¿·ÂÀ̸ç, ¿©±â¼­ ³ëµ¿Àº °³ÀÎÀûÀÎ °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó Àηù¶ó°í ÇÏ´Â ÇϳªÀÇ Á¾(ðú)À» À§ÇÑ ³ë·ÂÀÌ´Ù. Àΰ£ÀÇ ÅëÁ¦¹üÀ§¸¦ ¹þ¾î³ª±âµµ ÇÏ´Â º¹Àâ´Ù´ÜÇÑ ¿ª»çÀû »ç°Çµé·Î ÀÎÇØ ÀÌ¿Í °°Àº ÀÌ»óÀº ¾ÆÁ÷ ½ÇÇöµÇÁö ¸øÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ¿¹ÄÁ´ë ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ Ã¼Á¦¿¡¼­´Â âÁ¶ÀûÀÎ ¿¡³ÊÁö ȤÀº ³ëµ¿·ÂÀ» Åõ¿©ÇÏ´Â °³Àαº(ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®)°ú ÀÓ±ÝÀ» ÁÖ°í ÀÌ ³ëµ¿ÀÇ »ê¹°À» µµ¿ëÇÏ´Â °è±Þ(ºÎ¸£ÁÖ¾ÆÁö)ÀÌ µû·Î Á¸ÀçÇϸç, ÀÌ´Â ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®¿¡ ÀÇÇØ âÁ¶µÈ ¼¼°è°¡ ½ÇÁ¦·Î ³ëµ¿¿¡ Âü¿©ÇÏÁö ¾ÊÀº ÀÚº»°¡ °è±Þ¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ¼ÒÀ¯µÇ°í ÀÖÀ½À» ÀǹÌÇÑ´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ Çö½ÇÀÇ ¸ð¼øÀ» ' ¼Ò¿Ü'¶ó´Â ¸»·Î Ç¥ÇöÇß´Ù. ³ëµ¿ÀÚ °è±ÞÀÌ ³ëµ¿ÀÇ °á½ÇÀ» ȸº¹ÇÏ°Ô µÇ´Â ±×³¯ÀÌ µµ·¡ÇÒ ¶§, ¼Ò¿Ü´Â ±Øº¹µÇ°í ¸ðµç °è±ÞÀÇ ±¸ºÐµéÀº »ç¶óÁö°Ô µÉ °ÍÀÌ´Ù.

°è±ÞÅõÀï°ú °è±Þ ¾ø´Â »çȸÀÇ À̳äÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½º ÀÌÀü¿¡ ÀÌ¹Ì Á¦Ã¢µÇ°í ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. °øµ¿Ã¼ ³»ÀÇ °æÁ¦Àû ÀÌÇØ°ü°è°¡ °¥µîÀ» À¯¹ßÇÑ´Ù´Â Âø»óÀº ¸Ö¸® ÅõŰµðµ¥½ºÀÇ ÀúÀÛ¿¡±îÁö ¼Ò±ÞµÇ¸ç, ±âÁ¸ °æÁ¦Ã¼Á¦ÀÇ ºñÆÇ À§¿¡ °è±Þ¾ø´Â ÀÌ»ó»çȸ¸¦ °Ç¼³ÇÏ·Á´Â °®°¡Áö »ç»óµéÀÌ 19¼¼±âÀÇ Ã¹ 10³â µ¿¾È ²ÉÀ» ÇÇ¿ü´Ù. Ä«¸¦ ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â ÀÌ 2°¡Áö À̳äÀ» »ö´Ù¸¥ ¹æ½ÄÀ¸·Î °áÇÕ½ÃÄ×´Ù. °ø»óÀû »çȸÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀÇ °úÁ¦´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÌ »ý°¢ÇÏ´Â À¯ÅäÇǾư¡ ¾î¶°ÇÑ °ÍÀΰ¡¿¡ ÀÖ´Â °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ±×°Í¿¡ µµ´ÞÇÏ´Â ¹æ¹ýÀ» Á¦½ÃÇÏ´Â µ¥ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â °è±ÞÅõÀïÀ» ¿ª»çÀÇ ÃßÁø·ÂÀ¸·Î °£ÁÖÇÑ µÚ ÀηùÀÇ ¿ª»ç´Â °è±Þ ¾ø´Â »çȸÀÇ ÃâÇöÀ¸·Î Á¤Á¡¿¡ ¿À¸¦ °ÍÀ̶ó°í ³»´Ùº¸¾Ò´Ù. "Áö±Ý±îÁöÀÇ ¿ª»ç´Â °è±ÞÅõÀïÀÇ ¿ª»çÀÌ´Ù"¶ó°í ½ÃÀ۵Ǵ ¡´°ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei¡µÀÇ Ã¹ ±¸ÀýÀº ¸¶¸£Å©½º ¿ª»ç°üÀÇ °¡Àå °­·ÂÇÑ Ç¥ÇöÀ̾ú´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¿¨°Ö½º¿¡°Ô ¸ðµç ¿ª»ç´Â ÂøÃë°è±Þ°ú ÇÇÂøÃë°è±Þ »çÀÌÀÇ ÅõÀïÀÇ ¿¬¼ÓÀ¸·Î ºñÃÆ´Ù. ¿ª»ç´Â ÀüÀ¹ß°ß¡¤¹ß¸í¡¤Á¶¾à¡¤À½¸ð µîÀ¸·Î Àü°³µÈ´Ù´Â °ÍÀÌ Á¾ÀüÀÇ °ßÇØ¿´´Ù¸é ¸¶¸£Å©½º´Â À̵éÀÌ ¹ÛÀ¸·Î µå·¯³ª´Â Çã»ó¿¡ ºÒ°úÇÏ´Ù°í ´Ü¾ðÇß´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡°Ô ¿ª»çÀÇ µ¿ÀÎÀº Àΰ£ÀÇ ÀÇ¡¤½Ä¡¤ÁÖ ¹®Á¦¸¦ ÇØ°áÇÏ´Â '»ý»ê¼ö´Ü'ÀÇ ¹ßÀü¿¡ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.

