¡¡

Jesusi.com Homepage

¡¡

¡¡

 °Ô½ÃÆÇ  °Ë»ö  ÀÚ·á½Ç  »çÀÌÆ®¸Ê  ¿¹¼ö¿Í³ª?

¡¡
Philosophy 

öÇÐ - ÁöÇýÀÇ Å½±¸

Aristoteles

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º

¡¡

1 Introduction

Aristotle, more than any other thinker, determined the orientation and the content of Western intellectual history. He was the author of a philosophical and scientific system that through the centuries became the support and vehicle for both medieval Christian and Islamic scholastic thought: until the end of the 17th century, Western culture was Aristotelian. And, even after the intellectual revolutions of centuries to follow, Aristotelian concepts and ideas remained embedded in Western thinking.

Aristotle's intellectual range was vast, covering most of the sciences and many of the arts. He worked in physics, chemistry, biology, zoology, and botany; in psychology, political theory, and ethics; in logic and metaphysics; in history, literary theory, and rhetoric. His greatest achievements were in two unrelated areas: he invented the study of formal logic, devising for it a finished system, known as Aristotelian syllogistic, that for centuries was regarded as the sum of logic; and he pioneered the study of zoology, both observational and theoretical, in which his work was not surpassed until the 19th century.

Even though Aristotle's zoology is now out-of-date and his thought in the other natural sciences has long been left behind, his importance as a scientist is unparalleled. But it is now of purely historical importance: he, like other scientists of the past, is not read by his successors. As a philosopher Aristotle is equally outstanding. And here he remains more than a museum piece. Although his syllogistic is now recognized to be only a small part of formal logic, his writings in ethical and political theory as well as in metaphysics and in the philosophy of science are read and argued over by modern philosophers. Aristotle's historical importance is second to none, and his work remains a powerful component in current philosophical debate.

This article deals with the man, his achievements, and the Aristotelian tradition. For treatment of Aristotelianism in the full context of Western philosophy, see PHILOSOPHY, THE HISTORY OF WESTERN , and PHILOSOPHICAL SCHOOLS AND DOCTRINES, WESTERN: Ancient and medieval schools .

2 THE LIFE OF ARISTOTLE

Aristotle was born in the summer of 384 BC in the small Greek township of Stagira (or Stagirus, or Stageirus), on the Chalcidic peninsula of Macedonia, in northern Greece. (For this reason Aristotle is also known as the "Stagirite.") His father, Nicomachus, was court physician to Amyntas III, king of Macedonia, father of Philip II, and grandfather of Alexander the Great. As a doctor's son, Aristotle was heir to a scientific tradition some 200 years old. The case histories contained in the Epidemics of Hippocrates, the father of Greek medicine, may have introduced him at an early age to the concepts and practices of Greek medicine and biology. As a physician, Nicomachus was a member of the guild of the Asclepiads, the so-called sons of Asclepius, the legendary founder and god of medicine. (see also   Greek philosophy)

Because medicine was a traditional occupation in certain families, being handed down from father to son, Aristotle in all likelihood learned at home the fundamentals of that practical skill he was afterward to display in his biological researches. Had he been a medical student he would have undergone a rigorous and varied training: he would have studied the role in therapy of diet, drugs, and exercise; he would have learned how to check the flow of blood, apply bandages, fit splints to broken limbs, reset dislocations, and make poultices of flour, oil, and wine. Such, at least, were the skills of the trained physician of his time. It is not known for certain that Aristotle actually acquired these skills; it is known that medicine and its history were later studied in the Lyceum, Aristotle's own institute in Athens, and that later, in a snobbish vein, he considered a man sufficiently educated if he knew the theory of medicine without having gained experience practicing it.

This early connection with medicine and with the rough-living Macedonian court largely explains both the predominantly biological cast of Aristotle's philosophical thought and the intense dislike of princes and courts to which he more than once gave expression.

2.1 First period: in the Academy at Athens.

While Aristotle was still a youth, his father died, and the young man became a ward of Proxenus, probably a relative of his father. He was sent to the Academy of Plato at Athens in 367 and remained there for 20 years. These years formed the first of three main periods in Aristotle's intellectual development, years dominated by the formative influence of Plato and his colleagues in the Academy. Aristotle doubtless interested himself in the whole range of the Academy's activities. It is known that he devoted some time to the study of rhetoric, and he wrote and spoke for the Academy in its battles against the rival school of Isocrates.

After Plato's death in 348/347 his nephew Speusippus was named as head of the Academy. Aristotle shortly thereafter left Athens--in disgust, it is sometimes claimed, at not being appointed Plato's successor. This interpretation of his motive, however, lacks foundation, for evidence suggests that he was ineligible to be the school's head because of his status as a resident alien who could not hold property legally. It is more likely that his departure from Athens may have been linked with an anti-Macedonian feeling that arose in Athens after Philip had sacked the Greek city-state of Olynthus in 348. Aristotle's 12-year absence from Athens nevertheless indicates that he valued more the circle of friends who accompanied him on his travels--chief among them Theophrastus of Eresus, his pupil, colleague, and eventual successor as head of the Lyceum--than he did his membership in the Platonic Academy.

2.2 Second period: his travels.

With him went another Academy member of note, Xenocrates of Chalcedon, whose lethargy became the target of Plato's ridicule. Plato reportedly contrasted it with Aristotle's more energetic manner: "The one needs a spur, the other a bridle . . . . See what an ass I am training to compete with what a horse." The distinctive characters of the two men, however, seem to have integrated well in establishing a new academy on the Asian side of the Aegean at the newly built town of Assus.

At Assus, Hermeias of Atarneus, a Greek soldier of fortune, had first acquired fiscal and then political control of northwestern Asia Minor, as a vassal of Persian overlords. After a visit to the Athenian Academy he invited two of Plato's graduates to set up a small branch to help spread Greek rule as well as Greek philosophy to Asian soil. Aristotle came to this new intellectual centre. To this period may belong the first 12 chapters of Book 7 of Aristotle's Politics. There he sketches the connection between philosophy and politics, namely, that the highest purpose of a city-state (polis) is to secure the conditions in which those who are capable of it can live the philosophical life. Such a life, however, lies only within the capacity of the Greeks, whose superiority qualifies them to employ the non-Greek tribal peoples as serfs or slaves for the performance of all menial labour. Thus, citizenship and service in the armed forces are considered to be the exclusive rights and duties of the Greeks. Aristotle's espousal of an enlightened oligarchy, nonetheless, actually constituted an advance over the political concepts flourishing at the time and it should be viewed in its context as a positive development in the establishment of the noble civilization created by the Greeks.

At about the same time, Aristotle composed the work, now lost, On Kingship, in which he clearly distinguishes the function of the philosopher from that of the king. He alters Plato's dictum--for the better, it is said--by teaching that it is (see also   philosopher-king)

. . . not merely unnecessary for a king to be a philosopher, but even a disadvantage. Rather a king should take the advice of true philosophers. Then he would fill his reign with good deeds, not with good words.

Aristotle thus strove to assure the independent role of the philosopher.

Aristotle was on good terms with his patron, Hermeias, and married his niece, Pythias. She bore Aristotle a daughter, whom he called by her mother's name. In the Politics, Aristotle prescribed the ideal ages for marriage--37 for the husband and 18 for the wife. Because Aristotle was himself 37 at this time, it is tempting to guess that Pythias was 18. It is also possible that their own marital relations are reflected in his further, somewhat cryptic, observation: "As for adultery, let it be held disgraceful for any man or woman to be found in any way unfaithful once they are married and call each other husband and wife." In his will Aristotle ordered that "Wherever they bury me, there the bones of Pythias shall be laid, in accordance with her own instructions." Pythias did not live long, however; and after her death Aristotle chose another companion, Herpyllis (whether concubine or wife is uncertain), by whom he then had a son, Nicomachus. She outlived Aristotle, and he made ample and considerate provision for her in his will "in recognition of the steady affection she has shown me."

After three years at the young Assus Academy, Aristotle moved to the nearby island of Lesbos and settled in Mytilene, the capital city. With his friend Theophrastus, a native of that island, he established a philosophical circle patterned after the Athenian Academy. There his centre of interest shifted to biology, in which he undertook pioneering investigations. (The landlocked lagoon of Pyrrha in the centre of Lesbos has been identified as one of his favourite haunts.) He appears to have felt it necessary to justify this new attention to biology by rejecting the arguments that had classed it as an inferior, unattractive study. In his biological researches he focused on a new type of causation, namely teleological. Teleological causation has to do with the aim, or end, of nature, a type that is distinct from mechanical causation but one that is, nonetheless, operative in the inorganic sphere. According to Aristotle, natural organisms--plants and animals--have natural ends or goals, and their structure and development can only be fully explained when these goals are understood. To admit the existence of such ends, or aims, in nature is to argue teleologically (Greek telos, "an end") or to admit the idea of a final cause (Latin finis, "end"). Teleology, and theory in general, is important in Aristotle's biology; but it is always, in principle at least, subordinate to observation. Thus, confessing his ignorance of the mode of generation of bees, Aristotle wrote in his treatise On the Generation of Animals:

The facts have not yet been sufficiently established. If ever they are, then credit must be given to observation rather than to theories, and to theories only insofar as they are confirmed by the observed facts.

Associated with his researches into plant and animal life were his reflections on the relation of the soul to the body. As revealed by his tract On the Soul, Aristotle distanced himself from the Platonic conception of the soul as an independently existing substance that is only temporarily resident in the body. With greater emphasis on the positive value of material existence, he suggested instead that the soul is the vital principle essentially united with the body to form the individual person. With some acknowledgment to Plato, he then proceeded to define the soul as the form of the body and the body as the matter of the soul.

In late 343 or early 342 Aristotle, at about the age of 42, was invited by Philip II of Macedon to his capital at Pella to tutor his 13-year-old son, Alexander. As the leading intellectual figure in Greece, Aristotle was commissioned to prepare Alexander for his future role as a military leader. As it turned out, Alexander was to dominate the Greek world and defend it against the Persian Empire. Using the model of the epic Greek hero, as in Homer's Iliad, Aristotle attempted to form Alexander as an embodiment of the classical valour of an Ajax or Achilles enlightened by the latest achievement of Greek civilization, philosophy. With his firm conviction of the superiority of Greeks over foreigners, he instructed Alexander to dominate the barbarians--i.e., non-Greeks--and to hold them in servility by refraining from any physical intermixture with them. Despite this advice, however, Alexander later became committed to intermarriage; he chose a wife from the Persian nobility and forced his high-ranking officers (and encouraged his troops) to do likewise.

In other ways too the influence that Aristotle had on Alexander was negligible. Although later, on his return to Athens, Aristotle enjoyed considerable political and economic support from the Macedonians and perhaps received assistance in the organization of his biological researches, it is not likely--as some have held--that Alexander collected and dispatched to Aristotle specimens of rare animals from Persia and India; in fact, Alexander's first penetration of the valley of the Indus did not occur until 328/327, less than six years before Aristotle's death. Indeed, the relation between the two was embittered by the execution of Aristotle's nephew, the historian Callisthenes of Olynthus, who was charged with treason while accompanying Alexander to Persia early in 328 in order to write a chronicle of the campaign. It has even been reported that Alexander meditated revenge on Aristotle himself because he was a blood relative of the victim. But Alexander was diverted by his preoccupation with the invasion of India. Clearly, in matters of political ideology, a gulf separated Aristotle and Alexander. Aristotle showed no awareness of the fundamental changes that Alexander's conquests were bringing to the Greek world; indeed, he was opposed in principle to Alexander's imperial policy because it diminished the importance of the city-state. On the other hand, Alexander gratified his tutor by rebuilding the town of Stagira, Aristotle's birthplace, which Philip II had destroyed earlier.

After three years at the Macedonian court, Aristotle withdrew and returned to his paternal property at Stagira (c. 339). There he continued the associations of his philosophical circle, which still included Theophrastus and other pupils of Plato.

2.3 Third period: founding and directing of the Lyceum.

Aristotle remained in Stagira until 335, when, nearing 50 years of age, he once again returned to Athens. At this time the presidency of the Academy became vacant by the death of Speusippus, and Xenocrates of Chalcedon, his old associate in biological research, was elected to the post. Although Aristotle appears never to have wholly severed his links with the Academy, he nonetheless opened, in 335, a rival institution in the Lyceum, a gymnasium attached to the temple of Apollo Lyceus, situated in a grove just outside Athens. The place had for some time been frequented by other teachers--Plato even mentions it as having been one of Socrates' haunts--and the name of the temple came to be applied to Aristotle's school in particular. But it was probably only after Aristotle's death that the school, under Theophrastus, acquired extensive property. From the fact that his instruction was given in the peripatos, or covered walkway, of the gymnasium, the school has derived its name of Peripatetic. Informal as the school may have been under Aristotle, it was very important to him because, by coordinating the work of a number of scholars, he was able for the next 12 years to organize it as a centre for speculation and research in every field of inquiry and to give lectures on a wide range of scientific and philosophical questions. The chief difference between the new school and the Academy was that the scientific interests of the Platonists centred on mathematics whereas the main contributions of the Lyceum lay in biology and history.

