¡¡

Jesusi.com Homepage

¡¡

¡¡

 °Ô½ÃÆÇ  °Ë»ö  ÀÚ·á½Ç  »çÀÌÆ®¸Ê  ¿¹¼ö¿Í³ª?

¡¡
Philosophy 

öÇÐ - ÁöÇýÀÇ Å½±¸

Immanuel Kant

Ä­Æ®

¡¡

¡¡

1 Introduction

Immanuel Kant was the foremost thinker of the Enlightenment and one of the great philosophers of all time, in whom were subsumed new trends that had begun with the Rationalism (stressing reason) of René Descartes and the Empiricism (stressing experience) of Francis Bacon. He inaugurated a new era in the development of philosophical thought. His comprehensive and systematic work in theory of knowledge, ethics, and aesthetics greatly influenced all subsequent philosophy, especially the various German schools of Kantianism and Idealism. (see also  metaphysics)

This article deals with the man, his achievements, and the subsequent history of Kantianism.

2 Life and works

 

2.1 BACKGROUND AND EARLY YEARS

Kant was born on April 22, 1724, at Königsberg in East Prussia (now Kaliningrad, Russia) and lived in that remote province for his entire life. His father, a saddler, was, according to Kant, a descendant of a Scottish immigrant, although scholars have found no basis for this claim; his mother, an uneducated German woman, was remarkable for her character and natural intelligence. Both parents were devoted followers of the Pietist branch of the Lutheran Church, which taught that religion belongs to the inner life expressed in simplicity and obedience to moral law. The influence of their pastor made it possible for Kant--the fourth of nine children, but the eldest surviving child--to obtain an education.

At the age of eight Kant entered the Pietist school that his pastor directed. This was a Latin school, and it was presumably during the eight and a half years he was there that Kant acquired his lifelong love for the Latin classics, especially for the naturalistic poet Lucretius. In 1740 he enrolled in the University of Königsberg as a theological student. But, although he attended courses in theology and even preached on a few occasions, he was principally attracted to mathematics and physics. Aided by a young professor who had studied Christian Wolff, a systematizer of Rationalist philosophy, and who was also an enthusiast for the science of Sir Isaac Newton, Kant began reading the work of the English physicist and, in 1744, started his first book, dealing with a problem concerning kinetic forces. Though by that time he had decided to pursue an academic career, the death of his father in 1746 and his failure to obtain the post of undertutor in one of the schools attached to the university compelled him to withdraw and seek a means of supporting himself. (see also  mathematics, philosophy of)

2.1.1 Tutor and Privatdozent.

He found employment as a family tutor and, during the nine years that he gave to it, worked for three different families. With them he was introduced to the influential society of the city, acquired social grace, and made his farthest travels from his native city--some 60 miles (96 kilometres) away to the town of Arnsdorf. In 1755, aided by the kindness of a friend, he was able to complete his degree at the university and take up the position of Privatdozent, or lecturer.

Three dissertations that he presented on obtaining this post indicate the interest and direction of his thought at this time. In one, De Igne (On Fire), he argued that bodies operate on one another through the medium of a uniformly diffused elastic and subtle matter that is the underlying substance of both heat and light. His first teaching was in mathematics and physics, and he was never to lose his interest in scientific developments. That it was more than an amateur interest is shown by his publication within the next few years of several scientific works dealing with the different races of men, the nature of winds, the causes of earthquakes, and the general theory of the heavens.

At this period Newtonian physics was important to Kant as much for its philosophical implications as for its scientific content. A second dissertation, the Monodologia physica (1756), contrasted the Newtonian methods of thinking with those employed in the philosophy then prevailing in German universities. This was the philosophy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, a universal scholar, as systematized and popularized by Wolff and by Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, author of a widely used text, the Metaphysica (1739). Leibniz' works as they are now known were not fully available to these writers; and the Leibnizian philosophy that they presented was extravagantly Rationalistic, abstract, and cut-and-dried. It nevertheless remained a powerful force, and the main efforts of independent thinkers in Germany at the time were devoted to examining Leibniz's ideas.

In a third dissertation, Principiorum Primorum Cognitionis Metaphysicae Nova Dilucidato (1755), on the first principles of metaphysics, Kant analyzed especially the principle of sufficient reason, which, in Wolff's formulation, asserts that for everything there is a sufficient reason why it should be rather than not be. Although critical, Kant was cautious and still a long way from challenging the assumptions of Leibnizian metaphysics.

During the 15 years that he spent as a Privatdozent, Kant's renown as a teacher and writer steadily increased. Soon he was lecturing on many subjects other than physics and mathematics--including logic, metaphysics, and moral philosophy. He even lectured on fireworks and fortifications and every summer for 30 years taught a popular course on physical geography. He enjoyed great success as a lecturer; his lecturing style, which differed markedly from that of his books, was humorous and vivid, enlivened by many examples from his reading in English and French literature, and in travel and geography, science and philosophy.

Although he twice failed to obtain a professorship at Königsberg, he refused to accept offers that would have taken him elsewhere--including the professorship of poetry at Berlin that would have brought greater prestige. He preferred the peace and quiet of his native city in which to develop and mature his own philosophy.

2.1.2 Critic of Leibnizian Rationalism.

During the 1760s he became increasingly critical of Leibnizianism. According to one of his students, Kant was then attacking Leibniz, Wolff, and Baumgarten, was a declared follower of Newton, and expressed great admiration for the moral philosophy of the Romanticist Jean-Jacques Rousseau.

His principal work of this period was Untersuchung über die Deutlichkeit der Grundsätze der natürlichen Theologie und der Moral (1764; "An Inquiry into the Distinctness of the Fundamental Principles of Natural Theology and Morals"). In this work he attacked the claim of Leibnizian philosophy that philosophy should model itself on mathematics and aim at constructing a chain of demonstrated truths based on self-evident premises. Kant argued that mathematics proceeds from definitions that are arbitrary, by means of operations that are clearly and sharply defined, upon concepts that can be exhibited in concrete form. In contrast with this method, he argued that philosophy must begin with concepts that are already given, "though confusedly or insufficiently determined," so that philosophers cannot begin with definitions without thereby shutting themselves up within a circle of words. Philosophy cannot, like mathematics, proceed synthetically; it must analyze and clarify. The importance of the moral order, which he had learned from Rousseau, reinforced the conviction received from his study of Newton that a synthetic philosophy is empty and false. (see also  synthetic proposition)

Besides attacking the methods of the Leibnizians, he also began criticizing their leading ideas. In an essay Versuch, den Begriff der negativen Grössen in die Weltweisheit ein-zuführen (1763), he argued that physical opposition as encountered in things cannot be reduced to logical contradiction, in which the same predicate is both affirmed and denied, and, hence, that it is pointless to reduce causality to the logical relation of antecedent and consequent. In an essay of the same year, Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseyns Gottes, he sharply criticized the Leibnizian concept of Being by charging that the so-called ontological argument, which would prove the existence of God by logic alone, is fallacious because it confuses existential with attributive statements: existence, he declared, is not a predicate of attribution. Moreover, with regard to the nature of space, Kant sided with Newton in his confrontation with Leibniz. Leibniz' view that space is "an order of co-existences" and that spatial differences can be stated in conceptual terms, he concluded to be untenable.

Some indication of a possible alternative of Kant's own to the Leibnizian position can be gathered from his curious Träume eines Geistersehers erläutert durch Träume der Metaphysik (1766). This work is an examination of the whole notion of a world of spirits, in the context of an inquiry into the spiritualist claims of Emanuel Swedenborg, a scientist and biblical scholar. Kant's position at first seems to have been completely skeptical, and the influence of the Scottish Skeptic David Hume is more apparent here than in any previous work; it was Hume, he later claimed, who first awoke him from his dogmatic slumbers. Yet Kant was not so much arguing that the notion of a world of spirits is illusory as insisting that men have no insight into the nature of such a world, a conclusion that has devastating implications for metaphysics as the Leibnizians conceived it. Metaphysicians can dream as well as spiritualists, but this is not to say that their dreams are necessarily empty; there are already hints that moral experience can give content to the ideal of an "intelligible world." Rousseau thus acted upon Kant here as a counterinfluence to Hume.

2.1.3 Early years of the professorship at Königsberg.

Finally, in 1770, after serving for 15 years as a Privatdozent, Kant was appointed to the chair of logic and metaphysics, a position in which he remained active until a few years before his death. In this period--usually called his critical period, because in it he wrote his great Critiques--he published an astounding series of original works on a wide variety of topics, in which he elaborated and expounded his philosophy.

The Inaugural Dissertation of 1770 that he delivered on assuming his new position already contained many of the important elements of his mature philosophy. As indicated in its title, De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis: Dissertatio, the implicit dualism of the Träume is made explicit; and it is made so on the basis of a wholly un-Leibnizian interpretation of the distinction between sense and understanding. Sense is not, as Leibniz had supposed, a confused form of thinking but a source of knowledge in its own right, although the objects so known are still only "appearances"--the term that Leibniz also used. They are appearances because all sensing is conditioned by the presence, in sensibility, of the forms of time and space, which are not objective characteristics or frameworks of things but "pure intuitions." But though all knowledge of things sensible is thus of phenomena, it does not follow that nothing is known of things as they are in themselves. Certainly, man has no intuition, or direct insight, into an intelligible world; but the presence in him of certain "pure intellectual concepts, such as those of possibility, existence, necessity, substance, cause, enables him to have some descriptive knowledge of it. By means of these concepts he can arrive at an exemplar that provides him with "the common measure of all other things as far as real." This exemplar gives man an idea of perfection for both the theoretical and practical orders: in the first, it is that of the Supreme Being, God; in the latter, that of moral perfection.

After the Dissertation, Kant published virtually nothing for 11 years. Yet, in submitting the Dissertation to a friend at the time of its publication, he wrote:

About a year since I attained that concept which I do not fear ever to be obliged to alter, though I may have to widen it, and by which all sorts of metaphysical questions can be tested in accordance with entirely safe and easy criteria, and a sure decision reached as to whether they are soluble or insoluble.

2.2 PERIOD OF THE THREE "CRITIQUES"

In 1781 the Kritik der reinen Vernunft (spelled "Critik" in the first edition; Critique of Pure Reason) was published, followed for the next nine years by great and original works that in a short time brought a revolution in philosophical thought and established the new direction in which it was to go in the years to come.

2.2.1 The Critique of Pure Reason.

The Critique of Pure Reason was the result of some 10 years of thinking and meditation. Yet, even so, Kant published the first edition only reluctantly after many postponements; for although convinced of the truth of its doctrine, he was uncertain and doubtful about its exposition. His misgivings proved well-founded, and Kant complained that interpreters and critics of the work were badly misunderstanding it. To correct these wrong interpretations of his thought he wrote the Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können (1783) and brought out a second and revised edition of the first "critique" in 1787. Controversy still continues regarding the merits of the two editions: readers with a preference for an Idealistic interpretation usually prefer the first edition, whereas those with a Realistic view adhere to the second. But with regard to difficulty and ease of reading and understanding, it is generally agreed that there is little to choose between them. Anyone on first opening either book finds it overwhelmingly difficult and impenetrably obscure.

The cause for this difficulty can be traced in part to the works that Kant took as his models for philosophical writing. He was the first great modern philosopher to spend all of his time and efforts as a university professor of the subject. Regulations required that in all lecturing a certain set of books be used, with the result that all of Kant's teaching in philosophy had been based on such handbooks as those of Wolff and Baumgarten, which abounded in technical jargon, artificial and schematic divisions, and great claims to completeness. Following their example, Kant accordingly provided a highly artificial, rigid, and by no means immediately illuminating scaffolding for all three of his Critiques.

The Critique of Pure Reason, after an introduction, is divided into two parts, of very different lengths: A "Transcendental Doctrine of Elements," running to almost 400 pages in a typical edition, followed by a "Transcendental Doctrine of Method," which reaches scarcely 80 pages. The ". . . Elements" deals with the sources of human knowledge, whereas the ". . . Method" draws up a methodology for the use of "pure reason" and its a priori ideas. Both are "transcendental," in that they are presumed to analyze the roots of all knowledge and the conditions of all possible experience. The "Elements" is divided, in turn, into a "Transcendental Aesthetic," a "Transcendental Analytic," and a "Transcendental Dialectic." (see also  transcendental idealism, a priori knowledge)

The simplest way of describing the contents of the Critique is to say that it is a treatise about metaphysics: it seeks to show the impossibility of one sort of metaphysics and to lay the foundations for another. The Leibnizian metaphysics, the object of his attack, is criticized for assuming that the human mind can arrive, by pure thought, at truths about entities, which, by their very nature, can never be objects of experience, such as God, human freedom, and immortality. Kant maintained, however, that the mind has no such power and that the vaunted metaphysics is thus a sham.

As Kant saw it, the problem of metaphysics, as indeed of any science, is to explain how, on the one hand, its principles can be necessary and universal (such being a condition for any knowledge that is scientific) and yet, on the other hand, involve also a knowledge of the real and so provide the investigator with the possibility of more knowledge than is analytically contained in what he already knows; i.e., than is implicit in the meaning alone. To meet these two conditions, Kant maintained, knowledge must rest on judgments that are a priori, for it is only as they are separate from the contingencies of experience that they could be necessary and yet also synthetic; i.e., so that the predicate term contains something more than is analytically contained in the subject. Thus, for example, the proposition that all bodies are extended is not synthetic but analytic because the notion of extension is contained in the very notion of body; whereas the proposition that all bodies are heavy is synthetic because weight supposes, in addition to the notion of body, that of bodies in relation to one another. Hence, the basic problem, as Kant formulated it, is to determine "How [i.e., under what conditions] are synthetic a priori judgments possible?"