Àΰ£ÀÌ »ýÁ¸Çϱâ À§Çؼ­´Â ¹°Áú¿¡ÀÇ ÀÇÁ¸ÀÌ ºÒ°¡ÇÇÇÏ´Ù´Â °ÍÀÌ ¸¶¸£Å©½º°¡ Á¦Ã¢ÇÑ ' ¿ª»çÀû À¯¹°·Ð'ÀÇ ÇÙ½ÉÀ̾ú´Ù. ¹°ÁúÀûÀÎ »ýȰÀ» À¯ÁöÇϱâ À§ÇØ Àΰ£Àº »ý»ê¼ö´ÜÀ̶ó´Â ÀÏ´ÜÀÇ °ü°è¸¦ ÅëÇØ ÀÚ¿¬°ú ±³·ùÇØ¾ß¸¸ ÇÑ´Ù. Àηù´Â ¿ª»çÀÇ ¸Å´Ü°è¸¶´Ù µ¶Æ¯ÇÑ »ý»ê¼ö´ÜÀ» ¹ßÀü½ÃÄѿԴÙ. 14¼¼±âÀÇ ÀÚº»°¡ °è±ÞÀ̶õ »ó»óÇÒ ¼ö ¾øÀ¸¸ç, 20¼¼±âÀÇ ºÀ°Ç¿µÁÖ¶õ Á¸ÀçÇÏÁö ¾Ê´Â´Ù. ¿ª»ç´Â º¯Áõ¹ýÀÇ ¿ø¸®¿¡ µû¶ó ½º½º·Î ÁøÈ­Çذ£´Ù. ¸Å´Ü°è´Â »ó¹ÝµÇ´Â ´Ü°è¿¡ ÀÇÇØ °è½ÂµÇ¸ç ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ 2´Ü°èÀÇ »óÈ£ÀÛ¿ëÀÌ Á¾ÇÕÀ» ÀÌ·ç´Â °úÁ¤¿¡¼­ »õ·Î¿î ¿ª»ç´Ü°è°¡ ´ëµÎÇÑ´Ù. ¾î´À ´Ü°è¿¡¼­³ª »ý»ê¼ö´ÜÀÇ ÀüÁ¦°¡ µÇ´Â °ÍÀº Àΰ£°ú ÀÚ¿¬, ±×¸®°í Àΰ£°ú Àΰ£ »çÀÌÀÇ °ü°èÀε¥ Àΰ£Àº ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ °ü°èµé ¼Ó¿¡¼­ ½º½º·ÎÀÇ Àΰ£¼ºÀ» »ó½ÇÇØ°£´Ù.

ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ °æÁ¦Ã¼Á¦´Â °¡Àå ÃÖ±ÙÀÇ ¿ª»ç´Ü°èÀÌ´Ù. ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇÀÇ ¹ø¿µÀº »ý»ê·Â ±Ô¸ðÀÇ ¼¼°èÀûÀÎ È®´ë¿Í ¾öû³­ ¾çÀÇ À׿©°¡Ä¡ âÃâ¿¡ ±âÃÊÇϰí ÀÖÀ¸¸ç À׿©°¡Ä¡´Â °í½º¶õÈ÷ ÀÚº»°¡ÀÇ ¸òÀ¸·Î µÈ´Ù. ³»ÀçÀûÀÎ ¸ð¼ø¿¡ ½Ã´Þ¸®°í ÀÖ´Â ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ´Â ±×·¯³ª ¹ø¿µÀ» Áö¼ÓÇÒ ¼ö´Â ¾ø´Ù. °¡Àå Áß¿äÇÑ »ç½ÇÀº ÀÚº»ÁÖÀǰ¡ ¸ðµç Àΰ£µéÀ» »óǰȭÇÔÀ¸·Î½á °³¼ºÀ» ¸»»ì½ÃŲ´Ù´Â Á¡ÀÌ´Ù. ÀÌ·± ½ÄÀ¸·Î ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ´Â ÀÚ¸êÀ» ÃÊ·¡ÇÑ´Ù. ÀÚº»ÁÖÀÇ·Î ¸»¹Ì¾Ï¾Æ °è±ÞÅõÀïÀº °áÁ¤ÀûÀÎ ±¹¸éÀ» ¸ÂÀÌÇϸç, ¸í¹éÇÑ ÂøÃë·Î ÀÎÇØ ¿ÏÀüÈ÷ Àΰ£¼ºÀ» »ó½ÇÇÏ°Ô µÈ ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®´Â ¸¶Ä§³» °øµ¿¸ñÇ¥¸¦ ÇâÇØ ´ÜÇÕÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ°Ô µÈ´Ù. ±×¸®ÇÏ¿© ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ½Â¸®°¡ ÀÓ¹ÚÇÏ°í °è±Þ ¾ø´Â ÀÌ»ó»çȸ°¡ ½ÇÇöµÇ±â¿¡ À̸¥´Ù. ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ÀÌÀÍÀº Àüü ÀηùÀÇ ÀÌÀÍÀ̸ç, ÇÁ·Ñ·¹Å¸¸®¾ÆÆ®ÀÇ ½Â¸®´Â ³ëµ¿ÀÇ ºÐÈ­°¡ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁø ÀÌÈÄ ²÷ÀÓ¾øÀÌ °øµ¿Ã¼¸¦ ±«·ÓÇô¿Â °è±ÞÀÇ ºÐÈ­¸¦ ºÒ½Ä½Ãų °ÍÀÌ´Ù.