On the death of Alexander the Great in 323 a brief but vigorous anti-Macedonian agitation broke out in Athens. Aristotle, who had long-standing Macedonian connections and was a friend of Antipater, the Macedonian regent of Athens, felt himself in danger. He therefore left Athens and withdrew to his mother's estates in Chalcis on the island of Euboea. There he died in the following year from a stomach illness at the age of 62 or 63. It was reported that he abandoned Athens in order to save the Athenians from sinning twice against philosophy (referring to Socrates as the earlier victim).

3 PERSONALITY, CHARACTER, AND PHILOSOPHICAL STANCE

The features of Aristotle, familiar from busts and engravings, appear handsome and refined. An ancient tradition, possibly from an unfriendly source, says, however, that Aristotle had spindleshanks and small eyes and that he spoke with a lisp. In compensation for these physical defects, he was notably well dressed. His cloak and sandals were of the best quality and he sported rings. Presumably he was rich, with large family holdings at Stagira. One use that he made of his money was to collect books. Plato, with a touch of contempt for Aristotle's devotion to reading and perhaps not without some envy of his affluence, called him "the reader." Aristotle was an intellectual but not devoid of passion. A story is told of Plato giving a reading of his Phaedo, a purported record of Socrates' last day. The dialogue is moving and solemn. As Plato was reading, however, his audience gradually melted away. In the end, Aristotle alone was left. Probably fictitious, the anecdote was invented to express a truth: Aristotle was, in fact, spellbound by the Socratic doctrine of immortality as expounded by Plato. It not only interested him intellectually but also absorbed him emotionally. His earliest works, dialogues written when he was still a member of the Academy (now lost except for some fragments), were in part concerned with thoughts of the next world and the worthlessness of this one.

The anecdotes related of him reveal him as a kindly, affectionate character, and they show barely any trace of the self-importance that some scholars think they can detect in his works. His will, which has been preserved, exhibits the same kindly traits; he makes references to his happy family life and takes solicitous care of his children, as well as his servants.

This personal happiness is reflected in On Philosophy, perhaps the last of his strictly literary works. After writing this work, which he completed in around 348, he devoted his energies to research, teaching, and the writing of more technical treatises. The greatness of On Philosophy, which survives only in fragments, is evident in its influence on the thought of later antiquity; perhaps more than any other single work it established philosophy as a profession. In the extant part, Aristotle defines the specific role of the philosopher. Dividing the historical development of civilization into five main stages, Aristotle sees the emergence of philosophy as its culmination. First, men are compelled to devote themselves to the creation of the necessities because without them they could not survive. Next come the arts that refine life and then the discovery of the art of politics, the prerequisite of the good life as Aristotle conceived it. To these necessities and refinements of life is added the knowledge of their proper use in the fourth stage. Only with the emergence of the well-regulated state comes the leisure for intellectual adventure, used at first for the study of the material causes of existing things. Finally comes the shift from natural to divine philosophy, when the mind lifts itself above the material world and grasps the formal and final causes of things, realizing the intelligible aspect of reality and the purpose that informs all change.

This divine philosophy gave its attention to the astral gods. Aristotle had experienced in Athens the long intellectual struggle to discover perfect order in the heavens. He had learned that perfection was not to be confined to the mathematical abstractions, to which Plato had at first directed the attention of his pupils, but had come to recognize that the visible heavens themselves could be accepted as the embodiment of the divine. With the declaration of this intimacy between the deities and the work of their hands in the material universe, Aristotle issued his manifesto, which is an optimistic affirmation of the values of this world; simultaneously he rejected the Platonic doctrine that the soul is imprisoned in the body and in need of struggling free from the bonds of matter. It was by this stroke that Aristotle established his own identity in the history of thought.

4 WRITINGS

Aristotle's writings fall into two groups: the first consists of works published by Aristotle but now lost; the second of works not published by Aristotle and, in fact, not intended for publication but collected and preserved by others. In the first group are included (1) the writings that Aristotle himself termed "exoteric," or popular--that is, those written in dialogue or other current literary forms and meant for the general reading public--and (2) those that he termed "hypomnematic," or notes to aid the memory, and collections of materials for further work. Of these, only fragments are extant. Finally, the writings that generally have survived, termed "acroamatic," or treatises (logoi, methodoi, pragmateiai), were meant for use in Aristotle's school and were written in a concise and individualistic style. In later antiquity Aristotle's writings filled several hundred rolls; today the surviving 30 works fill some 2,000 printed pages. Three ancient catalogs list a total of more than 170 separate works by Aristotle, a figure corroborated by references and lists of titles in the extant treatises as well as by a number of citations and paraphrases in early commentators. Cicero must have been alluding to Aristotle's popular dialogues when he described in the Academica "the suave style of Aristotle . . . . A river of gold." The extant works contain several passages of polished prose, but for the most part their style is clipped.

4.1 Lost works published by Aristotle.

The lost popular works include poetry and letters as well as essays and dialogues in the Platonic manner. Several problems have confronted scholars in their attempts to reconstitute these lost popular works. The lost dialogues, for example, appear to diverge widely from the doctrines of the surviving treatises. Indeed, they appear to outdo Plato in his own teaching. Thus, what is known of Aristotle's dialogue Eudemus, or On the Soul, compares the relation of the soul to the body with an unnatural union, like that of the torture that the Tyrrhenian pirates inflicted on their prisoners by binding each of them to a corpse. Inasmuch as Aristotle in his extant treatises criticized his Platonist friends for making soul and body enemies, Alexander of Aphrodisias, an authoritative Aristotelian commentator of the late 2nd century AD, raised the question whether he expressed "two truths," one "exoteric" for public consumption, the other "esoteric" and reserved for his students in the Lyceum. The present consensus of scholars is that Aristotle's popular writings generally derived from the early stage of his intellectual development during his time in Plato's Academy: they represent not his "public" but his juvenile thoughts.

Chief among the lost works are: Eudemus, in the tradition of Plato's Phaedo; On Philosophy, a type of philosophical program containing themes to be developed later in his Metaphysics; the Protrepticus, or exhortation to the life of philosophy; Gryllus, or On Rhetoric; On Justice, expressing nascent themes of his Politics; and On Ideas, which criticizes Plato's theory of Forms.

4.2 Extant works.

The works that have been preserved derive from manuscripts left by Aristotle on his death; many of them were probably used by him as lecture notes. These are the "esoteric" writings of a concentrated, academic nature intended for the ears of the initiates. From classical antiquity romanticized accounts circulated of the way these manuscripts were preserved; e.g., in Plutarch's Sulla, chapter 26; and in Strabo's Geography 13:54. According to these versions, Aristotle's and Theophrastus' notes had been bequeathed to an old colleague, Neleus of Scepsis, whose heirs apparently were not interested in the contents but, in order to prevent them from being confiscated for the library of the kings of Pergamum, hid them in a cellar in Scepsis. Long afterward, in the 1st century BC, the descendants sold them to Apellicon of Teos, a philosopher, who brought them back to Athens. When Athens was conquered by Sulla in 86 BC, he appropriated the books and sent them to Rome, where they were purchased by Tyrannion the grammarian. The manuscripts suffered further maltreatment, first at the hands of copyists, then through subjective restoration of worm-eaten passages and systematic ordering irrespective of actual chronology, until Andronicus of Rhodes, the last head of the Lyceum, acquired the copies and edited and published them about 60 BC.

The story is improbable. It is difficult to imagine that the Lyceum would have allowed the manuscripts of its founder to have been so carelessly looked after. And it is now known that the "esoteric" writings were not wholly ignored in the two centuries after Theophrastus' death. It is true, nevertheless, that the Andronicus edition is the first publication of Aristotle's works, even if the story of the edition's appearance was spread by Andronicus to emphasize its novelty. The form, titles, and order of Aristotle's texts that are studied today were given to them by Andronicus almost three centuries after the philosopher's death, and the long history of commentary upon them began at this stage.

These facts have affected the interpretation of Aristotle. The books of Aristotle that are known today were, in effect, never edited by him. Thus, for example, Aristotle is not the author of the work called Metaphysics; rather, he wrote a dozen little treatises: on the theory of causes in the history of philosophy, on the chief philosophical problems, on the multiplicity of meanings of certain key philosophical terms, on act and potency, on being and essence, on the philosophy of mathematics, and on God. Those that the editors thought worth collecting were given the title Metaphysics; i.e., the tract that is to be read after the Physics. It is not surprising, then, that the Metaphysics and the other works of Aristotle sometimes seem to lack unity or any clear progression of thought, that they are sometimes repetitious and at times even contradictory. The texts furthermore suggest that students or subsequent members of the Lyceum even revised Aristotle's expressions. It is probable that Aristotle would never have released the work. Andronicus, assisted by previous editors, imposed a logical and didactic order upon all the writings, undoubtedly influenced by Aristotle's own emphasis on logic as the propaedeutic (preparatory study) of all understanding. By ignoring the chronological order of the treatises and by grouping dissertations from different periods under the same title, the editors fashioned the Aristotelian corpus into a systematic whole. It is quite likely that Aristotle himself had never thought of his writings in this way.

Aristotle's treatises reveal the philosopher at work. He defines the problem he is to deal with, assesses the views of his predecessors, formulates his own preliminary opinion, considers whether there is a need to modify it in the light of difficulties and objections, rehearses the arguments for different points of view--always searching, in short, for the most adequate solution or resolution of his problem. The reader, therefore, sees Aristotle at work, not dogmatically propounding a doctrine but often laboriously developing a perspective or an insight that emerges from difficulties, contradictions, and paradoxes. Not surprisingly, few syllogisms appear in Aristotle's treatises; the reader, however, should perceive in them a structure that Aristotle himself terms "dialectical"; i.e., in the manner of a dialogue by an exchange of arguments for and against.

5 THEORIES OF THE EVOLUTION OF ARISTOTLE'S THOUGHT

From the conclusions of Alexander of Aphrodisias in the latter part of the 2nd century, a distinction was established between the doctrine expressed in Aristotle's treatises (the technical writings that have come down to the present) and the popular Platonizing dialogues (the "exoteric" works surviving only in fragments). The orthodox view for 17 centuries was that the treatises were the sources for Aristotle's genuine thought; Valentin Rose, a 19th-century German scholar, proposed that all of the lost dialogues are spurious because their doctrine was inconsistent with that of the treatises. The underlying assumption was that a man of such strict and systematic mind as Aristotle would maintain strict constancy and never abandon opinions once formed.

5.1 Jaeger's developmental theory and rejoinders.

In the first half of the 20th century a developmental theory of Aristotle's thought was submitted by Thomas Case, an English scholar, and elaborated in detail by Werner Jaeger, a German historian of Greek philosophy, in his Studien zur Entstehungsgeschichte der Metaphysik des Aristoteles (1912; "Studies in the History of the Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysics") and later in his Aristoteles: Grundlegung einer Geschichte seiner Entwicklung (1923; Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development). Employing a historicogenetic methodology, Jaeger announced that the greater part of Aristotle's lost works represented his thought while he was still at the Academy and under the immediate influence of Plato: the preponderance of such themes as the immortality of the soul, disdain for the material world, the doctrine of the "recollection" of Ideas, the supremacy of wisdom, asceticism, and the existence of God were recognizably Platonic. These dialogues addressed a wide audience and were presented in an elegant literary style that fascinated classical authors. According to Jaeger, Aristotle gradually distanced himself from Plato's position, even during his time at the Academy--rejecting certain Platonic arguments, adopting contrary positions, continually evolving from Platonic Idealism to a marked empiricism.

In response to this evolutionary theory, critics have noted that the analysis of Aristotle's works generates complex problems, as observed above in the account of the formation of the text of his existing writings. The works edited by Andronicus of Rhodes are compilations of texts from different periods. Thus, the Metaphysics covers almost the entire career of Aristotle, as does the Politics. Often within the same chapter, even in a single paragraph, one discerns elements from different stages of Aristotle's thought: his early phase at the Academy, his maturity, his period of travel away from Athens, and his Lyceum experience, which purportedly was divided between morning sessions with his best students and afternoon meetings with a wider audience from Athens. Given all this, there are serious obstacles in the way of discussing the chronology of the treatises: it becomes extremely difficult to put a date on a work that was revised and modified in various ways during a considerable portion of Aristotle's intellectual career.