This problem arises, according to Kant, in three fields, viz., in mathematics, physics, and metaphysics; and the three main divisions of the first part of the Critique deal respectively with these. In the "Transcendental Aesthetic," Kant argued that mathematics necessarily deals with space and time and then claimed that these are both a priori forms of human sensibility that condition whatever is apprehended through the senses. In the "Transcendental Analytic," the most crucial as well as the most difficult part of the book, he maintained that physics is a priori and synthetic because in its ordering of experience it uses concepts of a special sort. These concepts-- "categories," he called them--are not so much read out of experience as read into it and, hence, are a priori, or pure, as opposed to empirical. But they differ from empirical concepts in something more than their origin: their whole role in knowledge is different; for, whereas empirical concepts serve to correlate particular experiences and so to bring out in a detailed way how experience is ordered, the categories have the function of prescribing the general form that this detailed order must take. They belong, as it were, to the very framework of knowledge. But although they are indispensable for objective knowledge, the sole knowledge that the categories can yield is of objects of possible experience; they yield valid and real knowledge only when they are ordering what is given through sense in space and time. (see also  mathematics, philosophy of)

In the "Transcendental Dialectic" Kant turned to consideration of a priori synthetic judgments in metaphysics. Here, he claimed, the situation is just the reverse from what it was in mathematics and physics. Metaphysics cuts itself off from sense experience in attempting to go beyond it and, for this very reason, fails to attain a single true a priori synthetic judgment. To justify this claim, Kant analyzed the use that metaphysics makes of the concept of the unconditioned. Reason, according to Kant, seeks for the unconditioned or absolute in three distinct spheres: (1) in philosophical psychology it seeks for an absolute subject of knowledge; (2) in the sphere of cosmology, it seeks for an absolute beginning of things in time, for an absolute limit to them in space, and for an absolute limit to their divisibility; and (3) in the sphere of theology, it seeks for an absolute condition for all things. In each case, Kant claimed to show that the attempt is doomed to failure by leading to an antinomy in which equally good reasons can be given for both the affirmative and the negative position. The metaphysical "sciences" of rational psychology, rational cosmology, and natural theology, familiar to Kant from the text of Baumgarten, on which he had to comment in his lectures, thus turn out to be without foundation.

With this work, Kant proudly asserted that he had accomplished a Copernican revolution in philosophy. Just as the founder of modern astronomy, Nicolaus Copernicus, had explained the apparent movements of the stars by ascribing them partly to the movement of the observers, so Kant had accounted for the application of the mind's a priori principles to objects by demonstrating that the objects conform to the mind: in knowing, it is not the mind that conforms to things but instead things that conform to the mind.

2.2.2 The Critique of Practical Reason.

Because of his insistence on the need for an empirical component in knowledge and his antipathy to speculative metaphysics, Kant is sometimes presented as a Positivist before his time; and his attack upon metaphysics was held by many in his own day to bring both religion and morality down with it. Such, however, was certainly far from Kant's intention. Not only did he propose to put metaphysics "on the sure path of science," he was prepared also to say that he "inevitably" believed in the existence of God and in a future life. It is also true that his original conception of his critical philosophy anticipated the preparation of a critique of moral philosophy. The Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (1788, spelled "Critik" and "practischen"; Critique of Practical Reason), the result of this intention, is the standard source book for his ethical doctrines. The earlier Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (1785) is a shorter and, despite its title, more readily comprehensible treatment of the same general topic. Both differ from Die Metaphysik der Sitten (1797) in that they deal with pure ethics and try to elucidate basic principles; whereas the later work is concerned with applying what they establish in the concrete, a process that involved the consideration of virtues and vices and the foundations of law and politics.

There are many points of similarity between Kant's ethics and his epistemology, or theory of knowledge. He used the same scaffolding for both--a "Doctrine of Elements," including an "Analytic" and a "Dialectic," followed by a "Methodology"; but the second Critique is far shorter and much less complicated. Just as the distinction between sense and intelligence was fundamental for the former, so is that between the inclinations and moral reason for the latter. And just as the nature of the human cognitive situation was elucidated in the first Critique by reference to the hypothetical notion of an intuitive understanding, so is that of the human moral situation clarified by reference to the notion of a "holy will." For a will of this kind there would be no distinction between reason and inclination; a being possessed of a holy will would always act as it ought. It would not, however, have the concepts of duty and moral obligation, which enter only when reason and desire find themselves opposed. In the case of human beings, the opposition is continuous, for man is at the same time both flesh and spirit; it is here that the influence of Kant's religious background is most prominent. Hence, the moral life is a continuing struggle in which morality appears to the potential delinquent in the form of a law that demands to be obeyed for its own sake--a law, however, the commands of which are not issued by some alien authority but represent the voice of reason, which the moral subject can recognize as his own.

In the "Dialectic," Kant took up again the ideas of God, freedom, and immortality. Dismissed in the first Critique as objects that men can never know because they transcend human sense experience, he now argued that they are essential postulates for the moral life. Though not reachable in metaphysics, they are absolutely essential for moral philosophy.

Kant is often described as an ethical Rationalist, and the description is not wholly inappropriate. He never espoused, however, the radical Rationalism of some of his contemporaries nor of more recent philosophers for whom reason is held to have direct insight into a world of values or the power to intuit the rightness of this or that moral principle. Thus, practical, like theoretical, reason was for him formal rather than material--a framework of formative principles rather than a content of actual rules. This is why he put such stress on his first formulation of the categorical imperative: "Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law." Lacking any insight into the moral realm, men can only ask themselves whether what they are proposing to do has the formal character of law--the character, namely, of being the same for all persons similarly circumstanced.

2.2.3 The Critique of Judgment.

The Kritik der Urteilskraft (1790: spelled "Critik")--one of the most original and instructive of all of Kant's writings--was not foreseen in his original conception of the critical philosophy. Thus it is perhaps best regarded as a series of appendixes to the other two Critiques. The work falls into two main parts, called respectively "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment" and "Critique of Teleological Judgment." In the first of these, after an introduction in which he discussed "logical purposiveness," he analyzed the notion of "aesthetic purposiveness" in judgments that ascribe beauty to something. Such a judgment, according to him, unlike a mere expression of taste, lays claim to general validity; yet it cannot be said to be cognitive because it rests on feeling, not on argument. The explanation lies in the fact that, when a person contemplates an object and finds it beautiful, there is a certain harmony between his imagination and his understanding, of which he is aware from the immediate delight that he takes in the object. Imagination grasps the object and yet is not restricted to any definite concept; whereas a person imputes the delight that he feels to others because it springs from the free play of his cognitive faculties, which are the same in all men.

In the second part, Kant turned to consider teleology in nature as it is posed by the existence in organic bodies of things of which the parts are reciprocally means and ends to each other. In dealing with these bodies, one cannot be content with merely mechanical principles. Yet if mechanism is abandoned and the notion of a purpose or end of nature is taken literally, this seems to imply that the things to which it applies must be the work of some supernatural designer; but this would mean a passing from the sensible to the suprasensible, a step proved in the first Critique to be impossible. Kant answered this objection by admitting that teleological language cannot be avoided in taking account of natural phenomena; but it must be understood as meaning only that organisms must be thought of "as if" they were the product of design, and that is by no means the same as saying that they are deliberately produced.

2.3 LAST YEARS

The critical philosophy was soon being taught in every important German-speaking university, and young men flocked to Königsberg as a shrine of philosophy. In some cases, the Prussian government even undertook the expense of their support. Kant came to be consulted as an oracle on all kinds of questions, including such subjects as the lawfulness of vaccination. Such homage did not interrupt Kant's regular habits. Scarcely five feet tall, with a deformed chest, and suffering from weak health, he maintained throughout his life a severe regimen. It was arranged with such regularity that people set their clocks according to his daily walk along the street named for him, "The Philosopher's Walk." Until old age prevented him, he is said to have missed this regular appearance only on the occasion when Rousseau's Émile so engrossed him that for several days he stayed at home.

With the publication of the third Critique, Kant's main philosophical work was done. From 1790 his health began to decline seriously. He still had many literary projects but found it impossible to write more than a few hours a day. The writings that he then completed consist partly of an elaboration of subjects not previously treated in any detail, partly of replies to criticisms and to the clarification of misunderstandings. With the publication in 1793 of his work Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft, Kant became involved in a dispute with Prussian authorities on the right to express religious opinions. The book was found to be altogether too Rationalistic for orthordox taste; he was charged with misusing his philosophy to the "distortion and depreciation of many leading and fundamental doctrines of sacred Scripture and Christianity" and was required by the government not to lecture or write anything further on religious subjects. Kant agreed but privately interpreted the ban as a personal promise to the King, from which he felt himself to be released on the latter's death in 1797. At any rate, he returned to the forbidden subject in his last major essay, Der Streit der Fakultäten (1798; "The Conflict of the Faculties").

The large work at which he laboured until his death--the fragments of which fill the two final volumes of the great Berlin edition of his works--was evidently intended to be a major contribution to his critical philosophy. What remains, however, is not so much an unfinished work as a series of notes for a work that was never written. Its original title was Übergang von den metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft zur Physik ("Transition from the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science to Physics"), and it may have been his intention to carry further the argument advanced in the Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft (1786) by showing that it is possible to construct a priori not merely the general outline of a science of nature but a good many of its details as well. But judging from the extant fragments, however numerous they are, it remains conjectural whether its completion would have constituted a major addition to his philosophy and its reputation.

After a gradual decline that was painful to his friends as well as to himself, Kant died in Königsberg, February 12, 1804. His last words were "Es ist gut" ("It is good"). His tomb in the cathedral was inscribed with the words (in German) "The starry heavens above me and the moral law within me," the two things that he declared in the conclusion of the second Critique "fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe, the oftener and the more steadily we reflect on." (O.A.B.)

3 Kantianism

As a philosophical designation, Kantianism can signify either the system of thought contained in the writings of the epoch-making 18th-century philosopher Immanuel Kant or those later philosophies that arose from the study of Kant's writings and drew their inspiration from his principles. Only the latter is the concern of this section.

3.1 NATURE AND TYPES OF KANTIANISM

The Kantian movement comprises a loose assemblage of rather diverse philosophies that share Kant's concern with exploring the nature, and especially the limits, of human knowledge in the hope of raising philosophy to the level of a science in some sense similar to mathematics and physics. Participating in the critical spirit and method of Kant, these philosophies are thus opposed to dogmatism, to expansive speculative naturalism (such as that of Baruch Spinoza, the Jewish Rationalist), and, usually, to irrationalism. The various submovements of Kantianism are characterized by their sharing of certain "family resemblances"; i.e., by the preoccupation of each with its own selection of concerns from among the many developments of Kant's philosophy: a concern, for example, with the nature of empirical knowledge; with the way in which the mind imposes its own categorial structure upon experience, and, in particular, with the nature of the structure that renders man's knowledge and moral action possible, a structure considered to be a priori (logically independent of experience); with the status of the Ding an sich ("thing-in-itself"), that more ultimate reality that presumably lurks behind man's apprehension of an object; or with the relationship between knowledge and morality. A brief exposition of Kant's philosophical system may be found above. (see also  epistemology, science, philosophy of, Empiricism, category)

A system such as the critical philosophy of Kant freely lends itself to reconstructions of its synthesis according to whatever preferences the private philosophical inclinations of the reader may impose or suggest. Kant's system was a syncretism, or union, of British Empiricism (as in John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume) that stressed the role of experience in the rise of knowledge; of the scientific methodology of Isaac Newton; and of the metaphysical apriorism (or Rationalism) of Christian Wolff, who systematized the philosophy of Gottfried Leibniz, with its emphasis on mind. Thus it constituted a synthesis of elements very different in origin and nature, which tempted the student to read his own presuppositions into it.

The critical philosophy has been subjected to a variety of approaches and methods of interpretation. These can be reduced to three fundamental types: those that conceive of the critical philosophy as an epistemology or a pure theory of (scientific) knowledge and methodology; those that conceive of it as a critical theory of metaphysics or the nature of Being (ultimate reality); and those that conceive of it as a theory of normative or valuational reflection parallel to that of ethics (in the field of action). Each of these types--known, respectively, as epistemological, metaphysical, and axiological Kantianism--can, in turn, be subdivided into several secondary approaches. Historically, epistemological Kantianism included such different attitudes as empirical Kantianism, rooted either in physiological or psychological inquiries; the logistic Kantianism of the Marburg school, which stressed essences and the use of logic; and the realistic Kantianism of the Austrian Alois Riehl. Metaphysical Kantianism developed from the transcendental Idealism of German Romanticism to Realism, a course followed by many speculative thinkers, who--like nearly all contemporary Kantians--saw in the critical philosophy the foundations of an essentially inductive metaphysics, in accordance with the results of the modern sciences. Finally, axiological Kantianism--concerned with value theory--branched, first, into an axiological approach (properly so-called), which interpreted the methods of all three of Kant's Critiques (i.e., Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of Practical Reason, and Critique of Judgment) as normative disciplines of thought; and, second, into an eclectic or relativistic Kantianism, which regarded the critical philosophy as a system of thought dependent upon social, cultural, and historical conditions. (see also  idealism)

The chief representatives of these submovements are identified in the historical sections below.

It is essential to distinguish clearly between two periods within the Kantian movement: first, the period from 1790 to 1831 (the death of Hegel); and, second, the period from 1860 to the present--separated by a time when an antiphilosophical Positivism, a type of thought that supplanted metaphysics with science, was predominant. The first period began with the thorough study and emendation of Kant's chief theoretical work, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (2nd ed., 1787; the Critique of Pure Reason, 1929); but it soon became intermingled with the romantic tendencies in German Idealism. The second period, called specifically Neo-Kantianism, was, first of all, a conscious reappraisal, in whole or in part, of the theoretical Critique, but also, as a total system, a reaction against Positivism. Earlier Neo-Kantianism reduced philosophy to the theory of knowledge and scientific methodology; systematic Neo-Kantianism, arising at the beginning of the 20th century, expressed itself in attempts at building metaphysical structures.