1848³â Çõ¸íÀÌ ½ÇÆÐ·Î µ¹¾Æ°¡°í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ºÐ¼®Æ²ÀÌ º¹À⼺À» ´õÇØ°¡´Â »çȸ±¸Á¶ÀÇ ÇØ¸í¿¡ ÇѰ踦 µå·¯³»ÀÚ, ƯÈ÷ ¸¶¸£Å©½º »çÈÄ¿¡ À̷п¡ ´ëÇÑ ¼öÁ¤°ú º¸¿ÏÀÛ¾÷ÀÌ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁ³´Ù. ¿¨°Ö½º¿Í Ä«¸¦ Ä«¿ìÃ÷۵î Á¤Åë ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀº ƯÁ¤ »óȲÀ» °Ü³ÉÇÑ Çõ¸í°­·ÉÀ¸·ÎºÎÅÍ ¿ª»çÀÇ ÁøÈ­¿¡ µû¸¥ ±Ã±ØÀûÀÎ ½Â¸®¶ó°í ÇÏ´Â ÆòÈ­ÀûÀÎ ±â´ë ÂÊÀ¸·Î ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÇ ¼º°ÝÀ» º¯È­½ÃÄ×´Ù. ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ´Â ºí¶óµð¹Ì¸£ Àϸ®Ä¡ ·¹´Ñ¿¡ ÀÇÇØ º¸´Ù ½É°¢ÇÑ º¯ÁúÀ» °Þ°Ô µÇ¾ú´Ù. ·¹´ÑÀº ³ëµ¿ÀÚ °è±ÞÀÇ ÀÚ¹ßÀûÀÎ Çõ¸í¼öÇà´É·ÂÀ» ºÎÀÎÇϰí Á÷¾÷Çõ¸í°¡¿¡ ÀÇÇÑ Ã¼°èÀûÀÎ Áöµµ¸¦ ¿ª¼³ÇßÀ¸¸ç, ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿ª»çÀÌ·ÐÀ» »õ·ÎÀÌ ÇØ¼®ÇØ Àü±Ù´ë»çȸ¿¡¼­ÀÇ Çõ¸í °¡´É¼ºÀ» ¹Þ¾Æµé¿´´Ù. '¸¶¸£Å©½º-·¹´ÑÁÖÀÇ'¶õ ÀüÅë ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ¿Í È¿À²ÀûÀÎ ´çÁ¶Á÷ÀÇ °áÇÕÀ» ÀǹÌÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ÇÑÆí ¿ÀÅä ¹Ù¿ì¾î°¡ ÁÖµµÇÏ´Â ¿À½ºÆ®¸®¾Æ ÇÐÆÄ´Â ±Ø´ÜÀûÀÎ °è±ÞÅõÀïÀ» °í¼öÇÏ´Â ±ÞÁø Çõ¸í¼¼·ÂÀÇ ºñÀ±¸®¼º¿¡ ¹Ý±â¸¦ µé°í »çȸÀû ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀÇ º»¿¬ÀÇ Àΰ£ÁÖÀÇÀû Åä´ë·Î µÇµ¹¾Æ°¥ °ÍÀ» ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¼¼°è °¢±¹ °ø»êÁÖÀÇÀÇ ½Ç»óÀº Á¤Åë ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ¿¡¼­ ¹þ¾î³­ ¿¹°¡ ¸¹À¸¸ç Áö½ÄÀεéÀº Çö´ëÀÇ ±â°è¹®¸íÀ» ºñÆÇÇÏ´Â µµ±¸·Î¼­ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀû ½Ã°¢µéÀ» ÀÀ¿ëÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ½ÇÁ¸ÁÖÀÇ Ã¶Çп¡ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ÀÌ·ÐÀ» À¶ÇÕ½ÃŲ »ç¸£Æ®¸£ÀÇ ¡´º¯Áõ¹ý ºñÆÇ Critique de la raison dialectique¡µ(1960)Àº ÈÄÀÚÀÇ ´ëÇ¥ÀûÀÎ ¿¹°¡ µÉ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù.

¡¡

4 Major Works

MAJOR WORKS Misère de la philosophie (1847; The Poverty of Philosophy, 1900); Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei (1848; Manifesto of the Communists, 1883); Die Klassenkämpfe in Frankreich 1848 bis 1850 (1850; The Class Struggles in France, 1848 to 1850, 1924); Der 18te Brumaire des Louis Napoleon (1852; The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, 1898); Zur Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (1859; A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, 1904); and Das Kapital (vol. 1, 1867; vol. 2-3 published by Engels in 1885 and 1894; Capital: A Critical Analysis of Capitalist Production, vol. 1 trans. by Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling, 1886; vol. 2-3 trans. by Ernest Untermann, 1907 and 1909).