One of Jaeger's main assumptions, moreover, is questionable. He supposes that Aristotle only agreed with Plato during his early years at the Academy or, at the latest, until the close of the first Athenian period (347 BC). This assumption, however, is arbitrary and cannot be corroborated by the evidence. (see also   Platonism)

One could conceivably defend the converse: that Aristotle, in a self-assured youth, could have strongly challenged Plato but, having subsequently become conscious of the more profound significance of his master's philosophical postulates, did not hesitate to integrate with his own thought one or more Platonic theses. Indeed, in one of the logical treatises, Topics, considered one of Aristotle's early works because it reflects discussions at the Academy, and in the Eudemian Ethics, the first version of Aristotle's course on ethics, there are strongly anti-Platonic views expressed.

Jaeger's theory is most plausible with regard to Aristotle's psychology, as demonstrated by François Nuyens, a Dutch historian of philosophy, in 1939. He held that in his early period, represented by the Eudemus and the Protrepticus, Aristotle began as a Platonist, describing the soul as a separate substance in an unnatural relationship with the body; next, in an intermediate stage, he described the body as the instrument of the soul, whose function is analogous to that of a pilot steering a ship; finally, in the tract On the Soul, he advanced more clearly the concept of a substantial unity of body and soul by making the soul the form, or actuality, of a natural body. (see also   dualism)

Other authorities on Aristotle have observed that such a linear transition in his thought occurs rarely among his writings. Even in the works on psychology, moreover, Aristotle's concern for metaphysical thought does not end with his intermediate biological phase but continues and extends even into his empirical stage at the Lyceum. Such a simultaneous preoccupation with both scientific and philosophical thought is further manifested in the sequence of books in the Metaphysics.

At the other extreme is the hypothesis of the German scholar Josef Zürcher, in Aristoteles Werke und Geist (1952; "The Works and Spirit of Aristotle"), who asserted that Aristotle's own thought always remained Platonic and that all of the characteristically Peripatetic philosophy came from his disciple and successor, Theophrastus, who is the true author of about three-quarters of the existing Aristotelian treatises. According to this theory, there never existed a young Aristotle and an elder Aristotle in terms of any development of his thought: there was simply a Platonic Aristotle and an anti-Platonic Theophrastus, an empiricist. This eccentric theory has found no followers. In reaction to it, the Swedish scholar Ingemar Düring suggested in 1966 that Aristotle never really subscribed to the Platonic theory of transcendent Forms, or Ideas, but maintained lifelong and coexistent interests in empirical investigation and metaphysical speculation; for Düring, as for Zürcher, there is no need to postulate any fundamental change or development in Aristotle's thought.

5.2 Recent analyses of Aristotle's development and systematizing.

Aristotelian scholars have generally concluded that a basis exists for a theory of evolution in his thought but that the determination of the chronology and the degree of change presents a difficult set of problems. It is quite possible to agree with Jaeger that during Aristotle's first years at the Academy he acknowledged Plato's teaching on Ideas, and that he later rejected the theory. It is another matter, however, to suggest that in his later years he renounced such Platonically influenced doctrines as the immortality of the soul or the conception of a religious philosophy concluding in an ultimate being termed God. Increased attention to data of the senses in subsequent phases of his life, moreover, is not a sufficient argument for the emergence of an empiricist Aristotle, who could not but oppose a spiritualist and idealist Plato. It is true that Aristotle later criticized the doctrine of Ideas as inadequate and contradictory. But he continued, nevertheless, to recognize the effectiveness of metaphysical thought in arriving at the concept of a transcendent, nonmaterial, and subsistent intellect as the necessary explanation for the fact that anything exists. The consensus of modern commentators thus suggests that not every aspect of Platonic idealism was rejected by Aristotle as his appreciation of empirical knowledge and of the dynamic aspects of matter grew. Rather, alongside his experimental work in biology and physics was his continued insistence on the crucial differences between perception and thought, between accidental characteristics and the essential natures of things.

The inconsistencies, contrasts, and varying degrees of emphasis on different modes of thought throughout the Aristotelian corpus are not adequately explained either by positing intervening editors and copyists or simply by different stages in Aristotle's thought. He clearly attempted in all of the treatises to relate his own views to the whole history of thought before his time. On many occasions he was concerned, at the same point in the development of his thinking, to state different views seen as alternative possibilities. Often his method was deliberately aporetic; that is to say, he raised difficulties that he knew had to be faced but for which he supplied no immediate or definitive solutions. Left by Plato with a vast body of problems, Aristotle conscientiously pursued the ideal of correcting and complementing the intellectual tradition bequeathed to him. To this end he often followed parallel but distinct paths of investigation. His method was exploratory, and he used it on whatever fertile soil he was free to work. Only relatively late in life was he able to unify his results with any degree of success. The philosophy of Aristotle does not unfold simply by deducing consequences from assumed principles. Rather, it starts from aporiai, from puzzles or problems, and it proceeds by piecemeal, tentative, and multiform attempts at solutions. The end result that Aristotle in his optimistic moments hoped to achieve was indeed a fixed body of knowledge, systematically ordered and deductively demonstrated. But his method of inquiry was not deductive, and the finished system remained an aspiration rather than an accomplishment.

6 SYNOPSES OF THE ARISTOTELIAN CORPUS

 

6.1 Works on logic.

The term logic was not invented by Aristotle but goes back to Xenocrates of the Academy. Aristotle, however, attributed extensive significance to language (logos) and to the rules of discourse; thus he emphasized that language is distinctive of the human species, and he defined man as a rational animal, which in the Greek also means an animal possessing a language or speech or word. (see also   formal logic)

In Aristotle's view, the purpose of language is to express the feelings and experiences of the soul, and consequently words are signs, or symbols, of thoughts and other mental phenomena.

The logical treatises of Aristotle make up the collection known as the Organon ("tool"). This title was adopted by later commentators, who, in accordance with the well-established Peripatetic tradition, regarded logic as an instrument for doing philosophy. In Aristotle's preferred view logic was not included in the classification of the sciences at all, but it was treated as a preliminary to the study of each and every branch of knowledge. Aristotle's own name for logic was "analytics." The term logic, however, is employed in a somewhat restricted sense in Aristotle's own writings; e.g., in the Topics I, 14. And there is some evidence that it was beginning to be used as the equivalent of dialectic or analytics almost immediately after Aristotle's death.

The Organon contains the following treatises: the Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, Posterior Analytics, Topics, and the Sophistical Refutations. The arrangement within the collection is meant to be systematic rather than chronological. Indeed, the original chronological order can hardly be determined now with any certainty because Aristotle, or other editors, apparently used later insertions to supplement the original treatises. In a possible sequence of their composition, the Categories, Topics, and the Sophistical Refutations are listed earlier than On Interpretation, and this work, in turn, is earlier than the Prior Analytics and the Posterior Analytics. The chapters on modal logic in the Prior Analytics are probably the last that Aristotle added to the body of the Organon. Apart from the Organon, the fourth book of the Metaphysics could be described as a logical work inasmuch as it is centrally concerned with certain general principles of thought (the principle of noncontradiction, the law of the excluded middle).

In the Categories, Aristotle distinguished expressions that exhibit propositional unity from expressions that do not; that is, he distinguished between a simple term and a composite statement that relates a subject to a predicate. This notion of propositional unity can be traced back to Plato, but the treatment of simple expressions was Aristotle's innovation. He considered simple expressions neither true nor false and held that they may signify things in one or another of the following categories: substance, quantity, quality, relation, place, time, position, state, action, and affection. It is by no means clear whether this classification is to be regarded as primarily ontological (concerning the nature of reality) or as primarily verbal--i.e., whether it is about actual things or about words and expressions; the same ambiguity has been characteristic of practically every other scheme of categories suggested since Aristotle's time. (see also   ontology)

As a part of a theory of reality Aristotle later used the categories to criticize Plato's theory of Forms. For Aristotle, Plato was involved in a confusion between the category of substance and the other categories when, for example, he attributed substantiality, or concrete existence, to qualities such as beauty or wisdom. In chapter 5 of the Categories, Aristotle distinguishes within the category of substance between "primary substance" and "secondary substance." Primary substances are particular men, particular horses, particular stones, etc., and secondary substances are the species and genera to which the individuals belong. There Aristotle treated genus and species as substances of a derived kind. In the Metaphysics, however, species and forms appear to be substances of a primary kind. Aristotle's view, it must be said, is far from clear--some scholars see the Metaphysics as a return to a more Platonic conception of ontology.

On Interpretation begins with a brief but influential discussion of the simple parts of sentences, such as "names" and "verbs"; it then considers complete sentences of various kinds and examines the logical relationships (contrariety, contradiction, implication) holding among them. The work also contains a pioneering account of "modal" sentences ("It is possible that . . ."; "It is necessary that . . .") and a celebrated discussion of "future contingents." (If it is already true that there will be a sea battle tomorrow, then how can the battle be considered a contingent event? For if the truth is already determined, surely the battle is fixed and necessary? Aristotle's answer to this is that certain types of sentences about the future are neither true nor false.)

The Topics appears to have been intended as a manual for participants in contests that involved argumentation. For the most part this treatise consists of suggestions about how to look for an argument that will either establish or refute a given thesis; thus it elucidates general logical laws or rules.

The Sophistical Refutations exposes forms of reasoning that appear valid on the surface but are in fact fallacious. Examples of fallacious arguments are "begging the question," or circular argument (e.g., a "proof" that the soul continues to exist after death because it is immortal); the "fallacy of the consequent," or arguing from a consequent to its condition (e.g., if a man is a drunkard he becomes destitute; Peter is destitute: therefore Peter is a drunkard); and the "fallacy of the irrelevant conclusion," wherein, instead of proving the fact in dispute, the arguer seeks to gain his point by diverting attention to some extraneous fact. (see also   fallacy of the consequent, fallacy of irrelevant conclusion)

The main achievement of the Prior Analytics is the development of the logical system now known as Aristotelian syllogistic. A syllogism is a form of argument consisting of three propositions (two premises and a conclusion). The stock example of a valid syllogism is the following:

Every Greek is a man.

Every man is mortal.

Every Greek is mortal.

Both premises are either affirmative or negative and contain two terms (the subject and the predicate) together with a sign of "quantity" ("every," "some," "no"). In addition, the propositions are either "assertoric" or "apodeictic" or "problematic"--they express the idea that something is or must or can be the case. "Every man must be rational" is apodeictic and affirmative; it is universal in quantity ("every"); its subject term is "man" and its predicate is "being rational." The Prior Analytics examines, with astonishing rigour and sophistication, the various possible forms of syllogistic argument.

In the Posterior Analytics Aristotle seeks to apply his logical theory to scientific and epistemological ends. He discusses the proper structure of scientific knowledge, urging that each science must depend on a set of first principles, or axioms, that are necessarily true and directly knowable. The truths, or theorems, that together constitute a science are to be deduced from its axioms, which both necessitate and explain them. Aristotle came to hope that all these scientific deductions could be formulated by way of apodeictic syllogisms. For this reason much of the second book of the Posterior Analytics is devoted to the theory of "definition," for Aristotle thought that the most important axioms of any science would be definitions of its proper subject matter. Among the various axioms of geometry, for example, there would be a definition of the triangle--an account of what a triangle really is or of the essence of a triangle.

6.2 Works on the philosophy of nature.

In his treatise Physics Aristotle deals with natural bodies in general, or with all that is corporeal; special kinds of material bodies are discussed in his other physical works, such as On the Heavens or the Meteorology. The first book of the Physics is concerned with the intrinsic, constitutive elements of a natural body, those that he called "matter" and "form"; i.e., the substratum that persists through change and the feature whose acquisition determines the nature of change. The second book treats mainly the different types of cause studied by the physicist, the material and the formal causes just mentioned, and the final and efficient causes, or the goal for the sake of which and the agent by means of which anything comes into being. Books 3 through 7 deal with movement, or motion, and the notions implied in it--such as space, position, and time, their magnitudes and continuity. The subject of Book 8 is the first mover, which, though not itself a natural body, is the cause of all movement in natural bodies; its necessary attributes--such as immovability and eternalness--are also examined. (see also   hylomorphism)

Whatever the virtues or defects, clarity or obscurity, of Aristotle's physical treatises, they assume that the distinction between physics and metaphysics (the "first philosophy," or the science of being as being) is valid. Although the conception of a continuous scale of nature from inorganic substances to biological and psychological phenomena is basic in all of his science, explanation does not consist in running uniformly up the hierarchy of beings to God nor in reducing all functioning to some material organ. The sciences of Aristotle are based on a multiple system of classification, not on a simple scheme of mutually exclusive and independently existent genera and species. The very distinction of causes in existing and mutable things permits the differentiation of the subject matters of the natural sciences. (see also   science, philosophy of)

The general principles discussed in the Physics are applied to the universe as a whole in On the Heavens (where Aristotle argues that the world is spatially finite but temporally eternal) and to the inanimate parts of the universe in On Generation and Corruption and the Meteorology. The former treatise discusses, in general terms, the four "elements" of the Aristotelian system (earth, air, fire, water) and their interrelations; Aristotle pays particular attention to the question of elemental change, whereby one element can alter and become another. The Meteorology deals with what, from a modern point of view, is a miscellany of topics--astronomy (e.g., comets), geography (e.g., rivers), chemistry (e.g., burning), as well as meteorology (e.g., rainbows). In addition to the general principles of physics and the theory of the elements, Aristotle relies on a further postulate: he supposes that "exhalations," some moist and some dry (steam and smoke), are constantly given off by the earth, and he attempts to explain the various phenomena he investigates in terms of the operation of these exhalations.