3.2 EARLY KANTIANISM: 1790-1835

According to Immanuel Kant, his major work, the Critique of Pure Reason, comprised a treatise on methodology, a preliminary investigation prerequisite to the study of science, which placed the Newtonian method (induction, inference, and generalization) over against that of Descartes and Wolff (deduction from intuitions asserted to be self-evident). The result was a critique of metaphysics, the value of which lay not in science but in a realm of being accessible only to the pure intellect. In exploring this "noumenal" realm, as he called it, Kant placed his Critique in a positive role. Recalling the revolution that occurred in astronomy when Nicolaus Copernicus discerned, in the apparent motions of the planets, reflections of the earth's own motion, Kant inaugurated a Copernican revolution in philosophy, which claimed that the subject doing the knowing constitutes, to a considerable extent, the object; i.e., that knowledge is in part constituted by a priori or transcendental factors (contributed by the mind itself), which the mind imposes upon the data of experience. Far from being a description of an external reality, knowledge is, to Kant, the product of the knowing subject. When the data are those of sense experience, the transcendental (mental) apparatus constitutes man's experience or his science, or makes it to be such. These transcendental elements are of three different orders: at the lowest level are the forms of space and time (technically called intuitions); above these are the categories and principles of man's intelligence (among them substance, causality, and necessity); and at the uppermost level of abstraction the ideas of reason--the transcendental "I," the world as a whole, and God. It is by virtue of the encounter between the forms of man's sensory intuition (space and time) and his perceptions that phenomena are formed. The forms arise from the subject himself; the perceptions, however--or the data of experience--have reference, ultimately, to things-in-themselves, which nevertheless remain unknowable, inasmuch as, in order to be known at all, it is necessary for things to appear clothed, as it were, in the forms of man's intuition and, thenceforth, to present themselves as phenomena and not as noumena. The thing-in-itself, accordingly, indicates the limit and not the object of knowledge. (see also  noumenon)

These theses of Kant provoked criticism among the followers of Christian Wolff, the Leibnizian Rationalist, and doubts among the disciples of Kant, which, as they further developed into systems, marked the first period of Kantianism. Inasmuch as these disciples took the Critique of Pure Reason to be a preface to the study of the pure reason or of the transcendental system and not the system itself, they saw in this interpretation an explanation for the ambiguities to which the Critique (as they felt) was subject. Their doubts revolved around two points: first, Kant had erroneously distinguished three kinds of a priori knowledge, coordinate with the three aforementioned levels or faculties of the mind; and second, Kant had accepted the thing-in-itself as constitutive of knowledge. Regarding the first point, they claimed that Kant had accepted the three faculties and their respective transcendental characteristics without investigation, in which case this structure should be viewed, in accordance with the preliminary character of the Critique, as a triple manifestation of a single fundamental faculty. For this reason the distinction between the levels of intuition and understanding (or between the receptivity and spontaneity of the mind) had to be rejected--for the three transcendentals--space and time, the categories, and the ideas of reason--were not existents but were only functions of thought. Finally, these disciples argued that the existence of a single transcendental subject, the Ego, would render the thing-in-itself superfluous and even pernicious for the scientific treatment of epistemology.

This function of human thought (the transcendental subject), which serves as the absolute source of the a priori, was variously designated by different early Kantian thinkers: for the German Realist Karl L. Reinhold, it constituted the faculty of representation; for the Lithuanian Idealist Salomon Maimon, it was a mental capacity for constructing objects; for the Idealist Jakob S. Beck, a protégé of Kant's, it was the act of synthesis; for the empirical critic of Kantianism G.E. Schulze, it was experience in the sense intended by Hume--a volley of discrete sense impressions; for the theory of knowledge of the outstanding ethical Idealist Johann G. Fichte, it was the original positing of the Ego and the non-Ego--which meant, in turn, in the case of the aesthetic Idealist F.W.J. von Schelling, "the absolute self," and in the case of G.W.F. Hegel "the Geist or absolute Spirit," and finally, in the case of the pessimistic Romanticist Arthur Schopenhauer, "the absolute Will." In each case (excepting Schulze) the interpretation of the thing-in-itself in a realistic metaphysical sense was rejected in favour of various degrees of transcendental Idealism. Removed from the main current of Kantianism was the empirically oriented thinker Jakob Friedrich Fries (the one figure in this group who was not an Idealist in the true sense), who interpreted the a priori in terms of psychological faculties and elements.

Having earlier renounced these apostates on a large scale, Kant, at the end of his life, prepared a new exposition of the transcendental philosophy (the second part of his Opus Postumum), which showed that he was ready tacitly to accede to the criticisms of his adversaries.

3.3 NEO-KANTIANISM: SINCE 1860

 

3.3.1 Nineteenth-century Neo-Kantianism.

The rejection of all of philosophy by Positivism had the anomalous effect of, itself, evoking an awakening of Kantianism, for many thinkers wished to give to Positivism itself a philosophical foundation that, while respecting the phenomenological attitude, would yet be hostile to the metaphysics of Positivism, which was usually a tacit, but inconsequent, Materialism. It was justifiably held that Kant could provide such a foundation because of his opposition to metaphysics and his limitation of scientific knowledge to the sphere of phenomena. The complexity of the critical philosophy was such that the theoretical criticism could be approached in diverse ways and that, through the facts themselves, diverse interpretations of the Critique of Pure Reason could be obtained. In the order of their origin (though not of their worth or importance), there thus arose currents of Kantianism that were empiricist, logicist, realist, metaphysical, axiological, and psychological--of which the most important have survived into the 20th century.

The return to Kant was determined by the historical fresco of the incomparable historian of philosophy Kuno Fischer entitled Kants Leben und die Grundlagen seiner Lehre (1860; "Kant's Life and the Foundations of his Teaching"), which replaced the earlier work of the semi-Kantian Ernst Reinhold, son of the more notable Jena scholar (published 1828-30), and especially that of the outstanding historian of philosophy Johann Eduard Erdmann (published 1834-53). In 1865 the order: "Zurück nach Kant!" ("Back to Kant!") reverberated through the celebrated work of the young epistemologist Otto Liebmann, Kant und die Epigonen ("Kant and his Followers"), which was destined to extricate their spirits from the Positivistic morass and, at the same time, to divert the Germans from romantic Idealism.

 

3.3.1.1 Epistemological Neo-Kantianism.

The empiricist, logistic, and realistic schools can be classed as epistemological.

Empiricist Neo-Kantianism was represented by the erudite pioneering physicist and physiologist Hermann L.F. von Helmholtz and, in part, by F.A. Lange, author of a famous study of Materialism. Helmholtz found support in Kant for his claim, first, that, although perception can represent an external thing, it usually does so in a way far removed from an actual description of its properties; second, that space and time comprise an empirical framework created for thought by the perceiving subject; and, third, that causality is an a priori law allowing the philosopher to infer a reality that is absolutely unknowable. Similarly, Lange reduced science to the phenomenal level and repudiated the thing-in-itself.

Logistic Neo-Kantianism, as represented in the most well-known and flourishing school of Kantianism, that at Marburg, originated with Hermann Cohen, successor of Lange, who, in a book on Kant (1871), argued that the transcendental subject is not to be regarded as a psychic being but as a logical function of thought that constructs both the form and the content of knowledge. Nothing is gegeben ("given"), he urged; all is aufgegeben ("propounded," like a riddle) to thought--as when, in the infinitesimal calculus, the analyst generates motion by imagining thin slices of space and time and adding up their areas. Hence experience is a perfect construction of man's logical spirit. Cohen's example inspired many authors, among them Cohen's colleague at Marburg Paul Natorp, who, in his work on the logical foundations of the exact sciences, integrated even psychology into the Marburgian transcendentalism; and Ernst Cassirer, best known for stressing the symbolizing capacities of man, who, in his memorable work Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit (1906-20; The Problem of Knowledge: Philosophy, Science, and History since Hegel, 1966), transposed this same logisticism into a form that illumines the history of modern philosophy.

Realistic Neo-Kantianism, the third manifestation of epistemological Neo-Kantianism, was represented in the Realism of the scientific monist Alois Riehl and of his disciple Richard Hönigswald. In a work on the significance of the critical philosophy for the positive sciences (published 1876-87), Riehl held, in direct opposition to the Marburgian logisticism, that the thing-in-itself participates positively in the constitution of knowledge inasmuch as all perception includes a reference to things outside the subject.

 

3.3.1.2 Metaphysical Neo-Kantianism.

Ten years after the appearance of the aforementioned ground-breaking book Kant und die Epigonen, its author, Otto Liebmann, introduced the new metaphysical approach in his book on the analysis of reality (1876), which came near to the Kantianism of Marburg. The Romanticist Johannes Volkelt, in turn, took up the theme of a critical metaphysics and expressed his persisting aspirations toward the Absolute in the claim that, beyond the certainties of man's own subjective consciousness, there exists a new kind of certainty in a transsubjective realm. Subjectivity is, thus, inevitably transcended, just as the sciences are surmounted when they presuppose a metaphysics. The influential spiritual moralist Friedrich Paulsen defended the claim that Kant had always behaved as a metaphysician, even in the Critique of Pure Reason, in spite of the epistemological restrictions that he imposed upon himself--a claim that made an impact that was felt throughout the following century.

 

3.3.1.3 Axiological Neo-Kantianism.

Inasmuch as the two principal representatives of the axiological interpretation both taught at Heidelberg, this branch is also known as the Southwest German or Baden school. Its initiator was Wilhelm Windelband, esteemed for his "problems" approach to the history of philosophy. The scholar who systematized this position was his successor Heinrich Rickert, who had come from the tradition of Kuno Fischer. Drawing a parallel between the constraints that logic exerts upon thought and those that the sense of ought exerts upon ethical action, these thinkers argued that, while man's action must answer to an absolute value (the Good), his thought must answer to a regulative value (the True), which imposes upon him the duty of conforming to it. The Critique of Pure Reason, they held, elaborates this rule--which is not an entity but an imperative, or absolute, charge to act. Rickert regarded the critical endeavour as having been too narrow, since it was suited merely to physics. Actually, he charged, it should be the foundation for all of the sciences of the spirit. The distinctive characteristic of this school thus consisted in reintegrating German Idealism (as in Fichte and Hegel) into a rather personal Kantianism. Consequently, it succeeded in annexing more than one area of semi-Kantian thought: e.g., "the philosophy of the spiritual sciences" of Wilhelm Dilthey, who held that intellectual life cannot be explained by means of naturalistic causality but only through historical understanding (Verstehen); "the life-philosophy" of the social philosopher Georg Simmel, who deviated from an earlier naturalistic relativism to the espousal of objective values; "the philosophy of value" of the experimental psychologist Hugo Münsterberg, author of one of the earliest systems of values; the "semi-Hegelianism" of Richard Kroner, a philosopher of culture and religion; and the general works of Bruno Bauch, Liebmann's successor at Jena. All of these philosophers were more or less related to axiological Neo-Kantianism. (see also  axiology)

 

3.3.1.4 Psychological Neo-Kantianism.

An initial attempt to interpret Kantian transcendentalism in psychological terms was made by the Friesian Empiricist Jürgen Bona Meyer in his Kants Psychologie (1870). Later, a more important contribution in this field was made by the Göttingen philosopher of ethics and law Leonard Nelson and published in the Abhandlungen der Fries'schen Schule (1904 ff; "Acts of the Friesian School"). Even this title suggests an intimate agreement with the Kantianism of Fries's new critique of reason (1807); and Nelson, indeed, is regarded as the founder of the Neo-Friesian school. At a time when other Kantian schools were concerned with the transcendental analysis of objective or outer knowledge, Nelson held that, in the analysis of the subjective or inner self, the transcendental equipment of the mind--the a priori--is directly revealed. It thus fell to psychology to lay bare this equipment, which belongs in itself to the metaphysical order. It was upon this basis that the Marburg theologian Rudolf Otto, in his book Das Heilige (1917; The Idea of the Holy, 1958), ventured a type of religious phenomenology that has proved very successful.

A discipline known as the Kant Philologie, concerned with the history, development, and works of Kant, has pre-empted a considerable portion of philosophical historiography since 1860. These studies began with the immense commentary on the Critique of Pure Reason produced in 1881-92 by Hans Vaihinger, known for his philosophy of the "As If " (which stresses man's reliance on pragmatic fictions), and with the founding of the new journal Kantstudien (1896) and the Kant-Gesellschaft ("Kantian Society," 1904)--both still extant. The most conspicuous result of this philological movement, however, was undeniably the monumental edition, in 23 volumes, of all of Kant's available works prepared (1900 ff) by the Academy of Sciences at Berlin under the editorship of the champion of humanistic studies, Wilhelm Dilthey. These volumes include: Sect. 1, Works; Sect. 2, Correspondence; Sect. 3, The "Nachlass." Since the transfer of this task to the University of Münster, Sect. 4, Kant's Lectures, has been undertaken. Those on logic and metaphysics (vols. 24-25) have been splendidly edited by Gerhard Lehmann.

 

3.3.2 Contemporary Neo-Kantianism.

The recent development of Neo-Kantianism, except for innumerable historical studies, is very one-sided: no longer considered as exclusively epistemological, it merely prolongs the metaphysical school. Moreover, a large portion of the present Kant research is covered by the so-called Problems of Kantianism (see below). Important studies have been made on the development of Kant's philosophical thought, on Kant as a metaphysician, on his ontology and teachings on science, and on his transcendental deduction.

3.4 NON-GERMAN KANTIANISM

The Kantian awakening, in no wise limited to Germany, extended throughout Western philosophy. Its principal initiators were as follows: France was the first to open to its influence, beginning with the eclectic thinker Victor Cousin, who had studied German authors and made several trips to Germany. The relativistic personalist Charles Renouvier then defended a rather personal critical philosophy, which exerted an enduring influence through its impact upon the extreme Idealist Octave Hamelin of the Sorbonne; upon the metaphysician and cofounder of French neospiritualism Jules Lachelier; and upon his pupil, the philosopher of science Émile Boutroux.