Recommended later translations of these works include Manifesto of the Communist Party, trans. by Samuel Moore (1888, reprinted 1952); The Communist Manifesto of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, with an introduction and explanatory notes by D. Ryazanoff, trans. by Eden Paul and Cedar Paul (1930); and The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, trans. by Eden Paul and Cedar Paul (1926). Selections from Marx's writings are available in the following: David McLellan (ed.), Selected Writings (1977); Robert C. Tucker (ed.), The Marx-Engels Reader, 2nd ed. (1978); and Jon Elster (ed.), Karl Marx: A Reader (1986).

A major English-language edition, Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works, trans. by Richard Dixon et al. (1975- ), is in progress. Planned to consist of 50 volumes and to include the correspondence, it is being prepared by an international editorial committee. Forty-one volumes had been published by 1992.

5 Bibliography

BIBLIOGRAPHY

 

5.1 Marx.

The most comprehensive biography of Marx is DAVID McLELLAN, Karl Marx: His Life and Thought (1973, reissued 1987). The classic biography of Marx, somewhat too partisan in his favour, is FRANZ MEHRING, Karl Marx: The Story of His Life (1935, reissued 1981; originally published in German, 1918). Marx's personal life is discussed in SAUL K. PADOVER, Karl Marx, an Intimate Biography (1978). JERROLD SEIGEL, Marx's Fate: The Shape of a Life (1978), is a psychological biography. YVONNE KAPP, Eleanor Marx, 2 vol. (1972-76), contains informative material on Marx's family life. Two good short biographies are ISAIAH BERLIN, Karl Marx: His Life and Environment, 4th ed. (1978, reprinted with corrections, 1982); and WERNER BLUMENBERG, Portrait of Marx: An Illustrated Biography (1972; originally published in German, 1962).

For introductory analysis and commentaries of Marx's works, see DAVID McLELLAN, The Thought of Karl Marx, 2nd ed. (1980); BRUCE MAZLISH, The Meaning of Karl Marx (1984); W.A. SUCHTING, Marx, an Introduction (1983), and Marx and Philosophy: Three Studies (1986); and RICHARD SCHMITT, Introduction to Marx and Engels: A Critical Reconstruction (1987). TERRELL CARVER, A Marx Dictionary (1987), provides brief definitions of Marxian concepts without interpretative deviations from the original. For more detailed studies, see ROMAN ROSDOLSKY, The Making of Marx's 'Capital' (1977, reissued 1980; originally published in German, 1968); DEREK SAYER, Marx's Method: Ideology, Science and Critique in Capital, 2nd ed. (1983); ROBERT PAUL WOLFF, Understanding Marx: A Reconstruction and Critique of Capital (1984); HAL DRAPER, Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution, 3 vol. (1977-86); D. ROSS GANDY, Marx and History: From Primitive Society to the Communist Future (1979); MURRAY WOLFSON, Marx: Economist, Philosopher, Jew: Steps in the Development of a Doctrine (1982); DANIEL LITTLE, The Scientific Marx (1986); THOMAS SOWELL, Marxism: Philosophy and Economics (1985); and JOHN CUNNINGHAM WOOD (ed.), Karl Marx's Economics: Critical Assessments, 4 vol. (1987). A particularly acute summary of the difficulties in Marx's work is JON ELSTER, Making Sense of Marx (1985). Many monographs explore Marx's political and ideological development: CAROL C. GOULD, Marx's Social Ontology: Individuality and Community in Marx's Theory of Social Reality (1978, reprinted 1980), a study based on Marx's Grundrisse; RICHARD E. OLSEN, Karl Marx (1978); S.S. PRAWER, Karl Marx and World Literature (1976); PAUL THOMAS, Karl Marx and the Anarchists (1980); and ALLEN W. WOOD, Karl Marx (1981).

 

5.2 Marxism.

Good introductions to the study of Marxism include LESZEK KOLAKOWSKI, Main Currents of Marxism: Its Rise, Growth, and Dissolution, 3 vol. (1978, reprinted 1981; originally published in Polish, 1976-78); GEORGE LICHTHEIM, Marxism: An Historical and Critical Study, 2nd ed. (1964, reprinted 1982); and DAVID McLELLAN, Marxism After Marx (1979, reissued 1981), which contains an extensive bibliography. Some important analyses are assembled in DAVID McLELLAN (ed.), Marxism: Essential Writings (1988). Studies of Marxism as a sociological doctrine may be found in KARL KORSCH, Karl Marx (1938, reissued 1963); HENRI LEFEBVRE, The Sociology of Marx (1968, reprinted 1982; originally published in French, 1966); and SIDNEY HOOK, Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx (1933). Developments in Marxism as a political theory are discussed in ALFRED SCHMIDT, History and Structure: An Essay on Hegelian-Marxist and Structuralist Theories of History (1981; originally published in German, 1971); DAVID RUBINSTEIN, Marx and Wittgenstein: Social Praxis and Social Explanation (1981); TOM ROCKMORE, Fichte, Marx, and the German Philosophical Tradition (1980); S.H. RIGBY, Marxism and History: A Critical Introduction (1987); and PAUL PHILLIPS, Marx and Engels on Law and Laws (1980). Specialized studies include STANLEY MOORE, Marx on the Choice Between Socialism and Communism (1980); JOSÉ PORFIRIO MIRANDA, Marx Against the Marxists: The Christian Humanism of Karl Marx (1980; originally published in Spanish, 1978); RALPH MILIBAND, Marxism and Politics (1977), including a discussion of the applicability of Marxism to contemporary politics in the Third World and communist countries; ROBERT L. HEILBRONER, Marxism, For and Against (1980); ANTHONY GIDDENS, A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism, 2 vol. (1981-85), an alternative, based on anthropological research, to the Marxist idea that all history has been the history of class struggle; MAURICE GODELIER, Perspectives in Marxist Anthropology (1977; originally published in French, 1973), presenting the contrasting view that classical Marxism may provide a methodology for analysis of empirical data in history and anthropology; and IAN CUMMINS, Marx, Engels, and National Movements (1980).