The principles of the Physics are also evident in Aristotle's biological and zoological writings. The largest of these, the History of Animals (a better translation of the Greek title would be Inquiry into Animals) consists in the main of descriptions of different animal species. Some of these descriptions--notably those of the crustaceans--are remarkable for their detail and accuracy. Some scholars regard the History as no more than a repository of raw data, collected for scientific scrutiny but not yet ordered or systematized. Others, however, think that Aristotle is concerned with constructing a biological taxonomy that divides the animal world into genera and species. The truth probably lies somewhere between these two views. There is neither a fully fledged Aristotelian taxonomy nor a fixed system of genera and species, but the material in the History is not simply an unorganized heap--the subject matter of the work is intelligently and significantly arranged.

However that may be, the Parts of Animals and the Generation of Animals, although they too present a quantity of empirical data, are primarily scientific and explanatory in intention. Aristotle is concerned with the nature and the function of the various animal organs and other "parts"; he wants not merely to describe and list them, but to "explain" them, both by reference to similarities across different animal species and also--and more strikingly--by reference to their functions within the animal's bodily system and behaviour. It is here that Aristotle's insistence on teleological explanation is most apparent: "nature," he says, "does nothing in vain," and although he does not, strictly speaking, hold that all features of animate beings have a functional explanation (the colour of eyes, for example, is accidental), such explanations are pervasive and are the mark of good science. The Generation of Animals considers specifically the problems of reproduction and growth. What contributions do male and female parents make to the embryo? What characteristics are inherited, and from whom, and how? How do embryos grow and develop, and how in particular do they acquire the different faculties that together constitute their souls? In this, Aristotle's most mature scientific work, the virtues and the vices of his method are most plainly to be seen: he is usually modest, careful, exact; he advances theoretical explanations, but he does not let theory prejudice observation; he attempts to produce a genuinely scientific work. On the other hand, the limitations of his knowledge--and of his means of acquiring new knowledge--are evident; and at least some of his theoretical concepts are crude and inadequate.

The biological works also include two short essays discussing animal locomotion entitled the Movement of Animals and the Progression of Animals. Here Aristotle attempts--not wholly successfully--to combine a rigorously mechanical account of animal motion, considered in terms of the physiology of the body and the nature of the medium, with a psychological discussion of the mental antecedents (perception, thought, desire) that explain animal behaviour.

6.3 Works on psychology.

The relation between the active principle and the passive continuum (or between form and matter) that is operational in sentient and intellectual life is examined in On the Soul. After exploring the concept and the conditions of life, Aristotle relates the function of matter and form (body and soul) in human life to all of life's biological and psychological phenomena while rejecting Platonic transcendentalist and pre-Socratic materialist theories on the nature of the soul. The soul, as the form of the organic body, consists of an ordered set of faculties; these are, in hierarchical order, the nutritive, the perceptual, and the intellectual faculties. The nutritive faculty is common to all living things and is responsible for growth and nutrition; the perceptual faculty is common to all animals and is responsible for, among other things, sight, hearing, smell, and locomotion; and the intellectual faculty is peculiar to humans. Aristotle gives detailed accounts of the modes of perception (in addition to the five senses and their objects he postulates the existence of a "common sense" that unites their deliverances) and a notoriously difficult account of thought (which distinguishes an "active" from a "passive" intellect). The work also contains a discussion of animal movement and of its preconditions--of imagination and of desire. (see also   mind)

In the Parva Naturalia, the medieval designation for a collection of short treatises on natural functions, the argument of On the Soul is supplemented by a sequence of treatises on sense and the sensible, memory and reminiscence, sleeping and waking, prophecy in sleep, the length and brevity of life, youth and old age, life and death, and respiration. (see also   "On the Senses and Their Objects," )

6.4 Works on metaphysics.

The study of metaphysics, the function and content of which have generated neither conviction nor consensus of opinion on the scope of its subject matter, is--together with the syllogism and the differentiation of kinds of premises--an innovation of Aristotle. In his Metaphysics the doctrines that Aristotle sometimes refers to as "wisdom" and sometimes as "first philosophy" or even as "theology" are developed. Its task is that of describing the most general or abstract features of reality and the principles that have universal validity. In a famous (and misleading) phrase, he describes metaphysics as the study of "being qua being." By that he means that metaphysics studies whatever must be true of all existent things just insofar as they exist, that it studies the general conditions which any existing thing must satisfy.

Book 1 of the Metaphysics discusses in a preparatory way the problem of causal explanation. Aristotle gives a survey of the forms of explanation used or discussed by his predecessors, and discovers that his own theory of "four causes" represents the truth toward which they were struggling. This survey is one of the most important sources for information about the pre-Socratics and also about certain aspects of Plato's philosophy. Book 2 is a short essay on the principles of science, and Book 3 sets out a long series of metaphysical puzzles, or aporiai. The puzzles receive a preliminary discussion: most, but not all, of them are dealt with at greater length in later parts of the Metaphysics.

Book 4 explains Aristotle's conception of "first philosophy" as the general study of the conditions of existence, and it contains a defense of the principle of noncontradiction ("not both P and not-P") and the law of the excluded middle ("either P or not-P"). Book 5, sometimes called Aristotle's philosophical lexicon, is devoted to ambiguous philosophical terms: Aristotle analyzes and distinguishes the different usages of some 40 key words. Book 6 returns to the issues of Book 4.

Books 7-9 form a unit. These central books are among the most difficult that Aristotle ever wrote, and they defy summary. The question to which they address themselves is this: What is substance? What are the fundamental constituents of the world, the things that enjoy an independent existence and can be known and defined? Aristotle's discussion is tortuous. It turns on the ideas of matter and form, of substance and essence, of change and generation, of actuality and potentiality. Aristotle's conclusion, it seems, is that substances are, in some sense, forms. They are not abstract Platonic Forms, but concrete, particular forms. They are the things designated by such phrases as "this man," "that horse," or "this oak tree."

Book 10 is a self-contained essay on "oneness"--on unity, continuity, identity, and related concepts. Book 11, which simply summarizes parts of the Physics and earlier parts of the Metaphysics, is generally regarded as spurious. Book 12 gives Aristotle's "theology": he asks how many causes must be posited to explain the world and arrives eventually at the conception of God, or of the first, or unmoved, mover. Aristotle's God, however, is not a personal God interested in the affairs of this world. Instead he is pure intelligence and as such completely indifferent to the vicissitudes of the world (as is implied in the concept of unmoved mover). In addition, the concept of first mover is not to be understood in a temporal sense. The first mover is not the creator of the world--indeed, Aristotle thought that the world was not created at all but had been in existence for all eternity--but the fountainhead of all motion. In that sense he is the ultimate cause of everything that happens in the world. Finally, Books 13 and 14 contain a long discussion--mostly critical and directed against Plato--of the nature of mathematical objects.

6.5 Works on ethics and politics.

In emphasizing the crucial differences in the purposes of the theoretical and practical sciences, Aristotle indicates that the practical disciplines, unlike the theoretical, are for the sake of doing or making something and not for the sake of contemplating, defining, or knowing it. Thus, at the start of his Nicomachean Ethics he explains how the practical sciences are incapable of the exactness of the theoretical sciences, for their subject matters are not limited to things that are amenable to precise definition, but involve habits and skills, which can be acquired and lost, and associations and institutions, which in their changes affect the accomplishment of political actions and the practicability of moral ends. And however precise biological or psychological definitions may be, man varies as moral agent and as citizen according to environmental determination, educational background, and the influences of family, economic position, social class, means of livelihood, and even the associations of his leisure.

Relating ethics to politics, Aristotle set out to demonstrate that problems of morality as they affect the individual cannot be separated from each other or from problems of political association. The Ethics and Politics therefore do not develop separate sciences or independent subject matters but rather supplement each other by treating a common field according to different aspects.

Although he treated moral problems in terms of the potentialities of individual men, the ability to practice and actualize these potentialities is dependent upon political circumstances. Therefore, in the first chapters of Book 1 of the Ethics, Aristotle begins by introducing moral considerations into the broad context of political philosophy, and he ends by returning, in the concluding Book 10, from the examination of happiness and the contemplative life to a shrewd statement of the contribution of law to moral questions, which forms the transition from ethics to politics. (see also   law, philosophy of)

Aristotle's approach to ethics is teleological; that is, he discusses ethics not in terms of moral absolutes but in terms of what is conducive to man's good. This approach leads him to examine various kinds of good and to arrive at the identification of the highest good with the attainment of happiness. After careful discussion of the problematic concept of happiness, Aristotle arrives at a definition of happiness as activity of the soul in accordance with virtue.

Aristotle distinguishes moral virtues and intellectual virtues, which are determined, respectively, by the irrational and the rational powers of the soul. Man, however, does not possess these virtues at birth but comes endowed with the capacity, or disposition, for developing them in the course of time. For example, a child begins by following his parents' injunction to tell the truth without initially realizing the moral excellence of his action; yet eventually the habit of veracity becomes an ingrained part of his moral character. Aristotle then differentiates virtue from vice, arriving at the definition of virtue as a "mean," or middle disposition, between the vicious extremes of excess and deficiency; courage, a virtue, for example, is the mean between cowardice and rashness.

Aristotle concludes his discussion by defining the highest happiness open to man. Because happiness is an activity in accordance with virtue, it follows that the highest happiness should be in accordance with man's highest virtue. And that, according to Aristotle, is the activity which distinguishes man from the other animals, namely the activity of reason or activity in accordance with reason. Thus in its ideal form happiness turns out to consist in a life of intellectual contemplation. Aristotle, on the other hand, also concedes that the political life (activity in accordance with moral virtue) can bring happiness, albeit "in a secondary degree."

The Politics takes up the problems of human action and association as they bear on the ends of communal life encompassed in living well. But the choice of political ends requires a complex examination of possible criteria capable of application to the vast diversity of men and human conditions. Grounding his argument on the premise that man is "naturally" a political animal, Aristotle develops the theory of the state, distinguishes various kinds of constitution, and considers the best state for the particular circumstances, character, and conditions of the citizens. Aristotle also discusses the nature and causes of political instability and revolution. The last two books of the Politics--part of an unfinished description of the ideal state--are largely concerned with education.

6.6 Works on art and rhetoric.

Aristotle analyzes rhetoric in terms of its end, or final, cause, which is persuasion. Like dialectic it is not a science, and therefore it has no specific subject matter, no single method, and no proper set of principles. It is simply the faculty, or power, of observing in any given case the available means of persuasion. According to Aristotle, there are three modes of persuasion that a speaker may exercise: the persuasive power of his own character, the excitation of desired emotions in the audience, and proof or apparent proof.

In the Poetics Aristotle's analysis of poetry provides for careful isolation of the specific character of poetry. In comparing poetry to history, he states that poetry is more philosophic than history and thus of greater intrinsic worth. The difference is attributable not to form--history written in metre is still history--but to the fact that the historian deals with singulars (i.e., with specific events and specific personages). The poet, on the other hand, creates types and situations that, while imitating nature, are, nonetheless, akin to universals; that is, the poet describes what is possible as though it were both likely and necessary. Yet Aristotle also permits the analogy of poetry to oratory as well as the consideration of the moral, political, and educational effects of both. Tragedy, however, which is the only kind of poetry analyzed in the extant portions of Aristotle's work, is defined in terms of its form, not in terms of its purpose, as a kind of imitation rather than as a mode of persuasion or excitation. Thus, in the famous definition of the sixth chapter, it imitates a serious action of great magnitude in a dramatic form and accomplishes the purification (katharsis) of the emotions of pity and fear. (see also   Aristotelian criticism, art, philosophy of, aesthetics)

Using this definition as the basis for the discussion of poetry, Aristotle considered poetic art in terms of the characteristics and interrelations of the six parts, or components, of tragedy: plot, character, and thought (the objects of imitation); diction and melody (the means of imitation); and spectacle (the manner of imitation).

The last four chapters of the Poetics return to more general questions of value and to final causes by means of detailed comparisons of tragedy with comparable poetic works and specifically with epic.