The English-speaking countries, on the other hand, have not seemed disposed to assimilate the critical philosophy as they did Hegelian Idealism. Except for the Scottish religious absolutist Edward Caird (The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant, 1889), who was chiefly an Hegelian, there was in Britain at the close of the 19th century only another Scot, the critical Realist Robert Adamson, who was a Kantian. After him, however, can be cited the commentary, published in 1918, of Norman Kemp Smith, producer of the standard English translation of Kant's first Critique, and more recently, the remarkable exposition by the Oxford Kantian Herbert J. Paton, Kant's Metaphysic of Experience (2 volumes, 1936). Finally, Kantian methods can be discerned today in the later work of the prominent Oxford "ordinary language" philosopher, Peter F. Strawson, entitled Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (1959). Kantianism became known in the United States toward 1840 primarily through the New England transcendentalist and poet Ralph Waldo Emerson--who was not, however, a Kantian himself. The physicist and logician Charles Sanders Peirce owes his Pragmatism largely to Kant's role as a counterweight against Hegelianism. The former southern California philosopher William H. Werkmeister represents a type of Neo-Kantianism inspired by the Marburg school (The Basis and Structure of Knowledge, 1948). (see also  "Critique of Pure Reason," )

Italian scholars, on the other hand, have been vigorously engaged in Kantian studies since the initiative was taken by Alfonso Testa. The chief Neo-Kantian in Italy, however, was the Realist Carlo Cantoni, who took an anti-Positivist stance. Later, in the period from 1900 to 1918, Kantianism was represented by the extreme Realism of the theist Francesco Orestano. A school of Kantian philology has formed at Turin around the erudite Christian Idealist Augusto Guzzo and his journal Filosofia. More independent in spirit is the work of the critical ontologist Pantaleo Carabellese, Giovanni Gentile's successor at Rome. (see also  idealism)

3.5 ASSESSMENT OF KANTIANISM

At the present time there does not exist, either in Germany or elsewhere, a purely Kantian philosopher; but all acknowledge the obligation to come to grips with him. Within the four great currents of contemporary thought, however--i.e., in Phenomenology, in the traditionalistic metaphysics, in Existentialism, and in the Positivistic Empiricism of the Vienna Circle and of Analytical philosophy--the predominant attitude toward Kant is negative.

 

3.5.1 Problems of Kantianism.

As far as epistemology is concerned, the critical philosophy constitutes a theory of science that agrees with current trends; for science must have a base that is empirical though also real. On the other hand, the transcendental or a priori is implicated; and severe complications ensue whenever the question is posed whether a type of apprehension can be acquired apart from experience that conveys, however, some new and genuine knowledge--whether, in short, synthetic a priori judgments can be made. Significantly, the founder of Phenomenology, the German philosopher Edmund Husserl, came back to the fold of Kantian transcendentalism after previously opposing it bitterly. As against the Kantian position, Empiricism entirely rejects the possibility (and even the meaning) of the synthetic a priori and, robbed thereby of everything traditionally regarded as the subject matter of philosophy, directs its philosophical inquiries principally to the study of language. The foremost recent analyst of language, however, the pioneering philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein, imposed upon philosophy the obligation to limit reason (or the transcendental element in knowledge)--a semi-Kantian position, which he nonetheless later renounced. As for Existentialism, one of recent Germany's foremost philosophers, Martin Heidegger, has presented in his Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929; Eng. trans., Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, 1962) a highly personalized interpretation. A student of Cohen at Marburg, the metaphysician Nicolai Hartmann, became the harbinger of the Realistic approach, elaborating in his analysis of the metaphysics of knowledge (1921) an ontological relation that he discerned to obtain between two forms of being: between thought and reality. Accordingly, the principles of thought correspond, in his view, to those of reality--a position at odds with Kant (even when he is interpreted as a Realist). Moreover, Hartmann treated the problems of mathematics--so urgent in current philosophy--in a manner that is again completely opposed to Kant; in particular, he questioned the validity of Kant's a priori intuition (or positing) of the spatio-temporal framework in terms of which man thinks about the world, challenging Kant at this point not merely to accommodate the non-Euclidean geometries (with curved space) that afforded a Realist alternative to the a priori but above all to reflect the distinctly logistic position regarding the foundations of mathematics to which he adhered. Discussion of the status of the thing-in-itself in man's knowledge of the real remained on the philosophical agenda both during and after Hartmann's time, but invoked the same indecision as it always had. At a time when Hartmann was accepting the thing-in-itself almost naïvely, Empiricism (in all its forms) rejected it categorically and attempted to construe the real in terms merely of what Kant had called phenomena. In the realm of ethics, Phenomenologists and Existentialists were dissatisfied with the purely formal character of Kant's ethics--i.e., with its lack of specificity--and substituted a "material" ethic, of concrete duties, which was no less absolute than that of Kant. For their part, Empiricists were only interested in the analysis of expressions of moral judgment, which they reduced to imperative statements that are emotive and aimed at winning adherents. (see also  Marburg school, mathematics, philosophy of)

 

3.5.2 Objections to Kantianism.

It must be acknowledged that Kant has furnished many of the most significant themes that are found in the currents of contemporary philosophy, even in the forms that they still assume today. Yet, as compared with the state of affairs that existed from 1860 to 1918, Kantianism has suffered an impressive decline--though a slight recovery seems to have occurred during the third quarter of the 20th century.

What were the reasons for this decline? In general, since World War I the reduction of philosophy to the philosophy of science has no longer been accepted, though contemporary Positivistic Empiricism has offered hardly any objection to it. The philosophy of science comprises, in fact, only one problem area, not the entire assemblage of philosophical problems. From this a second objection arises: Kantianism in general is too formalistic to satisfy man's actual inquisitiveness, which inclines more and more toward concrete concerns. Kantianism restricts itself to examining the a priori forms of thought and cares little for its diverse contents. Were this objection pertinent only to the exact sciences, it would not be serious--for these sciences attend to their own applications; but the objection becomes very grave for the field of ethics. For this reason, the objection against Kant's formalism has been raised most passionately against his ethical treatise, the Critique of Practical Reason--as by Hartmann, by the Phenomenologist Max Scheler, and by others. This transcendental formalism immediately encounters the further objection of subjectivism--in spite of efforts (from the side of logic) to evade it--i.e., it is blamed for obstructing man's apprehension of the real universality of his Ego, of the thinking subject, and for inexorably impelling the scholar to the view that man's knowledge is merely the product of subjective construction. This subjectivistic transcendentalism, by its intrinsic logic, denies man access to the external world. Not only does it debar him from the world of things-in-themselves but it also prevents him from granting objective reality to phenomena as such, inasmuch as the transcendental source is here viewed as playing a constructive role with respect to experience and the phenomenon. (see also  a priori knowledge, "Critique of Practical Reason," )

These three major objections, which stand out in the midst of many criticisms of minor details, recur constantly in the Kantian literature of the past quarter of a century. The result of these objections, as far as the evaluation of the critical philosophy is concerned, is that it is repudiated in its entirety--without, however, being thereby considered barred by limitation. Kant thus remains, in spite of everything, an inexhaustible source of problems and ideas, comparable in this respect to Plato and Aristotle, with whom he forms the great triad of Western philosophical thought. (H.J. de V.)

¡¡

Ä­Æ® (Immanuel Kant). 1724. 4. 22 ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ Äê´ÏÈ÷½ºº£¸£Å©~1804. 2. 12 Äê´ÏÈ÷½ºº£¸£Å©. µ¶ÀÏÀÇ °è¸ùÁÖÀÇ »ç»ó°¡.

öÇл縦 ÅëÆ²¾î °¡Àå À§´ëÇÑ Ã¶ÇÐÀÚ Áß ÇÑ »ç¶÷ÀÌ´Ù. À̸¶´©¿¤ Ä­Æ®´Â ¸£³× µ¥Ä«¸£Æ®¿¡¼­ ½ÃÀÛµÈ ÇÕ¸®·Ð°ú ÇÁ·£½Ã½º º£ÀÌÄÁ¿¡¼­ ½ÃÀÛµÈ °æÇè·ÐÀ» Á¾ÇÕÇß´Ù. ±×´Â öÇÐÀû »çÀ¯ÀÇ »õ·Î¿î ÇÑ ½Ã´ë¸¦ ¿­¾ú´Ù. ÀνķС¤À±¸®ÇС¤¹ÌÇп¡ °ÉÄ£ Á¾ÇÕÀû¡¤Ã¼°èÀûÀÎ ÀÛ¾÷Àº µÚ¿¡ »ý°Ü³­ öÇе鿡 Å« ¿µÇâÀ» ÁÖ¾ú´Ù.

Ãʱâ»ý¾Ö

Ä­Æ®´Â 1724³â 4¿ù 22ÀÏ µ¿ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ Äê´ÏÈ÷½ºº£¸£Å©(1946³âºÎÅÍ ¼Ò·Ã¿¡ ¼ÓÇÏ°Ô µÇ¾úÀ½)¿¡¼­ ž, Àü»ý¾Ö¸¦ °Å±â¿¡¼­ º¸³Â´Ù. Ä­Æ®´Â ¸¶±¸»óÀÎÀ̾ú´ø ¾Æ¹öÁö°¡ ½ºÄÚÆ²·£µå¿¡¼­ À̹ο »ç¶÷ÀÇ ÀÚ¼ÕÀ̶ó°í ÇßÁö¸¸ ¶Ñ·ÇÇÑ Áõ°Å¸¦ ã±â ¾î·Æ´Ù. ¾î¸Ó´Ï´Â µ¶ÀÏÀÎÀ¸·Î ±³À°À» ¹ÞÁö ¸øÇßÁö¸¸, Ÿ°í³­ ÀÎǰ°ú Áö¼ºÀ¸·Î À¯¸íÇß´Ù. ºÎ¸ð ¸ðµÎ ·çÅͱ³ °æ°ÇÆÄÀÇ µ¶½ÇÇÑ ½ÅÀÚ¿´´Ù. ÀÌ ±³ÆÄ´Â °Ë¼ÒÇÑ ³»Àû »î°ú µµ´ö¹ý¿¡ ´ëÇÑ º¹Á¾À» °¡¸£ÃÆ´Ù. ÀÌ ±³ÆÄ ¸ñȸÀÚÀÇ ¿µÇâÀ¸·Î Ä­Æ®´Â ±³À°À» ¹ÞÀ» ¼ö ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.

8¼¼ ¶§ ´ãÀÓ¸ñ»ç°¡ ¿î¿µÇÏ´ø °æ°ÇÁÖÀÇ Çб³¿¡ µé¾î°¬´Ù. ¶óƾ¾î¸¦ °¡¸£Ä¡´ø ÀÌ Çб³¿¡¼­ 8³â 6°³¿ù µ¿¾È ¹è¿ü´Âµ¥, ÀÏ»ý¿¡ °ÉÃÄ ¶óƾ¾î °íÀüÀ» ÁÁ¾ÆÇÏ°Ô µÈ °ÍÀº ¹Ù·Î À̶§ ¹ÞÀº ±³À° ¶§¹®À̾ú´Ù. 1740³â¿¡ Äê´ÏÈ÷½ºº£¸£Å©´ëÇб³¿¡ ½ÅÇлýÀ¸·Î ÀÔÇÐÇß´Ù. ½ÅÇаúÁ¤À» À̼öÇϸ鼭 ¶§¶§·Î ¼³±³µµ ÇßÁö¸¸, ÁÖ·Î Èï¹Ì¸¦ ´À³¤ °ÍÀº ¼öÇаú ¹°¸®ÇÐÀ̾ú´Ù. ÇÕ¸®·Ð öÇÐÀ» ü°èÈ­½ÃŲ Å©¸®½ºÆ¼¾È º¼ÇÁ¸¦ ¿¬±¸ÇßÀ¸¸ç, µ¿½Ã¿¡ ¾ÆÀÌÀÛ ´ºÅÏÀÇ °úÇÐÀ» ¿­·ÄÈ÷ ½ÅºÀÇß´ø ¾î¶² ÀþÀº ±³¼öÀÇ µµ¿òÀ¸·Î ´ºÅÏÀÇ ÀúÀÛµµ Àб⠽ÃÀÛÇß´Ù. 1744³â¿¡´Â ÃÖÃÊÀÇ Ã¥À» ½è´Âµ¥, ÁÖÁ¦´Â ¿îµ¿·Â¿¡ °üÇÑ °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ´ç½Ã ±×´Â ÇÐÀÚÀÇ ±æÀ» ÅÃÇϱâ·Î ¸¶À½¸Ô¾úÁö¸¸, 1746³â ¾Æ¹öÁö°¡ Á×°í, ´ëÇкμÓÇб³¿¡¼­ Á¶±³Á÷À» ¾ò´Â µ¥ ½ÇÆÐÇÏÀÚ ±×´Â °¡Á¤±³»çÁ÷À» ±¸Çؼ­ 9³â µ¿¾È ÀÏÇß´Ù. 1755³â¿¡ Ä£±¸ÀÇ µµ¿òÀ¸·Î ´ëÇп¡¼­ ÇÐÀ§¸¦ ¸¶Ä¡°í ¹«±Þ(ÙíÐå) ´ëÇа­»ç°¡ µÇ¾ú´Ù.