A. JAMES GREGOR, A Survey of Marxism: Problems in Philosophy and the Theory of History (1965), emphasizes philosophical problems in lieu of political or economic ones. The outstanding work on Marxist ethics is EUGENE KAMENKA, The Ethical Foundations of Marxism, 2nd ed. (1972). See also HUGO MEYNELL, Freud, Marx, and Morals (1981); and GARY NELSON and LAWRENCE GROSSBERG (eds.), Marxism and Interpretation of Culture (1988).

DAVID HOROWITZ (ed.), Marx and Modern Economics (1968), is an excellent collection of essays by leading economic theorists. Other treatments of Marxist economics worth consulting are PAUL M. SWEEZY, The Theory of Capitalist Development: Principles of Marxian Political Economy (1942, reissued 1970); and JOHN STRACHEY, The Nature of Capitalist Crisis (1935). The place of Marxist thought in the intellectual history of the 20th century is assessed in JACK LINDSAY, The Crisis in Marxism (1981); ANTHONY BREWER, Marxist Theories of Imperialism: A Critical Survey (1980); PERRY ANDERSON, Considerations on Western Marxism (1976); and WALTER L. ADAMSON, Marx and the Disillusionment of Marxism (1985).

An account of the historical development of Marxism can be found in HENRI CHAMBRE, From Karl Marx to Mao Tse-Tung: A Systematic Survey of Marxism-Leninism (1963; originally published in French, 1959). GEORGE D.H. COLE, A History of Socialist Thought, 5 vol. in 7 (1953-65), presents a detailed study of the Marxist movement rather than the ideas; see especially vol. 2, Socialist Thought: Marxism and Anarchism, 1850-1890. TOM BOTTOMORE (ed.), Interpretations of Marx (1988), is an authoritative collection of essays.

The development and influence of Russian, Soviet, and eastern European Marxist theories is covered in a number of works by both Marxist and non-Marxist authors: HERBERT MARCUSE, Soviet Marxism: A Critical Analysis (1958, reprinted 1985); BERTRAM D. WOLFE, Revolution and Reality: Essays on the Origin and Fate of the Soviet System (1981); BARUCH KNEI- PAZ, The Social and Political Thought of Leon Trotsky (1978); UMBERTO MELOTTI, Marx and the Third World (1977, reprinted 1982; originally published in Italian, 1971); ADAM WESTOBY, Communism Since World War II (1981); and ERNEST MANDEL, Revolutionary Marxism Today (1979). Specialized studies include DONALD C. HODGES, The Bureaucratization of Socialism (1981); ROBERT J. ALEXANDER, The Right Opposition: The Lovestoneites and the International Communist Opposition of the 1930's (1981); ESTHER KINGSTON-MANN, Lenin and the Problem of Marxist Peasant Revolution (1983); BOGDAN SZA JKOWSKI (ed.), Marxist Governments: A World Survey, 3 vol. (1981); V. KUBÁLKOVÁ and A.A. CRUICKSHANK, Marxism-Leninism and Theory of International Relations (1980); HORACE B. DAVIS, Toward a Marxist Theory of Nationalism (1978); ISAAC DEUTSCHER, Marxism in Our Time (1971); JOHN P. BURKE, LAWRENCE CROCKER, and LYMAN H. LEGTERS (eds.), Marxism and the Good Society (1981), on Russia and China; JOHN G. GURLEY, Challengers to Capitalism: Marx, Lenin, Stalin, and Mao, 3rd ed. (1988); and NICHOLAS ABERCROMBIE, STEPHEN HILL, and BRYAN S. TURNER, The Dominant Ideology Thesis (1980), a critique of current Marxist thought. Two important critical studies are DAVID LANE, The Socialist Industrial State: Towards a Political Sociology of State Socialism (1976); and DONALD WILHELM, Creative Alternatives to Communism: Guidelines for Tomorrow's World (1977, reprinted 1981).

Of special reference interest are JOHN LACHS, Marxist Philosophy: A Bibliographical Guide (1967); HARRY G. SHAFFER, Periodicals on the Socialist Countries and on Marxism: A New Annotated Index of English-Language Publications (1977); J. WILCZYNSKI, An Encyclopedic Dictionary of Marxism, Socialism and Communism (1981); and ROBERT A. GORMAN (ed.), Biographical Dictionary of Marxism (1986), and Biographical Dictionary of Neo- Marxism (1985), a compendium providing information on practitioners of Marxism in more than 50 countries. (D.T.McL.)