Aristotle and Aristotelianism

7 ON READING ARISTOTLE

Goethe compared Aristotle's philosophy to a pyramid rising on high in regular form from a broad base on the Earth. Because each part of Aristotle's philosophy contributes to the understanding of other parts, it is generally true of his works--even more than those of most philosophers--that they cannot be read initially with a sure and well-grounded understanding but they must be reread for the sake of perceiving the primary conceptual and methodological relationships. Faced with the mass of materials that constitute the imposing body of his works, the reader might best start with the treatment of those problems that are relevant, interesting, or important to him. Aristotle himself often reiterated the suggestion that the inquirer concentrate first on sense experience as something that is better known to him and attend only afterward to the essential concepts of things in the effort to organize knowledge and constitute the principles of the particular sciences. Indeed, he frequently distinguished the process of inquiry and discovery from that of demonstration and proof.

Aristotle's thought can be said to be known in two ways: (1) as remnants of his doctrines constituting the speech of Western culture, in the tradition of Western thought, and in the history of its sciences; and (2) as it is known from the attentive study of his writings. What Aristotle discovered in his intellectual inquiries and what he said can be most readily intelligible to someone of Western culture in the modified form in which it still constitutes part of that thought and conviction. It may be suggested, therefore, that Aristotle be read for the first time in an order the reverse of that in which his works have traditionally been arranged and that his conclusions and analyses be examined before inquiring about his principles. It is true, for example, that what Aristotle said concerning the poetic and rhetorical arts is more complex in manner of analysis and more difficult in systematic construction than what modern writers might say on such subjects; but it, nonetheless, still approximates more nearly to contemporary thought in this area than do his works on physics and metaphysics. And, for the same reason, his moral and political theory led him, in the course of its development, to many distinctions and statements that a modern reader would be disposed to accept or to reject without too lengthy critical discussion.

Once the manner of Aristotle's analysis is more firmly grasped and better appreciated, the reader can proceed to take up his logical works in the Organon and his investigations of space, time, and motion in the Physics. Through later consultation with the more complex thought in the Metaphysics and in On the Soul, he can review the earlier tentative conclusions made in the study of ethics and literary theory in the light of the deeper insights, acute distinctions, and strength of argument thus acquired.

When a student approaches Aristotle's conclusions in the light of his principles, allowing the text to illuminate his own experiences, Aristotle can then be appreciated not only for his expression of a philosophy but also as a help in the cultivation of the mind. And this is a task to which Aristotle himself thought all men should devote themselves and to which his philosophy remains a unique contribution. ( A.H.Ao./Ed.)

8 ASSESSMENT AND NATURE OF ARISTOTELIANISM

The extent to which Aristotelian thought has become a component of civilization can hardly be overestimated. To begin, there are certain words that have become indispensable for the articulate communication of thoughts, experiences, and problems. Some words still carry their Greek form, whereas others have become established in their more important meanings as Latin equivalents of Aristotle's own words. The centuries-long impact of Aristotelian schooling lies at the root of the establishment of the following vocabulary: "subject" and "predicate" in grammar and logic; "form" (information, transform) and "matter" as expressing the two correlative aspects of something that has acquired or acquires something else that is possibly essential to it; "energy" as the active power inherent in a thing; "potential" for what is latent but can be released; "substance" and "essence," "quantity" and "quality," "accidental," "relation," "cause" (and the many meanings of "because" corresponding to the four causes), "genus" and "species" (general, special), "individual," "indivisible" (atomic)--these constitute only a small sample of terms that still carry the mark of Aristotle's philosophy.

Beyond language, features that cumulatively or severally characterize Aristotelianism include, in philosophical methodology, a critical approach to previous, contemporary, or hypothetical doctrines; the raising and discussing of doctrinal difficulties; the use of deductive reasoning proceeding from self-evident principles or discovered general truths; and syllogistic forms of demonstrative or persuasive arguments.

In epistemology, or the theory of knowledge, Aristotelianism includes a concentration on knowledge either accessible by natural means or accountable for by reason; an inductive, analytical empiricism, or stress on experience, in the study of nature--including the study of men, their behaviour and organizations--leading from the perception of contingent individual occurrences to the discovery of permanent, universal patterns; and the primacy of the universal, that which is expressed by common or general terms.

In metaphysics, or the theory of Being, Aristotelianism involves belief in the primacy of the individual in the realm of existence; in the applicability to reality of a certain set of explanatory concepts (e.g., 10 categories; genus-species-individual, matter-form, potentiality-actuality, essential-accidental; the four material elements and their basic qualities; and the four causes--formal, material, efficient, and final); in the soul as the inseparable form of each living body in the vegetable and animal kingdoms; in activity as the essence of things; and in the primacy of speculative over practical activity.

In the philosophy of nature, Aristotelianism denotes an optimistic position concerning nature's aims and its economy; believing in the perfection and in the eternity of the heavenly, geocentric spheres, perceiving them as driven by intelligent movers, as carrying in their circular movements the stars, the Sun, the planets, and the Moon, and as also influencing the sublunary world; and holding that light bodies rise naturally away from the centre of the Earth, while heavy bodies move naturally toward it with a speed related to their weight.

In aesthetics, ethics, and politics, Aristotelian thought holds that poetry is an imitation of what is possible in real life; that tragedy, by imitation of a serious action cast in dramatic form, achieves purification (katharsis) through fear and pity; that virtue is a middle between extremes; that man's happiness consists primarily in intellectual activity and secondarily in the exercise of the virtues; and that the state is a self-sufficient society, necessary for men to achieve happiness.

9 HISTORY OF ARISTOTELIANISM

 

9.1 Continuity of the Aristotelian tradition.

Since Aristotle's death there have been, without interruption until the present, schools and individuals who have cultivated the study of his works and fully or partly adopted and expounded his doctrines and methods. They have interpreted or misinterpreted, approved or condemned, and reshaped or utterly transformed them. The languages in which this interest was most forcibly expressed have changed in turn and over time from Greek to Latin; to Syriac, Arabic, and Hebrew; to Italian, French, English, and German. The main centres in which it appeared have been as far apart as Greece, North Africa, and Rome in the ancient world; Persia and Spain, Sicily and the British Isles in the Middle Ages; and Germany and North America in more recent times.

The main strand of the Aristotelian tradition has been the Greek line, which lasted 2,000 years, mainly in the area along the eastern Mediterranean Sea, and branched off at various stages between the 4th and 15th centuries, giving rise to (or strengthening) other traditions. The Latin branch originated in Rome in the 4th century and acquired a new impulse, probably from Athens, in the early 6th century. From these beginnings it was revived in the 9th century and again in the 12th, at which time a second and even stronger Aristotelian wave emerged from Constantinople, to be followed by a third, via the western Arabic schools, from Spain; and both branches spread to Italy, France, and the British Isles. The final direct contribution from the Greek to the Latin tradition came to Italy, once more from or through Constantinople, in the 15th century.

Shortly after the beginning of Latin Aristotelianism certain Armenian and Syrian members of the Greek schools of Athens and Alexandria in Egypt introduced Aristotelian teachings into their schools. The Armenian tradition was still alive in the 19th century in such places as Madras and Venice; and the Syrian tradition, which never completely disappeared, was still powerful in the 14th century, after having given birth, in the 9th and 10th centuries, to an Arabic tradition. Arabic Aristotelianism was the product of Syrians, Persians, Turks, Jews, and Arabs who wrote and taught in their own countries as well as in Africa and Spain until the 12th century. Much of it and of what the Jews produced in Hebrew in the following two centuries passed into the Latin tradition between 1130 and 1550. Thus, all of the varied heritage that had derived ultimately from the Greek line and had been vastly enriched by other cultures came to be collected, through the Latin branch, by modern Western philosophical movements.

9.2 The Greek tradition.

 

9.2.1 Early development.

For some decades after his death Aristotle's own school, the Peripatos or Lyceum, remained, in a truly Aristotelian spirit, a centre for critical research--not for the dogmatic acceptance of a closed system. Aristotle's immediate successor, Theophrastus, independently elaborated his master's metaphysics and psychology and added to his study of nature (botany and mineralogy) and logic (theory of propositions and hypothetical syllogisms). Various members of the Lyceum coordinated Aristotelian thought with other current schools of philosophy. Thus Aristoxenus joined Aristotelian and Pythagorean doctrines; Critolaus united Aristotle's theory of the influence of the heavens on the world with the Stoic theory of providence; and Clearchus of Soli combined Plato's views on the human soul with Aristotle's.

Outside the Lyceum, the Stoic school was partly following Aristotle in its interest in formal logic, the theory of meaning, and use of the categories (e.g., substance, quality, relation). It was Aristotelian also in its empiricism, as well as in its concentration on nature, in several aspects of natural science, and in its belief that man is intrinsically a social being. The Skeptics sometimes relied on Aristotelian forms of argument to prove their systematic doubts. Even Epicurus, who may have fought against Aristotle's early theology and psychology and ignored his mature philosophy, was, nonetheless, near him in his doctrine of the will and in his conception of friendship and the pursuit of knowledge as the high aims that give satisfaction and pleasure to man. (see also   Stoicism)

Although relatively little was known of Aristotle's "esoteric" works until the 1st century BC, his more popular, literary, and Platonizing writings influenced eclectics such as Panaetius and his pupil Poseidonius; and this influence continued, helped by the Roman philosopher and lawyer Cicero, well into the 4th and 5th centuries AD. Upon it was based the tendency to establish a harmony between the thought of Plato and Aristotle--a feature that recurred through the whole history of Aristotelianism--and perhaps the ascription to Aristotle of the De mundo ("On the Universe"), a cosmological treatise of the 1st century BC, which found favour with all of the different traditions until the 16th century.

In the 1st century BC Aristotle's "esoteric" writings were organized into a corpus and critically edited by Andronicus of Rhodes and other scholars. The edition was used by Nicholas of Damascus, a historian and philosopher, in an attempt to expound Aristotle's system. This may be viewed as the beginning of a new era of a scholarly and scholastic Aristotelianism in which Aristotle had to be taken as the basis for the acquisition of true knowledge in a number of fields. Individual works began to be commented and lectured upon; organized philosophical studies began to have as their introduction Aristotle's works on logic, especially the Categories. Thus the pattern was set for the next 17 centuries. Almost pure Aristotelianism, based on the "esoteric" works, lived on until the 4th century. Many scholars--the most eminent of them being Alexander of Aphrodisias, who from AD 195 held the Athenian chair of Aristotelian studies created by the Roman emperor Marcus Aurelius--provided the works on logic, ethics, metaphysics, natural philosophy, and psychology with detailed and penetrating commentaries meant for the specialist. The interpretation of Aristotle was for many generations molded by these scholars. Others--the greatest being Themistius, a professor in Constantinople in about AD 350--practically rewrote many of Aristotle's treatises in a more modern language and more readable style.

This new, scholarly Aristotelianism had established itself sufficiently as the philosophical and methodological frame of learning for it to be adopted, at least in part, by most men of culture--including Ptolemy, the greatest astronomer of antiquity, and Galen, the most eminent medical scientist.

 

9.2.2 Relationship to Neoplatonism.

Aristotle's works were adopted by the systematic builders of Neoplatonism in the 3rd century AD. Plotinus, the school's chief representative, followed Aristotle wherever he found a possibility of agreement or development, as he did in Aristotle's theory of the intellect. And Plotinus' pupil Porphyry, the first great harmonizer of Plato and Aristotle, provided the field of logic with a short introduction (Isagoge). The Isagoge, in fact, is only concerned with a simple and rather mechanical treatment of five concepts that had been much used by Aristotle. These were the concepts of genus, or kind (as animal is the genus, or kind, under which Socrates falls); species, or sort (Socrates is a man); differentia, or distinguishing characteristic (rationality distinguishes men from other members of the genus animal); property (being capable of laughter was said to be a "property" of men inasmuch as all and only men are capable of laughter); and accident, or characteristic in general (as it might be an accident of Socrates to be pale). This introduction soon became an integral part of the Organon (the logical works of Aristotle) and thus acquired undeserved Aristotelian authority in all schools for more than 1,500 years. From that time on, Aristotelianism became indissolubly tied up with Neoplatonism. (see also   definition by genus and differentia)

Neoplatonism dominated the school of Athens, where, apart from logic, Aristotle's writings were destined to be studied mainly as a basis for philosophical disputations--disputations in which the Platonic view was usually victorious. Scholars like Ammonius--a pupil of Proclus, the most accomplished systematizer of Neoplatonism, head of the Athenian school in the mid-5th century, and himself extremely well-versed in Aristotle--found Alexandria a considerably more attractive place for Aristotelian studies, in that it was tolerant of many views. There pagans and Christians coexisted and cooperated, and from there they carried Aristotelian learning to a number of other schools: Simplicius, a pupil of Ammonius who was inclined to Platonism, took it back to Athens and--when Justinian closed that pagan school in 529--to Persia; Sergius, a physician and Nestorian priest, carried it to the Christian schools of Syria; and Stephanus of Alexandria took it to Constantinople. The schools of Alexandria and Athens produced from about AD 475 to 545 the most intensive collection of Aristotelian commentaries, by scholars like Ammonius, philosophers of science like Simplicius, and philosopher-theologians like Philoponus (see also PLATONISM ).