15³â µ¿¾ÈÀÇ °­»ç ½Ã±â´Â Ä­Æ®°¡ °­»ç¿Í Àú¼ú°¡·Î¼­ Á¡Á¡ Å« ¸í¼ºÀ» ¾ò°Ô µÇ´Â ½ÃÀýÀÌ´Ù. ù °­ÀÇ´Â ¼öÇаú ¹°¸®Çп¡ °üÇÑ °ÍÀ̾ú°í, °úÇÐ ¹ßÀü¿¡ ´ëÇÑ °ü½ÉÀ» °áÄÚ ÀÒÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. °ü½ÉÀÇ ¼öÁØÀÌ ¾Æ¸¶Ãß¾î ÀÌ»óÀ̾ú´Ù´Â °ÍÀº À̶§ºÎÅÍ ¸î ³â µ¿¾È ÀÎÁ¾, ¹Ù¶÷ÀÇ º»Áú, ÁöÁøÀÇ ¿øÀÎ, õü¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÀϹÝÀÌ·Ð µîÀ» ´Ù·é °úÇÐÀúÀÛµéÀ» ´Ù¼ö ¹ß°£Çß´Ù´Â »ç½Ç¿¡¼­ ¾Ë ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù. ¼öÇаú ¹°¸®Çп¡¼­ ½ÃÀÛµÈ °­ÀÇ´Â ´Ù¾çÇÑ ºÐ¾ß·Î È®´ëµÇ¾ú´Ù. ³í¸®ÇС¤ÇüÀÌ»óÇС¤µµ´ööÇÐ µî öÇÐÀÇ ÁÖ¿äºÐ¾ß ¹× ÀÚ¿¬Áö¸®Çп¡ À̸£±â±îÁö °­ÀÇ ÁÖÁ¦°¡ ³Ð¾îÁ³´Ù. ±ÛÀ» ¾²´Â ½ºÅ¸Àϰú ´Þ¸® °­ÀÇ´Â À¯¸Ó¿Í ¹ÚÁø°¨ÀÌ ³ÑÃÆÀ¸¸ç, ¿µ±¹¡¤ÇÁ¶û½ºÀÇ ¹®ÇÐÀº ¹°·Ð, ¿©Çà±â¿Í Áö¸®ÇÐ, °úÇаú öÇÐ µî ±¤¹üÀ§ÇÑ µ¶¼­¿¡¼­ ¾òÀº dzºÎÇÑ ½Ç·Ê¸¦ µé¾î ½Ç°¨ ÀÖ°í »ý±â ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.

Äê´ÏÈ÷½ºº£¸£Å©¿¡¼­ ±³¼öÁ÷À» ¾ò´Â µ¥ 2¹øÀ̳ª ½ÇÆÐÇßÀ½¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í ±×¸¦ ±³¼ö·Î µ¥¸®°í °¡·Á ÇÑ ´Ù¸¥ ´ëÇÐÀÇ Á¦¾ÈµéÀ» ¹Þ¾ÆµéÀÌÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. º£¸¦¸°´ëÇб³´Â ´Ù¸¥ °÷¿¡ ºñÇØ ¸¹Àº Ư±ÇÀ» ºÎ¿©Çϸ鼭±îÁö ½ÃÇÐ ±³¼ö·Î ÃʺùÇßÀ¸³ª À̰͵µ °ÅÀýÇß´Ù. ±×´Â °íÇâ¿¡¼­ Á¶¿ëÇÏ°í ÆòÈ­·Ó°Ô Áö³»¸é¼­ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀ» ¹ßÀü½ÃŰ°í ¿Ï¼ºÇذ¡±â¸¦ ´õ ¿øÇß´Ù.

ÀÌ ½Ã±â¿¡ Ä­Æ®´Â ´ºÅÏ ¹°¸®ÇÐÀÇ °úÇÐÀû ³»¿ë°ú öÇÐÀû ÇÔÃàÀ» ¶È°°ÀÌ Áß¿äÇÏ°Ô »ý°¢Çß´Ù. Ä­Æ®´Â ´ºÅÏÀÇ »çÀ¯¹æ¹ý°ú ´ç½Ã º¼ÇÁ¿Í ¾Ë·º»ê´õ ÄÚÆ²¸®ÇÁ ¹Ù¿ò°¡¸£ÅÙ¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ü°èÈ­µÇ°í ´ëÁßÈ­µÇ¾î µ¶ÀÏ´ëÇп¡ ³Î¸® ÆÛÁ® ÀÖ´ø ÄÚÆ²¸®ÇÁ ºôÇ︧ ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀ» ¼­·Î ´ë¸³ÀûÀÎ °ÍÀ¸·Î º¸¾Ò´Ù. ´ºÅÏÀ» ÁöÁöÇÏ°í ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷¸¦ ºñÆÇÇßÁö¸¸, 1750³â´ë¿¡´Â ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÇ ÀüÁ¦µé¿¡ °üÇØ ³ë°ñÀûÀ¸·Î µµÀüÇÏÁö´Â ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù. ±×·¯³ª 1760³â´ë¿¡ µé¾î¼­´Â ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ÁÖÀÇ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ºñÆÇÀÇ °­µµ¸¦ Á¡Á¡ ³ô¿©°¬´Ù. ¾î¶² Á¦ÀÚÀÇ Áõ¾ð¿¡ µû¸£¸é ´ç½Ã Ä­Æ®´Â ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷¡¤º¼ÇÁ¡¤¹Ù¿ò°¡¸£ÅÙÀ» °ø°ÝÇϸ鼭, ÀÚ½ÅÀ» ´ºÅÏÀÇ ÃßÁ¾ÀÚ·Î ¼±¾ðÇß°í, Àå ÀÚÅ© ·ç¼ÒÀÇ µµ´ööÇп¡ Å« Âù»ç¸¦ Ç¥Çß´Ù°í ÇÑ´Ù. ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ öÇп¡ ´ëÇÑ Ä­Æ®ÀÇ ºñÆÇÀº Å©°Ô µÎ ¹æÇâ¿¡¼­ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁø´Ù. ¿ì¼± öÇÐÀº ¼öÇÐÀ» ¸ðµ¨·Î ÇÏ¿© ÀÚ¸íÇÑ ÀüÁ¦µé¿¡ ±Ù°ÅÇØ¼­ Áõ¸íµÈ Áø¸®ÀÇ Ã¼°è¸¦ ±¸¼ºÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ» ¸ñÇ¥·Î »ï¾Æ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ÁÖÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ ¹æ¹ýÀû ÁÖÀåÀ» °ø°ÝÇß´Ù. ±×¸®°í ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ÁÖÀÇÀÚÀÇ ÇÙ½ÉÀûÀÎ À̷еéÀ» ºñÆÇÇß´Ù. ¸ð¼ø°ú Àΰú¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ³í¸®ÁÖÀÇÀû ÀÔÀå, Á¸Àç·ÐÀû ½ÅÀÇ Áõ¸í, °ø°£°³³ä µîÀÌ ÁÖ¿äÇÑ ºñÆÇÀÇ ÀïÁ¡À̾ú´Ù. ¸¶Ä§³» 1770³â Ä­Æ®´Â 15³â°£ÀÇ ¹«±Þ ´ëÇа­»ç »ýȰÀ» ¸¶°¨Çϰí Äê´ÏÈ÷½ºº£¸£Å©´ëÇб³¿¡¼­ ³í¸®ÇС¤ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐ ±³¼ö·Î ÀÓ¸íµÇ¾ú´Ù. À̶§ºÎÅÍ Á×±â ¸î ³â Àü±îÁö ±×´Â ´Ù¾çÇÑ ¹®Á¦¿¡ ´ëÇØ¼­ ³î¶ö ¸¸Å­ µ¶Ã¢ÀûÀÎ ÀúÀÛµéÀ» ¿¬´Þ¾Æ ¹ßÇ¥ÇÑ´Ù. ÀÌ¹Ì ºñÆÇöÇÐÀÇ Áß¿äÇÑ ¿ä¼ÒµéÀ» ¸¹ÀÌ Æ÷ÇÔÇϰí ÀÖ´ø 1770³âÀÇ ±³¼öÃëÀÓ³í¹® ÀÌÈÄ 11³â µ¿¾È ¾Æ¹« ±Ûµµ ¹ßÇ¥ÇÏÁö ¾Ê°í ¿¬±¸¿¡ Àü³äÇÑ ³¡¿¡ 1781³â ¡´¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ Kritik der reinen Vernunft¡µÀÌ ³ª¿À´Âµ¥, À̶§ºÎÅÍ ºñÆÇöÇÐ ½Ã±â°¡ ½ÃÀ۵ȴÙ.

ºñÆÇöÇÐ ½Ã±â

1781³â ¡´¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ¡µÀÌ ³ª¿Â ÀÌÈÄ 9³â µ¿¾È À§´ëÇÏ°í µ¶Ã¢ÀûÀÎ Àú¼úµéÀÌ °è¼Ó ³ª¿ÈÀ¸·Î½á ´Ü±â°£ µ¿¾È öÇÐ »ç»ó¿¡¼­ÀÇ Çõ¸íÀÌ ÀϾ°í ÀÌÈÄ Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ ³ª¾Æ°¥ ¹æÇâÀÌ Á¤¸³µÈ´Ù. ¡´¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ¡µÀº Ä­Æ®°¡ 10³â µ¿¾È »ý°¢ÇÏ°í ¸í»óÇÑ °á°úÀÌ´Ù. ±×·³¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸Çϰí Ä­Æ®´Â ¿©·¯ ¹ø ¿¬±âÇϸ鼭 ÁÖÀúÇÑ ³¡¿¡ ÃÊÆÇÀ» ¹ß°£Çß´Ù. ÀÚ±â ÀÌ·ÐÀÌ ¿Ç´Ù´Â °ÍÀ» È®½ÅÇßÁö¸¸, ÇØ¸íÀ» Á¦´ë·Î Çß´Ù°í È®½ÅÇÏÁö ¸øÇ߱⠶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù. ±×ÀÇ °ÆÁ¤Àº ÀûÁßÇß´Ù. ±×´Â ÀÌ Ã¥¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÇØ¼®ÀÚµéÀÇ ºñÆÇÀÌ ¸¹Àº ¿ÀÇØ¸¦ ¹üÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù°í ºÒÆòÇß´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ Àڽſ¡ ´ëÇÑ À߸øµÈ ÇØ¼®µéÀ» ¹Ù·Î Àâ±â À§ÇØ ¡´ÇÐÀ¸·Î ¼º¸³ÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â ¸ðµç ¹Ì·¡ÀÇ ÇüÀÌ»óÇп¡ ´ëÇÑ ÀÔ¹® Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können¡µ(1783)À» ½è°í, 1789³â¿¡´Â ÃÊÆÇÀ» °³Á¤ÇÏ¿© ÀçÆÇÀ» ¹ß°£Çß´Ù. ÀÌ µÎ ÆÇÀÇ Àå´ÜÁ¡¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ³íÀïÀº ¾ÆÁ÷µµ °è¼ÓµÇ°í ÀÖ´Ù. °ü³ä·ÐÀûÀÎ ÇØ¼®À» ¼±È£ÇÏ´Â µ¶ÀÚµéÀº º¸Åë ÃÊÆÇÀ» ´õ ÁÁ¾ÆÇϰí, ¹Ý¸é¿¡ ½ÇÀç·ÐÀûÀÎ °ßÇØ¸¦ °¡Áø »ç¶÷µéÀº ÀçÆÇÀ» ¼±È£ÇÑ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª Àаí ÀÌÇØÇÏ±â ¾î·Æ±â´Â ¸ðµÎ ¸¶Âù°¡ÁöÀÌ´Ù. ÀÌ Ã¥ÀÌ ³­ÇØÇÑ ÀÌÀ¯´Â Ä­Æ®°¡ °íµµÀÇ Àü¹®Àû ±â¹ý°ú ¾ö¹Ð¼ºÀ» Ãß±¸ÇÏ´ø º¼ÇÁ³ª ¹Ù¿ò°¡¸£ÅÙÀÇ ÀúÀÛÀ» öÇÐ Àú¼úÀÇ ¸ð¹üÀ¸·Î »ï°í ½è±â ¶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù.