  • ¸¶¸£Å©½º
  • Àú¼­
    • °ø»ê´ç¼±¾ð(»õ³¯°íÀü¹­À½ 2) : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¡¤F. ¿¨°Ö½º °øÀú, ±è±â¿¬ ¿ª, »õ³¯, 1991
    • ÇÁ¶û½ºÇõ¸í»ç 3ºÎÀÛ(¼Ò³ª¹«ÃѼ­ 1) : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, ÀÓÁöÇö¡¤ÀÌÁ¾ÈÆ °ø¿ª, ¼Ò³ª¹«, 1991
    • µ¶ÀÏÀ̵¥¿Ã·Î±â ¥° : Ä® ¸¶¸£Å©½º F. ¿¨°Ö½º, ¹ÚÀçÈñ ¿Å±è, û³â»ç, 1991
    • ¸¼½º¿¨°Ö½º¼±Áý(¼®Å¾ÃѼ­ 2) : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¡¤F. ¿¨°Ö½º °øÀú, ¼®Å¾ ÆíÁýºÎ Æí¿ª, ¼®Å¾, 1990
    • ÀÚº»·Ð ¥°¡¤¥±¡¤¥² : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, ±è¼öÇà ¿ª, ºñºÀÃâÆÇ»ç, 1989-90
    • Àӱݡ¤°¡°Ý¡¤ÀÌÀ± : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, ³²»óÀÏ ¿ª, ¹é»ê¼­´ç, 1990
    • À׿©°¡Ä¡Çм³»ç(Á¦1¡¤2ºÎ) : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, ¹éÀÇ, 1989
    • Àӱݳ뵿°ú ÀÚº» : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, ³²»óÀÏ ¿ª, ¹é»ê¼­´ç, 1989
    • ´ç¿¡ ´ëÇÏ¿© ¥° : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¡¤F. ¿¨°Ö½º °øÀú, ÇÑö ¿ª, À̼º°ú Çö½Ç, 1989
    • ¸¼½º¿¨°Ö½º¼±Áý ¥°¡¤¥± : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¡¤F. ¿¨°Ö½º °øÀú, ÆíÁýºÎ ¿ª, ¹éÀÇ, 1989
    • ¸¼½º¿¨°Ö½º¼±Áý : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¡¤F. ¿¨°Ö½º °øÀú, ¸¼½º·¹´ÑÁÖÀÇ¿¬±¸¼Ò Æí¿ª, ¹éÀÇ, 1989
    • ÇÁ·Î¸ÞÅ׿콺(¸¶¸£Å©½º Àü±â¼Ò¼³) :, ±è¼®Èñ ¿ª, °øµ¿Ã¼, 1989
    • ³ëµ¿Á¶ÇÕ·Ð : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¡¤F. ¿¨°Ö½º, ÀüÇý¿ø ¿ª, ½Ã¸°»õº®, 1988
    • Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐ ºñÆÇÀ» À§ÇÏ¿©(Áß¿ø¹®È­½Å¼­ 41) : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, ±èÈ£±Õ ¿ª, Áß¿ø¹®È­, 1988
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º ¿¨°Ö½º ÀúÀÛ¼± : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º¡¤F. ¿¨°Ö½º °øÀú, ±èÀç±â Æí¿ª, °Å¸§, 1988
    • ·çÀÌ º¸³ªÆÄ¸£¶ßÀÇ ºê·ò¸Þ¸£ 18ÀÏ : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, ÅÂ¹é ÆíÁýºÎ ¿ª, Źé, 1987
    • µµÀÌÄ¡À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â/°æÁ¦ÇÐöÇмö°í : K. ¸¶¸£Å©½º, Çϱâ¶ô ¿ª, Çü¼³ÃâÆÇ»ç, 1982
  • ¿¬±¸¼­
    • Ä® ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Ã¶Çаú ½ÅÈ­ : R. ÅÍÄ¿, ±èÇÐÁØ ÇѸíÈ­ °ø¿ª, Çѱæ»ç, 1993
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º »ê °Í°ú Á×Àº °Í : J. ¿¤½ºÅÍ, ¹ÚÁøÈ¯ ¿ª, ¹®¿ì»ç, 1992
    • º£¹ö¿Í ¸¶¸£Å©½º : Ä® ·ÚºñÆ®, ÀÌ»ó·ü ¿ª, ¹®¿¹ÃâÆÇ»ç, 1992
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿ª»çÀû À¯¹°·Ð°ú Àΰ£·Ð : ±èâȣ, Á×»ê, 1991
    • Ä® ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Á¦À̷п¡ ´ëÇÑ ºÐ¼® : ÀåÀÏÁ¶ ¿Ü, Çѱ¹Á¤½Å¹®È­¿¬±¸¿ø Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦¿¬±¸½Ç Æí, Çѱ¹Á¤½Å¹®È­¿¬±¸¿ø, 1991
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º : ÃÖÀåÁý, °í·Á´ëÇб³ ÃâÆÇºÎ, 1990