Before the 5th century, Christian theology had been affected only marginally and indirectly by Aristotle. The elementary study of Aristotelian logic had proved indispensable for a disciplined training of theologians, and some of the concepts from Aristotle's Physics and Metaphysics that entered into the elaboration of this logic became equally essential for the rational formulation of points of dogma. The aforementioned five terms of Porphyry and the 10 categories of Aristotle were used or implied in the mystical theology of Pseudo-Dionysius (an unidentified 5th-century Christian Neoplatonist), which was to become one of the principal components of Christian speculation in the Greek, Oriental, and Latin schools. Descriptions of God and distinctions between the three Persons of the Trinity came to include, in an increasingly technical sense, the Aristotelian terms substance, essence, accident, form and matter, species and nature, quality, quantity, and property; these terms were not always used in a purely Aristotelian sense, however. In this way, as well as through the purely philosophical schools, Aristotelianism entered the first Greek Scholasticism of St. John of Damascus, an 8th-century doctor of the church. (see also   Christianity)

 

9.2.3 From the Byzantine renaissance to the 15th century.

The Byzantine scholarly renaissance in the 9th century included a revival of interest in Aristotle: the old books were rediscovered and reedited (the oldest manuscripts still existing today belong to this time). Photius, patriarch of Constantinople and a leading figure in that renaissance, included in his encyclopaedic works summaries of the elements of Aristotelian logic. More extensive scholarly activity resulted from the reestablishment of the Academy in Constantinople in the 11th and 12th centuries under the successive leadership of such men as Michael Psellus, an encyclopaedic philosopher; his student John Italus; Michael, the archbishop of Ephesus; and Eustratius, the metropolitan of Nicaea. At the Academy teaching and exegetical work went hand in hand; debates on the superiority of Plato or Aristotle and attacks on philosophy by the religious schools did not seriously weaken these activities. There was perhaps not much that was new in the understanding or the development of Aristotle's doctrine; but logic was no longer the only focal point of Aristotelian studies. Indeed, they covered, more widely than had been done in Alexandria, practically the whole corpus, including some work on Aristotle's political theory, on his ethics, and on his biology. In addition, there were philosophical debates similar to those taking place in the Latin schools; they were based on texts of Aristotle and treated such issues as the theory of universals and the logical structure of language. (see also   Byzantine Empire)

In the 13th and 14th centuries popularization and systematization--in an encyclopaedic or philosophical form--took the upper hand in the work of Nicephorus Blemmydes, George Pachymeres, and Theodore Metochites. At a time when Greek thought was being strongly influenced by the Latin tradition, especially by the work of Thomas Aquinas, the traditional debate on Plato and Aristotle took new forms. Aristotelianism appeared in the teaching of Barlaam the Calabrian, who sought to champion rationalism in faith; this was combated from a Platonic point of view by Nicephorus Gregoras. In the 15th century, when Greeks were becoming part of the Italian philosophical scene, Aristotelian rationalism was strongly defended by the upholders of Christian theology against such men as George Gemistus Plethon, who proposed a new universal religiosity tinged with an admiration for Plato and paganism. The victory in this intellectual battle went to the moderates like John Bessarion, Plethon's influential pupil, who, though he preferred Plato, admired Aristotle, translated his Metaphysics, and collected manuscripts of his works; he converted from the Greek (i.e., the Greek Orthodox) church to the Latin (i.e., what is now called the Roman Catholic) church, in which latter communion he became a cardinal.

9.3 The early Latin tradition.

The echoes of Aristotle's early writings in Cicero, a few signs of his indirect influence on other writers, and a more considerable contribution to post-Aristotelian logic in Apuleius, a Platonic philosopher who flourished in the 2nd century AD, are indications of the general cultural intercourse in this area between Latins and Greeks. The presence of Plotinus and Porphyry in Rome in the 3rd and early 4th centuries probably started the more serious interest in Aristotle there, of which the first results were, perhaps, Victorinus' adaptations in Latin of Porphyry's Isagoge and Aristotle's Categories. Logic was still the only part of Aristotle that had entered Latin culture when Themistius' teaching attracted the attention of Roman pagan circles in the 4th century.

Again, only the logical works of Aristotle, together with some extracts from Greek commentaries on them, seem to have reached the hands of Boethius, a Roman scholar and statesman of the early 6th century, when he was attempting to transmit to the Latins as much as he could of Greek learning. He translated these works and elaborated on the commentaries and on some other later texts of logic that are partly based on Aristotle. He acted primarily as a conduit, and some scholars are not prepared to ascribe to him interpretations and plans contained in the Latin works that bear his name. Even the plan of commenting on "as much of Aristotle as would come into his hands" and showing that Aristotle and Plato agreed was the traditional approach going back at least to Porphyry. Nothing remains to show where Boethius himself stood in judging Aristotle and the several parts of his philosophy. The same observations probably hold true with regard to Boethius' various theological treatises, in which the Aristotelian concepts that helped to organize the theology of the Trinity were unmistakably taken over from similar Greek treatises. A disproportionate value, however, was later attached to Boethius' own original contribution in both logic and theology; simply the fact that his name was connected with these texts made people in the Middle Ages ascribe to him the primary responsibility for their contents.

9.4 The Syriac, Arabic, and Jewish traditions.

The increased sense of linguistic and national identity and the religious movements of the 5th and 6th centuries such as Nestorianism (a heterodox doctrine that so stressed the distinction between the divine and human natures of Jesus Christ as to suggest that they belonged to two persons) and Monophysitism (a heterodox doctrine asserting that there is only one nature in Jesus Christ) led to the foundation of Syriac centres of studies in the Persian and Byzantine empires, especially at Edessa (now Urfa, Tur.) and Antioch. Proba and Sergius of Resaina were among those who contributed, through translations of the basic logical texts and commentaries on them, to the establishment of Aristotelian studies in these centres. At the time of the Arabic invasion of the Byzantine and Sasanian empires around 640, and for several generations afterward, these centres continued to grow in importance. Most notable was the great school of Kinnesrin, which was represented by such men as Severus Sebokht, who wrote on Aristotle's syllogisms; Jacob, bishop of Edessa, a theologian, grammarian, and translator; and Georgius, bishop of the Arabs, author of a commentary on the Organon. Interest remained, however, mainly confined to logic and its application to theology.

The Syrian Christians formed the philosophical and scientific intelligentsia when in the 9th century al- Ma`mun, the seventh 'Abbasid caliph, organized the Arabic centre of learning of the new Islamic empire in Baghdad. By then the Syrian scholars had acquired and translated most of Aristotle's works. They also then translated them into Arabic, both from the Syriac and directly from the Greek, and added many texts of commentators on Aristotle. In this way Hunayn ibn Ishaq, his son Ishaq, Abu Bishr Matta ibn Yunus, Yahya ibn 'Adi, and many other Syrians provided the basis for a brilliant philosophical activity in Arabic. The Syrians retained their own independent culture; as late as the 13th century their language was used by the converted Jew Bar Hebraeus, "Son of the Hebrew" (also known as Gregorius or Abu al-Faraj), an encyclopaedist, philosopher, and theologian, who expounded all the works of Aristotle in his Kethabha dhe-hewath hekhmetha (Book of the Cream of Wisdom), elaborating many sections on the basis of the Greek and Arabic Aristotelians. (see also   Islamic philosophy)

In the 9th century the Arab al- Kindi was the first notable scholar to use the Arabic language in a general introduction of mainly Aristotelian philosophy. In the following century the Turkish Muslim al- Farabi produced a more specialized study in which he commented upon and expounded the books of logic and attempted to establish the relationship between philosophy and Islam. It was through the writings of Avicenna and Averroës, however, that Aristotle's thought became an integral part of lay Arabic culture.

Early in the 11th century, the Arab Avicenna (Ibn Sina) made Aristotle's philosophy the foundation of an original system of his own. For this he also found inspiration in a group of Plotinian texts that had been translated into Arabic under the title "Theology of Aristotle." Aristotle became, in Avicenna's hands, a much more systematic and coherent thinker than he really had intended to be; problems and solutions that were, at best, hinted at by Aristotle (e.g., the distinction between essence and existence or the relation between possible and necessary existence) were among the distinctive marks of Avicenna's own work.

For the Spanish Arab Averroës (Ibn Rushd) in the 12th century, Aristotle was "the measure and model offered by nature to show the ultimate perfection of man." He held that philosophy, specifically Aristotelian philosophy, was and taught truth; revelation or revealed religion was a debased philosophy for the simple. Averroës dissected Aristotle's works, analyzing and reconstructing them with a fine scholarly and philosophical sense and an incredible wealth of information derived from previous Greek and Arabic philosophers. He elicited doctrines that are not easily apparent and made them in some cases more compelling than the texts themselves might allow, but he rarely forced his own views onto Aristotle without at least finding some support in the texts themselves. The doctrines concerning the mortality of the individual soul, the eternity of the world, and the existence of a single Mind for the whole human race to the exclusion of individual minds were key doctrines for Averroës; they had some basis--but not much--in the thought of Aristotle.

Until the 13th century, Jewish Aristotelianism developed within the Arabic culture of North Africa, Mesopotamia, and Spain. This work was carried out in the Arabic language and distinguished itself for its almost constant concern with the relation between philosophy and Judaism. Many Aristotelian concepts were considered and discussed by Isaac ben Solomon Israeli, a 10th-century Neoplatonist, in his Kitab al-hudud ("Book of Definitions") and Kitab al-ustuqusat ("Book of the Elements"). Form and matter were the basis of the metaphysical structure of the Neoplatonic system of Solomon ibn Gabirol, an 11th-century poet and philosopher known as Avicebron. A fully conscious plan of inserting Aristotle--or at least the Aristotle of al-Farabi and Avicenna--into the intellectual and spiritual life of Judaism was carried out by Abraham ibn Daud of Toledo in the mid-12th century. Moses Maimonides of Córdoba found a way of reconciling the claims of empirical knowledge with those of revelation, which places him into clear contrast with his contemporary Spaniard Averroës, and in so doing he provided a Jewish anticipation of Thomas Aquinas' Christian compromise. His proofs for the existence of God and his acceptance of a theory of creation from eternity were typical of his approach. From the 13th century onward philosophical works, particularly those of Averroës on Aristotle, were being translated into Hebrew; a vast Hebrew literature of "super-commentaries" (those on the works of Aristotle as commented on by Averroës) appeared, and independent works were also produced, notably by Levi ben Gershom (Gersonides), who was faithful to both Maimonides and Averroës. Soon after, however, the more orthodox tradition based upon the Bible and the Talmud prevailed. Aristotelian works by Jews and Hebrew versions of Averroës, translated into Latin, contributed their share to the Italian philosophical movement of the 16th century (see also JUDAISM: Jewish philosophy).

9.5 The later Latin tradition.

 

9.5.1 The discovery of Aristotle's works in the Latin West.

Before 1115 only the very short Categories and On Interpretation were known in Latin, and these two works circulated, from about 800, in a version by Boethius. By 1278 practically the whole of the Aristotelian corpus existed in translations from the Greek, and much of it had a wide circulation. Apart from three other works of logic in translations done by Boethius, which reappeared in about 1115, this wholesale discovery was the result of cultural contacts with Constantinople and a few other Greek centres and the personal initiative of a few scholars. Most notable and first of these was James of Venice, who was in Constantinople and translated the Posterior Analytics, Physics, On the Soul, Metaphysics, and several minor texts before or around 1150; other scholars translated anew or for the first time works on ethics, natural philosophy, and logic before 1200. With higher standards of linguistic scholarship, Robert Grosseteste, about 1240, revised and completed the translation of the Nicomachean Ethics and translated On the Heavens for the first time from the Greek. (see also   Middle Ages)

The Flemish translator William of Moerbeke, active between about 1255 and 1278, completed the Latin Aristotelian corpus; he was the first to translate the Politics and Poetics and to give a full and reliable translation of the books on animals; he also translated anew some books of natural philosophy, and he revised several of the older translations. About half of the works were also translated from the Arabic, mainly in Toledo by Gerard of Cremona and Michael Scot, between 1165 and 1230. With two or three exceptions, these translations came after those from the Greek; all had a much more limited circulation and influence. A considerable contribution to the knowledge of Aristotle came from the translations of the ancient commentaries; nearly all of these were made from the Greek.

The view that Aristotle came to be known in Latin by way of the Arabic scholars must be understood as true only in the sense that a number of Aristotelian doctrines--partly transformed in the process--spread in Latin circles from the works of such men as al-Farabi, Avicenna, and Albumazar before the texts of Aristotle were accessible or had been properly interpreted. Further, there is little truth in a view that in the Latin world in the Middle Ages Aristotle was seen in a Neoplatonic light because Plotinian and Proclan texts translated from the Arabic--namely the Theologia Aristotelis ("Theology of Aristotle") and the Liber de causis ("Book of Causes")--were ascribed to him.