¡´¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ¡µÀº ÇüÀÌ»óÇп¡ ´ëÇÑ Àú¼úÀÌ´Ù. Ä­Æ®´Â ¿©±â¼­ ÀÚ±â ÀÌÀüÀÇ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÌ À߸øµÈ °ÍÀÓÀ» º¸¿©Áָ鼭 »õ·Î¿î ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÇ ±âÃʸ¦ ´Û°íÀÚ Çß´Ù. ±×ÀÇ ÁÖµÈ °ø°Ý´ë»óÀº ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ÁÖÀÇ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀ̾ú´Ù. ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ÁÖÀÇ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀº ½Å, Àΰ£ÀÇ ÀÚÀ¯, ¿µÈ¥ºÒ¸ê µî º»¼º»ó °æÇèÀÇ ´ë»óÀÌ µÉ ¼ö ¾ø´Â °Íµé¿¡ ´ëÇØ¼­µµ Àΰ£ Á¤½ÅÀÌ ¼ø¼ö»çÀ¯¸¦ ÅëÇØ ÂüµÈ ÀνĿ¡ µµ´ÞÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù´Â Á¡À» ÀüÁ¦Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù°í ºñÆÇÇß´Ù. Àΰ£ Á¤½ÅÀº °áÄÚ ±×·± ´É·ÂÀ» °®°í ÀÖÁö ¾Ê±â ¶§¹®¿¡ ¶óÀÌÇÁ´ÏÃ÷ÁÖÀÇ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀº ´Ù ¼ÓÀÓ¼ö¶ó´Â °ÍÀÌ´Ù. Ä­Æ®¿¡ µû¸£¸é ÁøÁ¤ÇÑ ÇÐÀ¸·Î¼­ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÌ ´ç¸éÇÑ ¹®Á¦´Â ¾î¶»°Ô ÇÐÀÇ ¿ø¸®µéÀÌ ÇÑÆíÀ¸·Î´Â ÇÊ¿¬ÀûÀÌ°í º¸ÆíÀûÀ̸鼭µµ(À̰ÍÀº ¸ðµç ÇÐÀû ÀνÄÀÇ Á¶°ÇÀÓ) ´Ù¸¥ ÇÑÆíÀ¸·Î´Â ½ÇÀç¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÀνÄÀ» Æ÷ÇÔÇØ ޱ¸ÀÚ¿¡°Ô ±×°¡ ÀÌ¹Ì ¾Ë°í ÀÖ´Â °Í ¼Ó¿¡ ºÐ¼®ÀûÀ¸·Î Æ÷ÇԵǾî ÀÖ´Â °Í, Áï ±× ÀÇ¹Ì ¼Ó¿¡ ÇÔÃàµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Â °Í ÀÌ»óÀ» ¾Ë ¼ö ÀÖ°Ô Çϴ°¡¸¦ ¼³¸íÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ÀÌ µÎ Á¶°ÇÀ» ¸¸Á·½ÃŰ·Á¸é ÀνÄÀÌ ¼±ÇèÀûÀ̸鼭 µ¿½Ã¿¡ Á¾ÇÕÀûÀÎ ÆÇ´Ü¿¡ ÀÇÁ¸ÇØ¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â °ÍÀÌ Ä­Æ®ÀÇ ÁÖÀåÀÌ´Ù. ¿Ö³ÄÇÏ¸é ¿ì¿¬ÀûÀÎ °æÇèµé·ÎºÎÅÍ ºÐ¸®µÇ¾î ¼±ÇèÀûÀÏ ¶§¿¡¸¸ ÇÊ¿¬ÀûÀÏ ¼ö ÀÖ°í, ±×·¯¸é¼­ µ¿½Ã¿¡ Á־ ºÐ¼®ÀûÀ¸·Î Æ÷ÇÔµÇÁö ¾ÊÀº °ÍÀ» ¼ú¾î°¡ Æ÷ÇÔÇϰí ÀÖÀ¸¸é¼­ Á¾ÇÕÀûÀ̾î¾ß Çϱ⠶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù. ¿¹¸¦ µé¾î '¸ðµç ¹°Ã¼´Â ¿¬ÀåÀûÀÌ´Ù'¶ó´Â ¸íÁ¦´Â Á¾ÇÕÀûÀÌÁö ¾Ê°í ºÐ¼®ÀûÀÌ´Ù. ¿Ö³ÄÇÏ¸é ¿¬Àå°³³äÀÌ ¹°Ã¼ °³³ä¿¡ ÀÌ¹Ì Æ÷ÇԵǾî Àֱ⠶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù. ¹Ý¸é¿¡ '¸ðµç ¹°Ã¼´Â ¹«°Ô¸¦ °¡Áø´Ù'¶ó´Â ¸íÁ¦´Â Á¾ÇÕÀûÀÌ´Ù. ¿Ö³ÄÇÏ¸é ¹«°Ô´Â ¹°Ã¼ °³³ä¿¡ µ¡ºÙ¿©¼­ ¹°Ã¼µéÀÌ ¼­·Î °ü°èµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù´Â °³³äÀ» ÀüÁ¦Çϱ⠶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ Ä­Æ®´Â ÀÌ ¹®Á¦¸¦ "¼±ÇèÀû Á¾ÇÕÆÇ´ÜÀÌ ¾î¶»°Ô(Áï ¾î¶² Á¶°Ç ¾Æ·¡¿¡¼­) °¡´ÉÇѰ¡?"¶ó´Â ¹°À½À¸·Î Á¤½ÄÈ­Çß°í, ÀÌ ¹®Á¦¸¦ ¹àÈ÷´Â °ÍÀÌ ¡´¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ¡µÀÇ ±Ùº» ¹®Á¦°¡ µÈ´Ù.

Ä­Æ®¿¡ µû¸£¸é ÀÌ ¹®Á¦´Â ¼öÇС¤¹°¸®ÇС¤ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÇ ¼¼ ¿µ¿ª¿¡¼­ Á¦±âµÈ´Ù. ±×¸®°í ¡´¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ¡µÀÇ 1ºÎ 'ÃÊ¿ùÀû ¿ø¸®·Ð'ÀÇ ¼¼ ºÎºÐÀÌ °¢°¢ ÇÑ ¿µ¿ª¾¿ ´Ù·é´Ù. 'ÃÊ¿ùÀû °¨¼º·Ð'¿¡¼­ Ä­Æ®´Â ¼öÇÐÀÌ ½Ã°£°ú °ø°£À» ´Ù·é´Ù´Â °ÍÀ» ³íÁõÇß°í, ¶Ç ½Ã°£°ú °ø°£Àº µÑ ´Ù Àΰ£ °¨¼ºÀÇ ¼±ÇèÀû Çü½ÄÀ¸·Î¼­ °¨°üÀ» ÅëÇØ Æ÷ÂøµÇ´Â °ÍÀÇ Á¶°ÇÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. °¡Àå ¾î·Á¿ì¸é¼­ °¡Àå ÇÙ½ÉÀûÀÎ ºÎºÐÀÎ 'ÃÊ¿ùÀû ºÐ¼®·Ð'¿¡¼­´Â ¹°¸®ÇÐÀÌ ¼±ÇèÀûÀ̸鼭 Á¾ÇÕÀûÀε¥ ±× ÀÌÀ¯´Â ¹°¸®ÇÐÀÌ °æÇèÀ» Áú¼­Áö¿ï ¶§ Ưº°ÇÑ Á¾·ùÀÇ °³³äÀ» »ç¿ëÇϱ⠶§¹®À̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. Ä­Æ®°¡ '¹üÁÖ'¶ó°í ºÒ·¶´ø ÀÌ °³³äµéÀº °æÇèÀ» ÅëÇØ »ý±ä °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï°í ¿ÀÈ÷·Á °æÇèÀ» ÇØ¼®ÇÏ´Â ÀüÁ¦°¡ µÇ±â ¶§¹®¿¡ ¼±ÇèÀûÀ̸ç, °æÇèÀûÀÌÁö ¾Ê´Ù´Â Á¡¿¡¼­ ¼ø¼öÇÑ °ÍÀÌ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ¹üÁÖ´Â ±× ±â¿ø ¸é¿¡¼­¸¸ °æÇèÀû °³³ä°ú ´Ù¸¥ °ÍÀº ¾Æ´Ï´Ù. ÀνĿ¡¼­ÀÇ ¿ªÇÒÀÌ ÀüÇô ´Ù¸£´Ù. °æÇèÀû °³³äÀº ƯÁ¤ÇÑ °æÇèµéÀ» ¼­·Î °ü·ÃÁö¾î¼­ ±¸Ã¼ÀûÀ¸·Î Áú¼­Áö¿öÁø °æÇèÀ» »êÃâÇÏ´Â ¹Ý¸é, ¹üÁÖ´Â ÀÌ ±¸Ã¼ÀûÀÎ Áú¼­Áö¿òÀÌ µû¶ó¾ß ÇÒ ÀÏ¹Ý Çü½ÄÀ» Á¦½ÃÇÏ´Â ±â´ÉÀ» °¡Áø´Ù. ´Þ¸® ¸»ÇÏ¸é ¹üÁÖ´Â ÀνÄÀÇ Æ²¿¡ ÇØ´çÇÑ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ºñ·Ï ¹üÁÖ°¡ °´°üÀû ÀνÄÀ» À§ÇØ ¹Ýµå½Ã ÇÊ¿äÇÏÁö¸¸, ¹üÁÖ°¡ ÁÙ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â ÀνÄÀº ´ÜÁö °¡´ÉÇÑ °æÇèÀÇ ´ë»ó¿¡ ´ëÇÑ °ÍÀÌ´Ù. ¹üÁÖ´Â °¨°¢À» ÅëÇØ ½Ã°ø Áß¿¡ ÁÖ¾îÁö´Â °ÍÀ» Áú¼­Áö¿ï ¶§¸¸ Ÿ´çÇÏ°í ½ÇÁúÀûÀÎ ÀνÄÀ» ÁÙ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù. 'ÃÊ¿ùÀû º¯Áõ·Ð'¿¡¼­´Â ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÇ ¼±ÇèÀû Á¾ÇÕÆÇ´ÜµéÀ» °ËÅäÇÑ´Ù. Ä­Æ®¿¡ µû¸£¸é ¿©±â¼­´Â »óȲÀÌ ¼öÇÐÀ̳ª ¹°¸®Çаú´Â ¹Ý´ëÀÌ´Ù. ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀº °¨°¢°æÇèÀ» ÃÊ¿ùÇÏ¿© Àý´ëÀû ¹«Á¦¾àÀÚ¸¦ Ãß±¸Çϱ⠶§¹®¿¡ °¨°¢°æÇèÀ¸·ÎºÎÅÍ ½º½º·Î¸¦ Â÷´ÜÇØ¹ö¸°´Ù. À̶§¹®¿¡ ÁøÁ¤ÇÑ ¼±ÇèÀû Á¾ÇÕÆÇ´ÜÀ» È®º¸ÇÒ ¼ö ¾ø°Ô µÈ´Ù. ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ÁÖÀåÀ» Á¤´çÈ­Çϱâ À§ÇØ Ä­Æ®´Â ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÌ ¿µÈ¥¡¤¼¼°è¡¤½Å°ú °°Àº ¹«Á¦¾àÀÚ °³³äÀ» ¾î¶»°Ô »ç¿ëÇϰí ÀÖ´ÂÁö¸¦ ºÐ¼®ÇÏ¿©, ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÇ ½Ãµµ°¡ ÀÌÀ²¹è¹Ý¿¡ ºüÁö°í ½ÇÆÐÇÒ ¼ö¹Û¿¡ ¾ø´Â ¿î¸íÀÓÀ» ¹àÈ÷·Á Çß´Ù.

Ä­Æ®´Â ¡´¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ¡µÀ» ÅëÇØ öÇп¡¼­ ÄÚÆä¸£´ÏÄí½ºÀû Çõ¸íÀ» ¼ºÃëÇß´Ù°í ÀÚ¶û½º·´°Ô ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ±Ù´ë õ¹®ÇÐÀ» ±âÃÊÇÑ ÄÚÆä¸£´ÏÄí½º°¡ °ÑÀ¸·Î º¸±â¿¡ º°ÀÌ ¿òÁ÷ÀÌ´Â °Íó·³ º¸ÀÌ´Â Çö»óÀ» »ç½ÇÀº °üÂûÀÚ°¡ ¿òÁ÷Àδٴ »ç½ÇÀ» ÅëÇØ ¼³¸íÇß´ø °Í°ú ¸¶Âù°¡Áö·Î, Ä­Æ®´Â ¸¶À½ÀÇ ¼±ÇèÀûÀÎ ¿ø¸®°¡ ´ë»ó¿¡ Àû¿ëµÊÀ» ¼³¸íÇÔÀ¸·Î½á ¸¶À½ÀÌ ´ë»ó¿¡ µû¸£´Â °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ´ë»óÀÌ ¸¶À½¿¡ µû¸¥´Ù´Â °ÍÀ» º¸¿©ÁÖ¾ú±â ¶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù.

±×·¯³ª Ä­Æ®°¡ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀ» ºñÆÇÇÑ °ÍÀº °áÄÚ Á¾±³¿Í µµ´öÀ» °ÅºÎÇϱâ À§ÇÑ °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï´Ù. ¿ÀÈ÷·Á ±×´Â ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀ» 'È®½ÇÇÑ ÇÐÀÇ ±æ À§¿¡' ¿Ã·Á³õÀ¸·Á Çß°í À̰ÍÀÌ ºñÆÇöÇÐÀÇ ÁøÁ¤ÇÑ Àǵµ¿´´Ù. ÀÌ·± Àǵµ ¶§¹®¿¡ Ä­Æ®´Â ¾Õ¼­ ¹ß°£ÇÑ ¡´µµ´öÇüÀÌ»óÇбâÃÊ Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten¡µ(1785)¸¦ ü°èÀûÀ¸·Î È®´ëÇÏ¿© 1788³â ¡´½ÇõÀ̼ººñÆÇ Kritik der praktischen Vernunft¡µÀ» ¹ß°£ÇÔÀ¸·Î½á ÁøÁ¤ÇÑ µµ´öÀÇ Ã¼°è¸¦ Á¦½ÃÇÏ·Á Çß´Ù. ¡´½ÇõÀ̼ººñÆÇ¡µ¿¡¼­ È®¸³ÇÑ ¿ø¸®¸¦ ±¸Ã¼ÀûÀÎ Â÷¿ø¿¡ Àû¿ëÇÏ·Á´Â ³ë·ÂÀ» °è¼ÓÇÏ¿©, 1797³â¿¡ ¹ß°£µÈ »çȸöÇÐÀú¼úÀÎ ¡´µµ´öÇüÀÌ»óÇÐ Die Metaphysik der Sitten¡µ¿¡¼­´Â ´öÀÇ ¹®Á¦¸¦ °ËÅäÇÏ°í ¹ý°ú Á¤Ä¡ÀÇ ±âÃʸ¦ Á¦½ÃÇÑ´Ù. ºñÆÇöÇÐÀ» ¸¶°¨ÇÏ´Â Á¦3ºñÆÇ¼­ÀÎ ¡´ÆÇ´Ü·ÂºñÆÇ Kritik der Urteilskraft¡µ(1790)¿¡¼­´Â Å©°Ô 2°¡Áö ¹®Á¦¸¦ ´Ù·é´Ù. ù°, ¹ÌÀÇ ¹®Á¦¸¦ ´Ù·ëÀ¸·Î½á ÃÖÃÊÀÇ Ã¼°èÀûÀÎ ¹ÌÇÐÀ» Á¦½ÃÇϰí ÀÖÀ¸¸ç, µÑ°, ÀÚ¿¬¿¡¼­ ¸ñÀû·ÐÀÇ ¹®Á¦¸¦ ½É°¢ÇÏ°Ô ´Ù·é´Ù.