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º : °í¸¶Å° ¿À»ç¹«, ¹ÎÁß»ç»ó¿¬±¸¼Ò ¿ª, ÂüÇÑÃâÆÇ»ç, 1990
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º¸¦ À§ÇÏ¿©(¹éÀǽż­ 17) : L. ¾ËÆ¢¼¼¸£, °í±æÈ¯¡¤ÀÌÈ­¼÷ °ø¿ª, ¹éÀÇ, 1990
    • Ä® ¸¶¸£Å©½º Àü±â ¥°, ¥±(¼Ò³ª¹«ÃѼ­ 22¡¤3) : ¼Ò·Ã¸¶¸£Å©½º·¹´ÑÁÖÀÇ¿¬±¸¼Ò, ±è³ªÇÕ ¿ª, 1988-89
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¼¼°è : D. ¸ÅŬ·¹·±, °­¿ì¶õ ¿ª, Ã¥¼¼»ó, 1988
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º »ç»óÀÇ ÀÌÇØ : ±ÇÇõ¸é, ÀÌ¿ìÃâÆÇ»ç, 1988
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ »ý¾Ö¿Í »ç»óÆò°¡ : D. ¸®¾ð, ¹Ú¿µÈ£ ¿ª, ±âµ¶±³¹®¼­¼±±³È¸, 1987
    • Ä® ¸¶¸£Å©½º : ¼Òõ½Å»ï, À̿켮 ¿ª, ¹ÎÁß¼­°¢, 1986
    • Àΰ£ ¸¶¸£Å©½º-±×ÀÇ »ç¶ûÀÇ »ý¾Ö : P. µÚ¶û, ³ªÇý¿ø ¿ª, µÎ·¹, 1984
    • Ä® ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ »çȸ»ç»ó°ú Á¤Ä¡»ç»ó : ½¯·Î¸ð ¾Æºñ³×¸®, ÀÌÈ«±¸ ¿ª, ±îÄ¡, 1983
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Àΰ£±Ç(¼±¼­ 10) : E. ÇÁ·Ò H. Æ÷ÇÍÃ÷, ±èâȣ ¿ª, µ¿³è, 1983
    • û³â¸¼½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ(¼±¼­ 10) : N. ·ÎÅÙ½ºÆ®¶óÀÌÈ÷, Á¤½ÂÇö ¿ª, ÇÑ¿ï, 1983
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ(Çö´ë»ç»ó¼±¼­ 9) : P. ¿ö½½¸®, Áø´ö±Ô ¿ª, Çй®°ú »ç»ó»ç, 1983
    • ¸¼½º¿Í ¸¼½ºÁÖÀÇÀÚµé : ½Ãµå´Ï ÈÄÅ©, ¾çÈ£¹Î ¿ª, ¹®¸í»ç, 1982
  • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ
    • ÀÌÅ»¸®¾Æ¸¼½ºÁÖÀÇ¿Í ±¹°¡ÀÌ·Ð : Ä«¸° ÇÁ¸®½ºÅÍ, À±¼öÁ¾ ¿ª, »õ±æ, 1993
    • Çö´ë»çȸ¿Í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ(µ¿³è 3) : Çѱ¹Ã¶Çлç»ó¿¬±¸È¸ Æí, µ¿³è, 1992
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ : À¯Áø·± ¿Ü, ±èº´ÀÍ ¿Ü ¿ª, °í·Á¿ø, 1991
    • ÀÚº»·ÐÀ» Àд´٠: L. ¾ËÆ¢¼¼¸£, ±èÁø¿± ¿ª, µÎ·¹, 1991
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ¿Í ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀÇ : ÇÑ»óÁø ÆíÀú, »çȸ¹®È­¿¬±¸¼Ò ÃâÆÇºÎ, 1991
    • ÀϺ» ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ»ç °³¼³ : ¼Ò»ïÈ«°Ç Æí, Çѻ󱸡¤Á¶°æ¶õ °ø¿ª, À̷аú ½Çõ, 1991
    • Àüȯ±âÀÇ ¼¼°è¿Í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ : ÄíÄ£½ºÅ°¡¤¿ù·¯½ºÅ¸ÀÎ °øÀú, Á¶¿µÈ¯ ¿Ü Æí¿ª, °æ³²´ëÇб³ ÃâÆÇºÎ, 1990
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º Á¤Ä¡°æÁ¦ÇÐÀÇ º¯Áõ¹ýÀû ¹æ¹ý ¥°, ¥±(»çȸ°úÇнż­ 19-20) : M. M. ·ÎÁ¨Å», öÇлç»ó¿¬±¸È¸ ¿ª, À̷аú ½Çõ, 1989
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ Á¤Ä¡ÇÐ ÀÔ¹® : R. ¹Ð¸®¹Ýµå, Á¤¿øÈ£ ¿ª, Ç®ºû, 1989
    • ÄݶóÄÚÇÁ½ºÅ°ÀÇ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ ¥°, ¥± : ÄݶóÄÚÇÁ½ºÅ°, ÀÌ»óȯ ¿Ü ¿ª, ÇѰܷ¹, 1989
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ¿Í ¹ÎÁÖÁÖÀÇ Á¤Ä¡ÀÌ·Ð : Å©¸®½ºÅäÆÛ ÇǾ, ¾î¼ö¿µ ¿ª, Çй®°ú »ç»ó»ç, 1989
    • ǪÄÚ¿Í ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ-»ý»ê¾ç½Ä ´ë Á¤º¸¾ç½Ä(¹Î¸Æ½Å¼­ 1) : ¸¶Å© Æ÷½ºÅÍ, Á¶±¤Á¦ ¿ª, ¹Î¸Æ, 1989