 

9.5.2 From the 9th through the mid-13th century.

The study of Porphyry's Isagoge, of Aristotle's Categories and On Interpretation, and of theological texts containing Aristotelian elements formed the basis, from the 9th century onward, of logical methodology (dialectic) in a wide number of fields. When applied to problems concerning the Trinity or the Eucharist, or in general to problems concerning individuality and universality of concepts and things, dialectic was perceived as a powerful instrument for clarifying faith or--on the opposite side--for endangering it. For Abelard, the first great Aristotelian of the Middle Ages, dialectic was an essential method for analysis and the discovery of truth. As part of his study, he produced an illuminating account of the linguistic, mental, and objective aspects of universals on the basis of Aristotelian doctrines. Soon thereafter, new developments of Aristotle's theory of language and logic took place, partly as a result of the recently acquired knowledge of his Sophistical Refutations.

At the same time, in the later 12th century and during the beginning of the 13th century, Aristotle's physics, cosmology, and metaphysics began to attract attention through the Latin texts both of Arabic works on science and philosophy and of Aristotle's own works, and did so mainly among scientists of the famous medical school at Salerno and among the English philosophers. Around 1190 Alfred of Sareshel used the new texts in his treatise De motu cordis ("On the Movement of the Heart"). Between 1210 and 1235 Robert Grosseteste commented on Aristotle's Physics and drew on various aspects of Aristotle's natural philosophy for his own scientific and philosophical treatises, and around 1245 Roger Bacon commented on the Physics and part of the Metaphysics. It would be wrong, however, to try to find in this scholarship the origin of modern experimental science, which is rather to be found in the study of ancient and more recent mechanics, medicine, and technology or in original inventiveness. (see also   nature, philosophy of, scholasticism)

The introduction of the new Aristotle met with difficulties in Paris. The impact of non-Christian Aristotelian and Arabic philosophy engendered fears, doubts, and suspicions. Although the masters at Paris were free to teach Aristotle's logic, which was value free, and although no obstacle was put in the way of lecturing on any of Aristotle's works at the universities of Oxford and Toulouse, in the first part of the 13th century the ecclesiastical authorities at Paris imposed a ban on lectures relating to the physics, the metaphysics, and the psychology of Aristotle and his commentators. While this ban succeeded in slowing down some activities it also quickened reactions and aroused strong curiosity; the very demand for some kind of censorship of the works led to more intimate study of them. Certainly by the 1240s the prohibition against teaching Aristotle had become a dead letter at Paris, as can be seen from the fact that Roger Bacon was then commenting on the "dangerous" Physics and Metaphysics. Shortly thereafter, before 1255, all of Aristotle's philosophical treatises then known had become a required part of the Parisian Master of Arts curriculum, and, around the same time, Albertus Magnus--committed though he was, as a Dominican friar, to safeguarding the purity of faith and dogma--made Aristotle's works an indissoluble part of philosophical and scientific literature in the Latin world. Albertus Magnus announced it as his intention to make all of Aristotle's natural philosophy "intelligible to the Latins." His vast encyclopaedia of secular knowledge and wisdom consisted of an analytical exposition of Aristotle's thought combined with all the information and interpretations that Albertus had gathered from other, mainly Arabic, sources or that he had gained as the product of his own extensive research and speculation. Faced with the danger of being accused of following Aristotle against church dogma, he asserted: "I expound, I do not endorse, Aristotle."

The approach of Albertus' pupil, Thomas Aquinas, to Aristotle was that of a scholar. He wrote numerous detailed commentaries on a variety of Aristotle's works, including the Physics, Metaphysics, Ethics, and Politics; he analyzed the structure of every section of most works; he tried to discover their organization and to follow the arguments; and he was careful to obtain the best texts and to get from them the genuine meaning. Above all, Thomas Aquinas drew heavily on Aristotle's thought in composing his own masterwork, the Summa theologiae. He respected Aristotle's authoritativeness and credited him with reasonableness, even when that was not explicitly justified. Sometimes he drew inferences that went beyond Aristotle's own conclusions, and he allowed himself considerable freedom whenever Aristotle had left loose ends in his attempts to solve difficulties. At these points he often went his own way, without ascribing the new steps to Aristotle but without feeling that he was going against him. Compromises followed; for example, he stepped beyond Aristotle when he argued that the individual soul, although remaining essentially and indissolubly the form of the individual body, is separable from it and immortal. Aristotle's account was stretched almost to the breaking point but it was not transformed. Beyond that point Thomas Aquinas was not a Christian Aristotle but a man of faith and dogma; he divorced himself from Aristotle when necessary and approached closer to St. Augustine, to the Neoplatonists, or to Avicenna.

 

9.5.3 From the late 13th century through the 15th century.

The suspicion that reading Aristotle might lead to heresy became stronger when the closer study of his texts and of Averroës' interpretations enhanced the admiration for The Philosopher and increased the following of The Commentator, as these two thinkers were known respectively. Siger de Brabant was the most redoubtable of many Averroistic Aristotelians. What came to be called Averroism was in fact a tendency to accept genuine or consistent Aristotelian tenets, particularly those concerning the eternity of the world, the unity of the intellect, and the ability of humans to achieve happiness on earth. Ecclesiastical condemnations of propositions considered false or dangerous and threats against the holders of doctrines implied by these propositions gave a more definite status to the Averroists, although many propositions condemned at Paris and Oxford in 1270 and 1277 had nothing to do with Aristotle and little with Averroës. The effect of the condemnations soon became visible: it took the form of a separation between the teaching of "philosophy" in the faculty of arts and the teaching of "truth" in the faculty of theology. This separation became rigid, with the ambiguous result that two "truths"--truth of coherence in philosophical contexts and revealed truth--were thought to coexist.

At the turn of the century, however, Dante's powerful poetical vision could still merge the Averroists' Aristotle, who claimed that natural truths were self-sufficient, and Thomas Aquinas' Aristotle, who endorsed many of the truths of faith. For Dante, as for Averroës, Aristotle was the embodiment of total human knowledge--"the master of them that know." A remarkable index of Dante's commitment to Aristotelianism is the fact that he placed Siger de Brabant, by that time condemned for his Aristotelian heresy, in Paradise. In Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Dante found moral guidance (he even said that this work "showed man his true happiness"), and in Aristotle's scientific books he found the key to understanding the workings of nature. In some aspects of Averroës' theory of a universal human Intellect combined with the Stoic-Aristotelian principle that all men are by nature citizens of one city, he found the basis of the Empire, seeing it as the one polity (civilitas) for the whole human race.

The 14th century was no less Aristotelian than the 13th. Some scholars have indeed claimed that Aristotelianism collapsed, but such an assertion does not take into account the non-Aristotelian components of previous philosophies and the permanent acceptance of Aristotelian doctrines in the new ones. Form, matter, causality, and the idea of a universe in which events occurred with regularity but were not necessitated provided the Aristotelian frame of the system of Duns Scotus. The nominalism (or "terminism") of William of Ockham, an English Franciscan, his rejection of "useless entities," his metaphysics of a world of individual self-contained things, and his conceptualism gave neat, though extreme, expression to Aristotle's theory of language, the economy of nature, and the primacy of individuals in existence and of universals in intellectual knowledge. He followed Aristotle closely in his views on the scientific coordination of notions. He was more faithful to Aristotle than either Thomas Aquinas or Averroës when he said that Aristotle did not give a clear lead on the question of the immortality of the soul. The various schools of Scholastic philosophy--Thomism, Scotism, Ockhamism--that asserted themselves in the 14th century and that lived on had a common Aristotelian basis, but they had different ways of interpreting it (see also PHILOSOPHICAL SCHOOLS AND DOCTRINES, WESTERN: Scholasticism ; CHRISTIANITY: Christian philosophy ).

Averroistic Aristotelianism flourished in this century in connection with, or independently of, the other trends. The Italian medical faculties at Bologna and Padua were lively centres of logical and philosophical studies; for example, Peter of Abano, a professor of medicine at Padua who had been trained at Paris, pushed Aristotle's cosmology to the brink of determinism in human affairs and used his logic to suggest that Christ's death was only apparent. Political science, which had been a field for lofty speculations or restrained exercises in the analysis and exposition of texts, became important for those who practiced politics and those who wanted to satisfy, under the aegis of Aristotle's doctrine, the potentialities of human beings for happiness. John of Paris wanted France to be self-sufficient, self-controlling, and without interference from the pope; John of Jandun, a successor of Siger de Brabant, upheld Aristotle's Politics in all its worldliness; and Marsilius of Padua, John of Jandun's friend in Paris, followed Aristotle in his insistence that government had no supernatural origins but arose naturally from the needs of the governed and that priests should be considered in the same way as members of a guild in a city, without special privileges.

Perhaps with less attachment to the details of Aristotle's doctrines and with a keen critical sense, the Mertonians, a group of logician-philosophers based in Merton College, Oxford (e.g., Thomas Bradwardine, William of Heytesbury), and encyclopaedists, scientists, and philosophers in France (e.g., Jean Buridan and Nicholas Oresme) made laborious efforts to express science wholly in terms of mathematics, to quantify changes in quality, and to determine the nature of continuity in movement and the acceleration and speed of falling bodies. Their starting points were the Physics and the other texts of Aristotle. In a similar (almost mathematical) spirit, many of the same men carried logic even further than Ockham had done into the fields of logical calculus, paradoxes, and sophisms. Thus one may say that Aristotle was not abandoned but expanded.

9.6 Modern developments.

 

9.6.1 From the Renaissance to the 18th century.

In the 15th century Italy became the focal point at which various forms of Aristotelianism converged. Certain links between Italian universities and religious schools and the University of Paris had already flourished for a long time. In the late 14th century Paolo Nicoletti (Paulus Venetus) returned from Oxford to Padua after having absorbed the new logic and physics of the Mertonians and the radical nominalism of Ockham and after having increased his acquaintance with the French Averroistic trend; works by the Englishmen and by Paolo were textbooks in Italian universities for many generations. At the end of the century a number of Spanish and Italian Jews were passing on, in Latin, still more texts of Averroës on Aristotle, as well as the Jews' own recent contributions to Aristotelian learning.

A more spectacular contribution of books, linguistic and didactic competence, and stimulating debates came with an influx of Greek scholars into the Western sphere. They were attracted by the humanists' craving for classical learning, the theological discussions between Orthodox and Roman Catholic leaders, and the relative freedom offered by the Republic of Venice and by Florence to those who were taking refuge from Turkish domination. Many manuscripts were taken to Italy, and many were transcribed in Italy by the Greeks, who also taught the Greek language to the Italian scholars. An editorial masterpiece by Aldus Manutius, an early printer, publisher, and editor, at the end of the 15th century made accessible to many almost the complete Greek corpus of Aristotle's works. A great number of Greek and Latin scholars--such as Bessarion, John Argyropoulos, Leonardo Bruni, and Lorenzo Valla--produced new translations of those texts; others translated many works on Aristotle previously unknown in Latin.

As soon as printing had been established (that is to say, by the late 15th century), editorial activity was directed to the production of many complete as well as partial editions of the Latin versions of Aristotle and Averroës in both their older and newer versions from the Greek, the Arabic, and the Hebrew. At the universities of Padua and Bologna and at Ferrara and Venice, Averroists such as Agostino Nifo and Nicoletto Vernia and independent interpreters such as Pietro Pomponazzi were dominating the philosophical scene. For Pomponazzi, Aristotle, whether right or wrong, had to be studied directly by way of his own works and not by way of his interpreters; yet he did not think that Aristotle had a monopoly on knowledge, and for this reason his mistakes concerning facts needed to be exposed.

There were others who followed Aristotle in his vast scientific achievements or searched his works for a clearer formulation of scientific methods. It was this scientific spirit that kept alive the interest in Aristotle's methodology and in his philosophy of nature down to the time, in the 17th century, when William Harvey, the English physician who discovered the circulation of the blood, was lecturing on Aristotle's books on animals and Galileo was writing on science and logic.

In a less apparent form, Aristotelianism, still strongly entrenched in most European schools, continued to have its effect on the most modern philosophers. The methodology of Francis Bacon, English philosopher, scientist, and statesman, grew out of it, and his basic metaphysical concepts were borrowed from Aristotle, although he was critical of the distorted version of Aristotelianism in the academic circles of his day. The Polish astronomer Copernicus was still attached to the perfection of circular movements. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, the German Rationalist and mathematician, not only admired Aristotle's logic but also built his own metaphysics of individuals ("monads") around the theory of matter and form. Like Aristotle, political theorists such as Jean Bodin in France carried on their inquiries into the nature of the state by studying existing organizations and their natural backgrounds.