¸»³â

ºñÆÇöÇÐÀº °ð µ¶ÀϾ ¾²´Â ¸ðµç Áß¿äÇÑ ´ëÇп¡¼­ °­ÀǵǾú°í ¸¹Àº ÀþÀºÀ̵éÀÌ Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ ¼ºÁö°¡ µÈ Äê´ÏÈ÷½ºº£¸£Å©¿¡ ¸ô·Áµé¾ú´Ù. ±×µéÀº ¸¶Ä¡ ½ÅŹÀ» ±¸ÇϵíÀÌ Ä­Æ®¿¡°Ô¼­ ¿Â°® Á¾·ùÀÇ ¹®Á¦¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ´äÀ» ±¸ÇÏ·Á Çß´Ù. ÀÌ·± Á¸°æÀ» ¹ÞÀ¸¸é¼­µµ Ä­Æ®´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ±ÔÄ¢ÀûÀÎ ½À°üÀ» ¾î±ä ÀûÀÌ ¾øÀ¸¸ç ¾ö°ÝÇÑ »ýȰÀ» À¯ÁöÇß´Ù. 5ÇÇÆ®°¡ ä µÇÁö ¾Ê´Â Ű¿¡ ±âÇüÀûÀÎ °¡½¿À» °¡Áø Ä­Æ®´Â ¸öÀÌ ¾àÇ߱⠶§¹®¿¡ Æò»ý ¾ö°ÝÇÑ ½Ä»ýȰÀ» Çß´Ù. Ä­Æ® ¶§¹®¿¡ 'öÇÐÀÚÀÇ »êÃ¥·Î'¶ó À̸§ºÙ¿©Áø °Å¸®¸¦ ±ÔÄ¢ÀûÀ¸·Î »êÃ¥Ç߱⠶§¹®¿¡, »ç¶÷µéÀÌ ±×ÀÇ »êÃ¥À» ±âÁØÀ¸·Î ½Ã°£À» ¸ÂÃß¾ú´Ù. ±×´Â ³ë·ÉÀ¸·Î »êÃ¥ÀÌ Èûµé¾îÁú ¶§±îÁö ·ç¼ÒÀÇ ¡´¿¡¹Ð Émile¡µÀ» Àд µ¥ ¿­ÁßÇÏ´À¶ó ¸çÄ¥ Áý¿¡¼­ ³ª¿ÀÁö ¾ÊÀº ¶§¸¦ Á¦¿ÜÇϰí´Â 1¹øµµ ±ÔÄ¢Àû »êÃ¥À» ¾î±ä ÀûÀÌ ¾ø¾ú´Ù.

¡´ÆÇ´Ü·ÂºñÆÇ¡µÀÌ ÃâÆÇµÊÀ¸·Î½á Ä­Æ®ÀÇ Áß¿äÇÑ Ã¶ÇÐ ÀúÀÛÀº ¿Ï¼ºµÈ ¼ÀÀÌ´Ù. 1790³âºÎÅÍ ±×´Â °Ç°­ÀÌ ½É°¢ÇÒ Á¤µµ·Î ³ªºüÁö±â ½ÃÀÛÇß´Ù. ¿©ÀüÈ÷ ±×´Â ¸¹Àº Àú¼ú°èȹÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ¾úÁö¸¸, ÇÏ·ç 2~3½Ã°£ ÀÌ»ó Àú¼úȰµ¿À» ÇÏ´Â °ÍÀº ºÒ°¡´ÉÇß´Ù. ±×¶§ ±×°¡ ¿Ï¼ºÇÑ ÀúÀÛµéÀº ÇÑÆíÀ¸·Î´Â Àü¿¡´Â ÀÚ¼¼È÷ ´Ù·é ÀûÀÌ ¾ø´Â ÁÖÁ¦µéÀ» Á¤±³ÇÏ°Ô ´Ù·ç´Â °ÍÀ̾ú°í, ´Ù¸¥ ÇÑÆíÀ¸·Î´Â ºñÆÇ°ú ¸íÈ®ÇÑ ¿ÀÇØµé¿¡ ´ë´äÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. 1793³â ¡´À̼ºÀÇ ÇÑ°è ³»¿¡¼­ÀÇ Á¾±³ Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft¡µ¸¦ Ãâ°£Çϸ鼭 Ä­Æ®´Â ÇÁ·ÎÀ̼¾ ´ç±¹°ú Á¾±³ÀÇ ¹ÏÀ½À» Ç¥ÇöÇÒ ±Ç¸®¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ³íÀï¿¡ ÈÖ¸»·Áµé¾ú´Ù. ÀÌ Ã¥¿¡¼­ Á¾±³¿¡ Á¢±ÙÇØ°¡´Â Áö³ªÄ¡°Ô ÇÕ¸®ÁÖÀÇÀûÀΠŵµ°¡ Á¤ÅëÁ¾±³¿¡ ¹®Á¦°¡ µÇ¾ú´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ Ä­Æ®´Â ¼º¼­¿Í ±×¸®½ºµµ±³ÀÇ Áß¿äÇÑ ¸¹Àº ±Ùº» ±³¸®¸¦ ¿Ö°îÇÑ Ã¥ÀÓÀ» Áö°í, Á¾±³Àû ÁÖÁ¦¿¡ ´ëÇÑ °­Àdzª Àú¼úȰµ¿À» ±ÝÁö´çÇß´Ù. Ä­Æ®´Â ÀÏ´Ü ¼ö±àÇßÁö¸¸ ÀÌ ±ÝÁö¸¦ ¿Õ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ °³ÀÎÀû ¾à¼ÓÀ¸·Î ¿©°å°í, 1797³â ¿ÕÀÌ Á×ÀÚ ½º½º·Î ÀÌ ±ÝÁö¿¡¼­ Ç®¸° °ÍÀ¸·Î »ý°¢Çß´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ 1798³â¿¡´Â ±×ÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· ÁÖ¿äÀú¼­ÀÎ ¡´ÇкεéÀÇ ³íÀï Der Streit der Fakultäten¡µ¿¡¼­ ±ÝÁöµÈ ÁÖÁ¦¸¦ ´Ù½Ã ´Ù·ç¾ú´Ù.

±×°¡ Á×À» ¶§±îÁö ¿­½ÉÈ÷ ¾´ ¹æ´ëÇÑ À¯°í´Â º£¸¦¸°ÆÇ ÀüÁýÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· 2±Ç¿¡ ¸ð¾ÆÁ® Àִµ¥, ³»¿ëÀº ÁÖ·Î ºñÆÇöÇÐÀ» ´õ¿í ¹ßÀü½ÃŰ·Á´ø °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ±× À¯°íµéÀº ¹Ì¿Ï¼º ÀúÀÛÀ̶ó±âº¸´Ù´Â ¾î¶² ÀúÀÛÀ» ÁغñÇϱâ À§ÇÑ ´ÜÆíÀûÀÎ ¸Þ¸ðµéÀÌ´Ù. ±×°¡ ¾²·Á ÇÑ Ã¥ÀÇ Á¦¸ñÀº ¡´ÀÚ¿¬°úÇÐÀÇ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀû ±Ù°Å·ÎºÎÅÍ ¹°¸®ÇÐÀ¸·ÎÀÇ ÀÌÇà Übergang von den metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft zur Physik¡µÀ̾ú´Ù. ÀÌ Ã¥Àº ¡´ÀÚ¿¬ °úÇÐÀÇ ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀû ±Ù°Å Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft¡µ(1786)¿¡¼­ Á¦½ÃÇÑ ÁÖÀåÀ» ´õ¿í ¹ßÀü½ÃÄÑ, ÀÚ¿¬°úÇÐÀÇ ÀϹÝÀû üÁ¦¸¸ÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó »ó´çÈ÷ ÀÚ¼¼ÇÑ ºÎºÐ±îÁöµµ ¼±ÇèÀûÀ¸·Î ±¸¼ºÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖÀ½À» º¸ÀÌ·Á°í Çß´ø °Í °°´Ù. ³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â À¯°íµé·Î ÆÇ´ÜÇØº¼ ¶§, ºñ·Ï À¯°íÀÇ ¾çÀÌ ¸¹±â´Â ÇÏÁö¸¸, ±× À¯°í°¡ ¿Ï¼ºµÇ¾ú´õ¶óµµ ºñÆÇöÇÐÀÇ Ã¼°è¿Í ¸í¼º¿¡ Áß¿äÇÑ ³»¿ëÀÌ µ¡ºÙ¿©Áú ¼ö ÀÖ¾úÀ»Áö´Â Àǹ®ÀÌ´Ù. Á¡Á¡ ¼è¾àÇØÁö¸é¼­ °íÅ뽺·± ³ª³¯À» º¸³»´Ù°¡ 1804³â 2¿ù 12ÀÏ Ä­Æ®´Â Äê´ÏÈ÷½ººÎ¸£Å©¿¡¼­ Á×¾ú´Ù. ±×ÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· ¸»Àº "ÀÌÁ¦ µÇ¾ú´Ù"´Â °ÍÀ̾ú´Ù. ±×ÀÇ ¹¦ºñ¿¡´Â Á¦2ºñÆÇÀÇ °á·Ð¿¡¼­ ¼±¾ðÇÑ ´ÙÀ½ ¹®±¸°¡ »õ°ÜÁ® ÀÖ´Ù. "´õ¿í´õ ÀÚÁÖ, ±×¸®°í ´õ¿í´õ °õ°õÀÌ »ý°¢Çغ¼¼ö·Ï, ³» À§¿¡ º°ÀÌ ¹Ý¦ÀÌ´Â Çϴðú ³» ¼ÓÀÇ µµ´ö¹ýÄ¢Àº ´õ¿í´õ »õ·Ó°í Å« Á¸°æ°ú °æ¿Ü½ÉÀ¸·Î ¸¶À½À» °¡µæ ä¿öÁØ´Ù."

O. A. Bird ±Û

¡¡

4 Major Works

MAJOR WORKS

PRE-CRITICAL WRITINGS: Gedanken von der wahren Schätzung der lebendigen Kräfte und Beurteilung der Beweise derer sich Herr von Leibniz und anderer Mechaniker in dieser Streitsache bedient haben (1746); Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels (1755; Kant's Cosmogony . . . , 1900 and 1968; Universal Natural History and Theories of the Heavens, 1969); Principiorum Primorum Cognitionis Metaphysicae Nova Dilucidatio (1755; Eng. trans. by F.E. England in Kant's Conception of God, 1929); Metaphysicae cum geometria iunctae usus in philosophia naturali, cuius specimen I. continet Monadologiam physicam (1756); Versuch einiger Betrachtungen über den Optimismus (1759); Die falsche Spitzfindigkeit der vier syllogistischen Figurerewiesen (1762; trans. in Kant's Introduction to Logic and His Essay on the Mistaken Subtilty of the Four Figures, 1963); Der einzige mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseyns Gottes (1763; Enquiry into the Proofs for the Existence of God, 1836); Versuch, den Begriff der negativen Grössen in die Weltweisheit einzuführen (1763; An Attempt to Introduce the Conception of Negative Quantities into Philosophy, 1911); Untersuchung über die Deutlichkeit der Grundsätze der natürlichen Theologie und der Moral (1764); Beobachtungen über das Gefühl des Schönen und Erhabenen (1764, 1766, 1771; Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime, 1960); Träume eines Geistersehers erläutert durch Träume der Metaphysik (1766; Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics, 1900; Dreams of a Spirit Seer, and Other Related Writings, 1969); De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis: Dissertatio (1770; Kant's Inaugural Dissertation and Early Writings on Space, 1929); Von den Verschiedenen Racen der Menschen (1775).

CRITICAL AND POST-CRITICAL WRITINGS: Critik der reinen Vernunft (1781; rev. ed., Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 1787; Critique of Pure Reason, 1929, 1950); Prolegomena zur einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können (1783; Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, 1951); Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (1785; The Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Ethics, 1938; The Moral Law; or, Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, 1948; Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, 1969); Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft (1786; Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, 1970); Critik der practischen Vernunft (1788; Critique of Practical Reason, 1949); Critik der Urteilskraft (1790, 2nd ed. 1793; Kant's Kritik of Judgment, 1892, reprinted as Kant's Critique . . ., 1914; new version, Critique . . ., vol. 1, Kant's Critique of Aesthetic Judgment and vol. 2, Critique of Teleological Judgment, 1911-28, republished 1952); Über eine Entdeckung, nach der alle neu Critik der reinen Vernunft durch eine ältere entbehrlich gemacht werden soll (1790; 2nd ed., 1791); Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft (1793; 2nd ed., 4 pt., 1794; Religion Within the Boundary of Pure Reason, 1838; Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, 2nd ed., 1960); Zum ewigen Frieden (1795; 2nd ed., 1796; Project for a Perpetual Peace, 1796, many later editions called Perpetual Peace; 1915 ed. reprinted 1972); Die Metaphysik der Sitten (1797; 2nd ed., 1798-1803; The Metaphysic of Morals, 2 vol., 1799 and 1965; The Metaphysic of Ethics, 1836), comprising Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre (The Philosophy of Law, 1887) and Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Tugendlehre (The Doctrine of Virtue, 1964); Der Streit der Facultäten (1798); Von der Macht des Gemüths durch den blossen Vorsatz seiner krankhaften Gefühle Meister zu seyn (1798; Kant on the Art of Preventing Diseases, 1806); Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht abgefasst (1798; improved ed., 1800; The Classification of Mental Disorders, 1964); Immanuel Kants Physische Geographie, 3 vol. in 6 pt., 1801-04); I. Kants Logik: Ein Handbuch zu Vorlesungen (1800; Logic, 1819); Immanuel Kant über Pädagogik (1803; Kant on Education, 1899; The Educational Theory of Immanuel Kant, 1904; Education, 1960); Welches sind die wirklichen Fortschritte, die Metaphysik seit Leibnizens und Wolf's Zeiten in Deutschland gemacht hat? (1804).

5 Bibliography

BIBLIOGRAPHY

 

5.1 Kant. Biography:

The main sources for Kant's life are three memoirs published in 1804: LUDWIG ERNEST VON BOROWSKI, Darstellung des Lebens und Charakters Immanuel Kants (reprinted 1968); REINHOLD B. JACHMANN, Immanuel Kant geschildert in Briefen an einen Freund (reprinted 1968); and CHRISTOPH WASIANSKI, Immanuel Kant in seinen letzten Lebensjahren (the basis of THOMAS DE QUINCEY'S "The Last Days of Kant" included in his Works). See also JOHN H.W. STUCKENBERG, The Life of Immanuel Kant (1882); FRIEDRICH PAULSEN, Immanuel Kant: His Life and Doctrine (1902, reissued 1963; originally published in German, 1898); ERNST CASSIRER, Kant's Life and Thought (1981; trans. of 2nd German ed., 1921); and KARL VORLÄNDER, Immanuel Kants Leben, 3rd ed. (1974), and Immanuel Kant: Der Mann und das Werk, 2 vol. (1924, reissued 1977).