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿Í ·¹´ÑÁÖÀÇÀÇ ½Çõ³íÀï(°Å¸§½Å¼­ 44) :, À̼±ÀÏ Æí¿ª, °Å¸§, 1989
    • ¼Ò·ÃÀÇ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ(¸í¹®»ç»ó¼±Áý 19) : Á¦ÀÓ½º P. ½ºÄµ·±, °­ÀçÀ± ¿ª, ¸í¹®´ç, 1989
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º ·¹´ÑÁÖÀÇÀÇ °íÀüÀÔ¹® : ¾È³Ú¸®Á¦ ±×¸®Á¦ ¿Ü, À±Á¤À± Æí¿ª, °Å¸§, 1988
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º»ç»ó»çÀü : T. º¸Æ®¸ð¾Æ ¿Ü, ÀÓ¼®Áø Æí¿ª, û¾ÆÃâÆÇ»ç, 1988
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ Á¤Ä¡ÀÌ·Ð :, ÀÓÁö¿î Æí¿ª, µ¿³è, 1988
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ÃÁò Àü7±Ç : ÇÐ¹Î»ç °­ÁÂÆíÁýÀ§¿øÈ¸ Æí, Çйλç, 1988
    • °è¸ù»çÁ¶¿¡¼­ ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀDZîÁö : ¸¸µå·¹À̹߸®Âê³¢ Æí, Àå½Ç ¿ª, ½½¶óºê¿¬±¸»ç, 1988
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ ¿ª»çÀÌ·Ð : W. ¼î¾î, ±¸½ÂÈñ ¿ª, ûÇÏ, 1987
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º»ç»ó°ú ÁÖº¯À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â-Çö´ë»çȸ»ç»óÀÇ ÀÌ·ÐÀû ±âÃÊ(Àü¿¹¿ø»ç»ó½Å¼­ 19) : ³ë½Â¿ì, Àü¿¹¿ø, 1987
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º¿¡¼­ ¼Òºñ¿¡Æ® À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â·Î : I. Æäó, ȲÅ¿¬ ¿ª, Áß¿ø¹®È­, 1986
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º ÀÚº»·ÐÇØ¼³ : K. Ä«¿ìÃ÷Ű, ±¤ÁÖ ÆíÁýºÎ ¿ª, ±¤ÁÖ, 1986
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ : L. µÚÇÁ·¹, ±Ç¿Àö ¿ª, ¾ð¾î¹®È­»ç, 1986
    • ·¯½Ã¾Æ ¸¼½ºÁÖÀÇ : ´ÒÇϵù, À̼ºÇõ ¿ª, °Å¸§, 1986
    • Çö´ë¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÇ ÇöÀç¿Í ¹Ì·¡(¿­¸°±Û ½Ã¸®Áî 31) : H. M. ȦÂê, ÁÖÁ¤ÈÆ ¿ª, ÇÑ¿ï, 1985
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º °æÁ¦»ç»óÀÇ Çü¼º°úÁ¤ : E. ¸¸µ¨, ±èÅà ¿ª, ÇѰܷ¹, 1985
    • ¸·½ÃÁò, Ä޹´ÏÁò°ú ¼­±¸»çȸ : C. D. Ä¿¸µ Æí, µ¿¾ÆÃâÆÇ»ç, 1984
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ÃÁòÀÇ ÀÌÇØ : ±èÇÐÁØ, Á¤À½»ç, 1984
    • ¸¼½ÃÁò : ¾Ùºó ±¼µå³Ê, ±èÈ«¸í ¿ª, Çѹþ, 1984
    • ½Å¸¶¸£Å©½ÃÁò : ¾Èµå·¹¾Æ½º Æù ¹ÙÀ̽º, ±ÇÇõ¸é ¿ª, ÇѾç´ëÇб³ ÃâÆÇ¿ø, 1984
    • ¸¼½ÃÁòÀ̶õ ¹«¾ùÀΰ¡ : R. L. ÇÏÀϺê·Î³Ê, ½ÅÁ¤Çö Àå´ÞÁß °ø¿ª, ÇÑ¿ï, 1983
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÀÇ Àΰ£°ü(µ¿³è½Å¼­ 10) : E. ÇÁ·Ò, ±èâȣ ¿ª, µ¿³è, 1983
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ ºó°ï : B. P. ºê¸®½¦½½¶øÂÅÇÁ, ±è¿µ±¹ ¿ª, ¾Æ¼¼¾Æ¹®È­»ç, 1983
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½ºÁÖÀÇÀÚµé : C. W. ¹ÐÁî, ±èÈ«¸í ¿ª, Çѱæ»ç, 1982
    • ¸¼½º¿Í ¸¼½ºÁÖÀÇÀÚµé : ½Ãµå´Ï ÈÄÅ©, ¾çÈ£¹Î ¿ª, ¹®¸í»ç, 1982
    • ¸¶¸£Å©½º»çÈĹé³â(»ï¼º¹®È­¹®°í 33) : ߣô»ãáß², À¯±ÙÀÏ ¿ª, »ó¼º¹®È­Àç´Ü, 1973
    • ¸¼½ºÁÖÀÇ·Ð : A. G. ¸¶À̾î, ¾çÈ£¹Î ¿ª, À»À¯¹®È­»ç, 1948

¡¡

¡¡ ¡¡



¡¡
¡¡
 

 °Ô½ÃÆÇ  °Ë»ö  ÀÚ·á½Ç  »çÀÌÆ®¸Ê  ¿¹¼ö¿Í³ª?

¡¡
 

Jesusi.com Homepage



This page was last modified 2001/05/30