 

5.2 Editions:

The standard edition of Kant's works is that of the Berlin Academy (later the DDR Academy), Gesammelte Schriften (1902- ), 29 vol. by 1980, which contains Kant's lectures, correspondence, and literary remains as well as his published writings. There are also modern collected editions by ERNST CASSIRER, 11 vol. (1912-23); and by KARL VORLÄNDER, 10 vol. (1920-29). A convenient edition of the Critique of Pure Reason is that by RAYMOND SCHMIDT, 1926).

 

5.3 Aids to study:

RUDOLF EISLER, Kant-lexicon (1930, reprinted 1971); HEINRICH RATKE, Systematisches Handlexikon zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1929, reprinted 1965).

 

5.4 General works:

The best introduction is STEPHAN KÖRNER, Kant (1955, reissued 1982). See also EDWARD CAIRD, The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant, 2 vol. (1889, reprinted 1969); KUNO FISCHER, Kants Leben und die Grundlagen seiner Lehre (1860); ALOIS RIEHL, Der philosophische Kriticismus . . . , 3rd ed., 3 vol. (1924-26); BRUNO BAUCH, Immanuel Kant, 4th ed. (1933), in German; HENRICH RICKERT, Kant als Philosoph der modernen Kultur (1924); MAX WUNDT, Kant als Metaphysiker (1924); MARTIN HEIDEGGER, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics (1962, reissued 1972; originally published in German, 1929); HERMAN J. DE VLEESCHAUWER, La Déduction transcendentale dans l'oeuvre de Kant, 3 vol. (1934, reissued 1976), and L'Évolution de la pensée kantienne (1939); PANTALEO CARABELLESE, Il problema della filosofia in Kant (1938); GOTTFRIED MARTIN, Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science (1955, reissued 1974; originally published in German, 1951); HEINZ HEIMSOETH, Studien zur Philosophie Immanuel Kants, 2nd ed. (1971); RICHARD KRONER, Kant's Weltanschauung (1956; originally published in German, 1914); FRIEDRICH DELEKAT, Immanuel Kant, 3rd ed. (1969), in German.

 

5.5 Precritical writings:

MARIANO CAMPO, La genesi del criticismo kantiano (1953); GIORGIO TONELLI, Elementi metodologici e metafisici in Kant dal 1745 al 1768 (1969), in German.

 

5.6 The "Critique of Pure Reason":

NORMAN KEMP SMITH, A Commentary to Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason," 2nd ed. rev. (1923, reissued 1979); HERBERT J. PATON, Kant's Metaphysic of Experience, 2 vol. (1936); ALFRED C. EWING, A Short Commentary on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1938, reprinted 1974); THOMAS D. WELDON, Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd ed. (1958); HERMANN COHEN, Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, 4th ed. (1925), and Kommentar zu Immanuel Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 4th ed. (1925); HANS VAIHINGER, Kommentar zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 2nd ed., 2 vol. (1922, reissued 1970); HEINZ HEIMSOETH, Transzendentale Dialektik, 3rd vol. (1966-69). See also GRAHAM BIRD, Kant's Theory of Knowledge (1962, reissued 1973); PETER F. STRAWSON, The Bounds of Sense (1966, reissued 1975).

 

5.7 Ethical writings:

JEFFIRIE G. MURPHY, Kant: The Philosophy of Right (1970); PAUL A. SCHILPP, Kant's Pre-Critical Ethics, 2nd ed. (1960, reprinted 1977); HERBERT J. PATON, The Categorical Imperative (1947, reissued 1971); ORNA NELL, Acting on Principle: An Essay on Kantian Ethics (1975); VIGGO ROSSVAER, Kant's Moral Philosophy: An Interpretation of the Categorical Imperative (1979); LEWIS W. BECK, A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason (1960); A.E. TEALE, Kantian Ethics (1951, reprinted 1975); WILLIAM D. ROSS, Kant's Ethical Theory (1954, reprinted 1978); HERMANN COHEN, Kants Begründung der Ethik, 2nd ed. (1910); MAX SCHELER, Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik, 6th ed. (1980). See also PAUL MENZER'S ed. of Eine Vorlesung Kants über Ethik (1924; Eng. trans., Lectures on Ethics by Immanuel Kant, (1930); MORRIS STOCKHAMMER, Kants Zurechnungsidee und Freitheitsantinomie (1961); HENRICH W. CASSIRER, A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Judgement (1938, reprinted 1970); ALFRED BAEUMLER, Kants Kritik der Urteilskraft (1923).

 

5.8 Particular problems:

(Science): ERICH ADICKES, Kant als Naturforscher, 2 vol. (1924-25); JULES VUILLEMIN, Physique et métaphysique kantiennes (1955). (Ontology): CHRISTOPHER B. GARNETT, The Kantian Philosophy of Space (1939, reprinted 1965); MARTIN HEIDEGGER, Kants These über das Sein (1963), and What Is a Thing? (1968; originally published in German, 1962). (Philosophy of history): YIRMIAHU YOVEL, Kant and the Philosophy of History (1980); KLAUS WEYAND, Kants Beschichtsphilosophie: Ihre Entwicklung und ihr Verhältnis zur Aufklärung (1963). (Political philosophy): SUSAN M. SHELL, The Rights of Reason: A Study of Kant's Philosophy and Politics (1980); GEORGES VLACHOS, La Pensée politique de Kant (1962). (Religion): CLEMENT C.J. WEBB, Kant's Philosophy of Religion (1926, reprinted 1970); JOSEF BOHATEC, Die Religionsphilosophie Kants . . . (1938, reprinted 1966); ALLAN W. WOOD, Kant's Rational Theology (1978). (Comparative studies): JOHANNES B. LOTZ (ed.), Kant und die Scholastik heute (1955); KARL JASPERS, Die grossen Philosophen, 2 vol. (1957-81; abridged Eng. trans., The Great Philosophers, ed. by HANNAH ARENDT, 1966). (Aesthetics): DONALD W. CRAWFORD, Kant's Aesthetic Theory (1974); PAUL GUYER, Kant and the Claims of Taste (1979).

 

5.9 Opus postumum:

ERICH ADICKES, Kants Opus Postumum (1920, reprinted 1978); GERHARD LEHMANN, Kants Nachiasswerk und die Kritik der Urteilskraft (1939).

5.10 Journals:

Many important works of Kantian scholarship have been published in the periodical Kant-studien (quarterly).

 

5.11 Kantianism.

Though the literature on Kant himself comprises innumerable titles, that on Kantianism is relatively scanty. One work that contains the complete history of Kantianism is Freidrich Ueberwegs Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, 13th ed. (1953), vol. 3:606-620 and 4:1-128 for the first period and pp. 410-483 for the second. For the first period, there is an abundant literature. Of particular interest for the present purposes are JOHANN E. ERDMANN, Versuch einer wissenschaftlichen Darstellung der Geschichte der neuern Zeit, 2nd ed., vol. 3 (1923); and G. LEHMANN, "Kant im Spätidealismus und die Anfänge der neukantischen Bewegung," in Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 17:438-456 (1963). For the second period, MARIANO CAMPO has begun the history in his Schizzo storico della esegesi e critica Kantiana (1959); and summaries have been written by LEWIS W. BECK in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 5:468-473 (1967, reissued 1972); and by HERMANN NOACK in his Die Philosophie Westeuropas, pp. 143-196 (1962). See also the Enciclopedia Filosofica, new ed., vol. 3, col. 1225, and vol. 4, col. 953 (1967); WOLFGANG RITZEL, Studien zum Wandel der Dantauffassung (1952); HENRI DUSSORT, L'École de Marbourg (1963); and HEINRICH RICKERT, Die Heidelberger Tradition und Kants Kritizismus (1934).

¡¡

  • Àú¼­
    • ª««ó«Èîïó¢ îï18Ïé : I. kant, ê«éΪ۪«øº¡¤æ», ìµßÌÞä, 1965 - 77
    • ¿µ¿øÇÑ ÆòÈ­¸¦ À§ÇÏ¿© : I. Ä­Æ®, ÀÌÇѱ¸ ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1992
    • Ä­Æ®ÀÇ ¿ª»çöÇÐ : I. Ä­Æ®, ÀÌÇѱ¸ ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1992
    • ½ÇõÀ̼ººñÆÇ(¼¼°è±³¾ç»ç»ó¹é¼± 8) : I. Ä­Æ®, °­´ëÁ¤ ¿ª, ÀϽż­ÀûÃâÆÇ»ç, 1991
    • À̼ºÀÇ ÇѰè¾È¿¡¼­ÀÇ Á¾±³(ÀÌÈ­¹®°í 31) : I. Ä­Æ®, ½Å¿ÁÈñ ¿ª, ÀÌÈ­¿©ÀÚ´ëÇб³ ÃâÆÇºÎ, 1984
    • ¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ : I. Ä­Æ®, ÃÖÀçÈñ ¿ª, ¹Ú¿µ»ç, 1983
    • Ä­Æ®Àλý·Ð : I. Ä­Æ®, »çȸ°úÇבּ¸È¸ ¿ª, ¼­¸í, 1981
    • ºñÆÇöÇм­·Ð : I. Ä­Æ®, ÃÖÀçÈñ ¿ª, ¹Ú¿µ»ç, 1978
    • µµ´öÇüÀÌ»óÇпø·Ð/¿µ±¸ÆòÈ­·Ð(¹Ú¿µ¹®°í 7) : I. Ä­Æ®, À̱ÔÈ£ ¿ª, ¹Ú¿µ»ç, 1974
    • ºñÆÇ·ÂºñÆÇ : I. Ä­Æ®, À̼®À± ¿ª, ¹Ú¿µ»ç, 1974
    • ÇÁ·Î·¹°í¸Þ³ª : I. Ä­Æ®, ¼­µ¿ÀÍ ¿Ü ¿ª, ÈÖ¹®ÃâÆÇ»ç, 1972
  • Àü±â
    • Ä­Æ®ÀÇ ÀÏ»ý : ¾ß¼­¸Õ¡¤ºê³ë½ºÅ° °øÀú, ÀÌ¿µÃ¶ ¿ª, ±Û¹þÁý, 1959
  • ÀÔ¹®¼­
    • Ä­Æ®(»ý¾Ö¿Í »ç»ó 4) : ¿ìº£ ½¶Ã÷, ÃÖÇõ¼ø ¿ª, ÇาÃâÆÇ»ç, 1989
    • Ä­Æ®(PM¹®°í 5) : ·ÎÀú ½ºÅ©·¯Æ°, ¹ÎÂùÈ« ¿ª, ¹®°æÃâÆÇ»ç, 1986
    • ĭƮöÇבּ¸ : ÃÖÀçÈñ, »ïÁö¿ø, 1985
    • ĭƮöÇаú Çö´ë»ç»ó : ÇÏ¿µ¼® ¿Ü, Çü¼³ÃâÆÇ»ç, 1984
    • ÀηùÀÇ ½º½Â Ä­Æ®(¸í¹®½Å¼­ 8) : ÃÖÇö, ¸í¹®»ç, 1983
    • ĭƮöÇлç»óÀÇ ÀÌÇØ : ÇѴܼ®, ¾ç¿µ°¢, 1983
    • Ä­Æ®ÀÇ »ý¾Ö¿Í öÇÐ : ÃÖÀçÈñ, ž繮ȭ»ç, 1981
    • ĭƮöÇÐÀÌÇØÀÇ ±æ(»õ¹ç½Å¼­ 5) : B. O. µÇ¿¡¸µ, ±è¿ëÁ¤ ¿ª, »õ¹ç, 1979
  • Àü¹®¼­
    • Ä­Æ®ºñÆÇöÇÐÀÇ Çü¼º°úÁ¤°ú ü°è : F. Ä«¿ï¹ÙÇÏ, ¹éÁ¾Çö ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1992
    • ĭƮöÇÐÀÇ ºÐ¼®Àû ÀÌÇØ(¹ø¿ªÃѼ­ 139) : C. D. ºê·Îµå, ÇÏ¿µ¼®¡¤À̳²¿ø °ø¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1992
    • Ä­Æ®¿Í ÃÊ¿ùöÇÐ - Àΰ£À̶õ ¹«¾ùÀΰ¡ : ÇÑÀÚ°æ, ¼­±¤»ç, 1992
    • Àνİú Á¸Àç - ¼ø¼öÀ̼ºÀÇ ÀÌÀ²¹è¹Ý°ú ¼±ÇèÀû °ü³ä·Ð : ¹®¼ºÇÐ, ¼­±¤»ç, 1991
    • Ä­Æ®ÀÇ µµ´ööÇÐ : H. J. ÆäÀÌÆ°, ±è¼ºÈ£ ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1988
    • Ä­Æ®ÀÇ ¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇ : T. E. ¿ùÄ¿½¼, ¹éÇмö ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1987
    • ¼ø¼öÀ̼ººñÆÇÀÔ¹® : A. C. À¯À×, ±è»óºÀ ¿ª, ÇѰܷ¹, 1985
    • Ä­Æ®ÀÇ ºñÆÇöÇÐ : S. Ä긣³Ê, °­¿µ°è ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1983

¡¡

¡¡ ¡¡



¡¡
¡¡
 

 °Ô½ÃÆÇ  °Ë»ö  ÀÚ·á½Ç  »çÀÌÆ®¸Ê  ¿¹¼ö¿Í³ª?

¡¡
 

Jesusi.com Homepage



This page was last modified 2001/05/30