In the literary field, Aristotle's Poetics, practically unknown until 1500, was now read and analyzed in both the Greek and Latin versions; its doctrines were compared and partly made to harmonize with the then-prevailing views of the ancient Roman poet Horace, and Aristotle's view that art imitates nature prevailed for many over the conflicting theory that stressed the creativity of the poet. The doctrine of the unities of action, place, and time--though actually a later development resulting from forced interpretations of Aristotle--ruled over the work of many writers of tragedies (e.g., Gian Giorgio Trissino in Italy, Jean Racine and Pierre Corneille in France, and, to a certain extent, Goethe in Germany). Many critics (including the English critics from Sir Philip Sidney to Matthew Arnold) accepted those rules, although few English poets--the great exception was John Milton--welcomed them. A lesser influence was exercised by Aristotle's Rhetoric outside the field of systematic theory. (see also   aesthetics, literary criticism, poetry)

Scholasticism in these centuries belonged to the history of Aristotelianism. All over western and central Europe and also in Spanish America the continuance of Scholasticism ensured that higher education remained generally within an Aristotelian framework. Remarkable work was produced by Scholastics in the fields of commentaries and of detailed interpretation; Pedro de Fonseca, the "Portuguese Aristotle," in the 16th century and Sylvester Maurus, author of short but pithy commentaries on all of Aristotle's works, in Rome in the 17th are noteworthy examples. Insofar as the different Scholasticisms were living and interesting philosophical movements, however, they had more to do with newer philosophies than with Aristotle.

Martin Luther's rebellion against Rome, on the other hand, involved a rebellion against Scholastic philosophy and its distorted Aristotelian structure, although not against Aristotle. In fact, when Luther's follower Philipp Melanchthon undertook to reorganize the curriculum for higher education, a more genuine, humanistic Aristotle emerged as the great master of philosophy, independent of theology. Once again, as in the early 13th century in Paris, Aristotle took pride of place, particularly in the realms of logic and ethics, and to a lesser extent in metaphysics and natural philosophy.

The anti-Aristotelianism of the 16th to 18th century touched only a small part of the real Aristotle. Partly it was a reaction against Scholasticism, as though this had faithfully represented Aristotle's own philosophy. Thus, Aristotle was wrongly accused of extreme formalism, irresponsible use of syllogisms consisting of empty or irrelevant concepts, a multiplication of pseudo-real entities, and the application of "scientific" methods to facts that could be vouched for only by faith. For other critics the whole of Aristotle's canon stood condemned because of his unsatisfactory account of local movement and the consequences it had in the areas of mechanics, dynamics, cosmology, and astronomy. His downfall in the 17th century was the result, above all, of his failure to create, in the 4th century BC, a language that allowed him to describe the forms of things and events (i.e., their knowable aspects) in mathematical formulas and of his failure to lay sufficient stress, in his philosophy of experience, on the need for experiments. (see also   Empiricism)

 

9.6.2 The 19th and 20th centuries.

The anti-Aristotelian movement was countered mainly by historical and philological scholarship. As Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg, a German philosopher, saw it, Aristotle's personality and works must be known as exactly as possible because he provides the indispensable historical basis of any serious philosophy. Such a type of study had declined after the great achievements of the 16th century. After the work done between the first new learned edition of the collected Greek texts of Aristotle by J.G. Buhle (1791-93) and a vast collection of all documentary material in the Aristoteles-Archiv at Berlin (which began in 1965), there is little, if anything, that remains to be discovered concerning the original and deteriorated forms of Aristotle's traditional corpus. A monumental edition sponsored by the Prussian Academy from 1831 to 1870 became the basis for almost innumerable critical editions of individual works. A rich crop of fragments, which were identified and edited in the last centuries, brought to light previously almost unknown aspects of Aristotle's early activity. And in 1890 a papyrus was discovered in Egypt that contained most of the otherwise lost Constitution of Athens. European and American academies have sponsored the editing of ancient and medieval commentaries and translations in Greek, Latin, Arabic, and Hebrew. Historical, philological, and philosophical exegesis has explored in great detail the contents and background of most of Aristotle's writings. Translations of all the works into English, German, and French and of many of them into most of the other European languages as well as into Hebrew, Arabic, and Japanese have made Aristotle widely accessible. Historians of ideas have investigated Aristotle's relationship to Plato and to the Greece of his day, his influence in following ages, and his own philosophical development.

Philosophical Aristotelianism has been mainly confined to the German schools established by Trendelenburg and Franz Brentano. Trendelenburg was concerned to effect a revaluation of Aristotle's metaphysics in the face of German idealism; he had a measure of influence in the United States on such thinkers as Felix Adler, George Sylvester Morris, and John Dewey. Aristotle's theories of being and knowledge formed the point of departure for Brentano's "descriptive psychology" and his doctrine of human experience, and they also contributed to Edmund Husserl's phenomenology. Outside Germany, J.-G.-F.-L. Ravaisson-Mollien, a spiritualist philosopher, and Sir David Ross, editor and translator of Aristotle's works, acknowledged a debt to Aristotle, respectively, for their metaphysics and ethics; and the reestablishment of Thomas Aquinas, by Pope Leo XIII in 1879, as the great doctor of the church increased the interest in Aristotle and in his influence on the history of Christian thought. Contemporary philosophy in the Anglo-Saxon world is often associated with a keen interest in Aristotle (nor is he entirely neglected in other philosophical traditions), and the name of the Aristotelian Society (London) reflects the view that good philosophy must be practiced in the spirit of Aristotle. (see also   Christianity)

¡¡

°³¿ä

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º (Aristoteles), (¿µ)Aristotle. BC 384 ¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾Æ ±Ùó Į۵ðÄÉ ½ºÅ¸±â·Î½º~BC 322 ±×¸®½º ¿¡¿ìº¸ÀÌ¾Æ Ä®Å°½º. °í´ë ±×¸®½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀÚ¡¤°úÇÐÀÚ.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º, ±×¸®½º ¿ø»óÀ» º¸°í ÄÚ ºÎºÐÀ» º¹¿øÇÑ ·Î¸¶ÀÇ ...
ÇöóÅæ°ú ÇÔ²² ±×¸®½º ÃÖ°íÀÇ »ç»ó°¡·Î ²ÅÈ÷´Â Àι°·Î ¼­¾çÁö¼º»çÀÇ ¹æÇâ°ú ³»¿ë¿¡ ¸Å¿ì Å« ¿µÇâÀ» ³¢ÃÆ´Ù. ±×°¡ ¼¼¿î öÇаú °úÇÐÀÇ Ã¼°è´Â ¿©·¯ ¼¼±â µ¿¾È Áß¼¼ ±×¸®½ºµµ±³ »ç»ó°ú ½ºÄݶóÁÖÀÇ »ç»óÀ» µÞ¹ÞħÇß´Ù. 17¼¼±â¸»±îÁö ¼­¾ç ¹®È­´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÁÖÀÇ¿´À¸¸ç ¼ö¹é ³â¿¡ °ÉÄ£ °úÇÐÇõ¸í µÚ¿¡µµ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÁÖÀÇ´Â ¼­¾ç»ç»ó¿¡ ¿©ÀüÈ÷ »Ñ¸® ±í°Ô ³²¾Æ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¿¬±¸ÇÑ Áö½Ä ºÐ¾ß´Â ¹°¸®ÇС¤È­ÇС¤ »ý¹°ÇС¤µ¿¹°ÇС¤½É¸®ÇС¤Á¤Ä¡ÇС¤À±¸®ÇС¤³í¸®ÇС¤ÇüÀÌ»óÇС¤¿ª»ç¡¤¹®¿¹À̷С¤¼ö»çÇÐ µî ¸Å¿ì ´Ù¾çÇÏ´Ù. °¡Àå Å« ¾÷ÀûÀº Çü½Ä³í¸®Çаú µ¿¹°ÇÐ ºÐ¾ßÀÇ ¿¬±¸ÀÌ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ µ¿¹°ÇÐÀº ÀÌÁ¦ ³°Àº °ÍÀÌ µÇ¾úÁö¸¸, 19¼¼±â±îÁö´Â °üÂû°ú ÀÌ·Ð ¸é¿¡¼­ ±×ÀÇ ¿¬±¸¸¦ ³Ñ¾î¼± »ç¶÷ÀÌ ¾ø¾ú´Ù. öÇÐ ºÐ¾ß¿¡¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾ÆÁ÷µµ »ì¾Æ ÀÖ´Ù. »ï´Ü³í¹ý·ÐÀº ÀÌÁ¦ Çü½Ä³í¸®ÇÐÀÇ ÀÛÀº ºÎºÐÀÏ »ÓÀÌÁö¸¸, ±×ÀÇ À±¸®ÇС¤Á¤Ä¡ÇС¤ÇüÀÌ»óÇС¤°úÇÐöÇÐ µîÀº Çö´ë öÇÐÀÚµé »çÀÌ¿¡¼­µµ ³íÀǵǰí ÀÖ´Ù.

»ý¾Ö

¾Æ¹öÁö ´ÏÄÚ¸¶ÄÚ½º´Â Çʸ®Æ÷½º 2¼¼ÀÇ ¾Æ¹öÁöÀÌÀÚ ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º ´ë¿ÕÀÇ ÇҾƹöÁöÀÎ ¾Æ¹ÎŸ½º 3¼¼ÀÇ ½ÃÀÇ(ã´ì¢)¿´´Ù. ´ç½Ã ÀǼúÀº °¡¾÷À» ÀÕ´Â ÀüÅëÀû Á÷¾÷À̾ú±â ¶§¹®¿¡ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºµµ ÀǼúÀ» ¹è¿üÀ» °¡´É¼ºÀÌ Å©´Ù. Èʳ¯ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¼¼¿î Çб³ÀÎ ¸®ÄÉÀ̿¿¡¼­´Â ÀǼú°ú ½ÇÁ¦ ÀÇ·áÇàÀ§¸¦ ¿¬±¸ÇÑ °ÍÀ¸·Î ¾Ë·ÁÁ® ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ¿Í °°ÀÌ ¾î¸± ¶§ºÎÅÍ ÀǼú°ú ¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾ÆÀÇ ±ÃÁ¤»ýȰÀ» Á¢ÇÑ Å¿¿¡ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â »ý¹°ÇÐÀÇ ¿µÇâÀÌ °­ÇÑ Ã¶Çлç»óÀ» ³»³õ¾Ò°í, ¿ÕÀÚµé°ú ±ÃÁ¤¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ±íÀº Çø¿À°¨À» ¿©·¯ ¹ø Ç¥ÇöÇß´Ù.

Á¦1±â(¾ÆÅ׳×ÀÇ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀÌ¾Æ ½ÃÀý)

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¾î¸± ¶§ ¾Æ¹öÁö°¡ Á×ÀÚ Ä£Ã´À¸·Î ÃßÁ¤µÇ´Â ÇÁ·ÎÅ©¼¼³ë½º°¡ ÈİßÀÎÀÌ µÇ¾ú°í, ÇÁ·ÎÅ©¼¼³ë½º´Â BC 367³â ±×¸¦ ¾ÆÅ׳׿¡ ÀÖ´Â ÇöóÅæÀÇ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ƿ¡ º¸³Â´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ±×°÷¿¡¼­ 20³â µ¿¾È ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ÀÌ ±â°£Àº ±×ÀÇ ÁöÀû ¼ºÀåÀÇ Á¦1±â¿´À¸¸ç, ÇöóÅæ°ú ±×ÀÇ µ¿·áµéÀÇ ¿µÇâÀ» Å©°Ô ¹ÞÀº ½Ã±â¿´´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â Ʋ¸²¾øÀÌ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ÆÀÇ ¸ðµç Ȱµ¿ ¿µ¿ª¿¡ °ü½ÉÀ» °¡Á³À» °ÍÀÌ´Ù. ¶§¶§·Î ¼ö»çÇÐ °øºÎ¿¡µµ ¸ôµÎÇß´Ù°í ¾Ë·ÁÁ® ÀÖÀ¸¸ç, ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀÌ¾Æ¿Í °æÀïÇÑ À̼ÒÅ©¶óÅ×½º ÇÐÆÄ¿¡ ¸Â¼­ ±ÛÀ» ¾²±âµµ Çß´Ù. BC 348(¶Ç´Â 347)³â ÇöóÅæÀÌ Á×ÀÚ ±×ÀÇ Á¶Ä« ½ºÆä¿ì½ÃÆ÷½º°¡ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾Ƹ¦ À̲ø¾ú°í ±×µÚ °ð ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾ÆÅ׳׸¦ ¶°³µ´Ù. ¾ÆÅ׳׸¦ ¶°³­ µ¿±â´Â ÇöóÅæÀÇ ÈİèÀÚ°¡ µÇÁö ¸øÇÑ ºÒ¸¸ ¶§¹®À̶ó´Â ÇØ¼®ÀÌ ÀÖÀ¸³ª ÀÌ ÇØ¼®Àº ±Ù°Å°¡ ¾ø´Ù. ¿Ö³ÄÇÏ¸é ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¿ÜÁöÀÎÀ̾úÀ¸¹Ç·Î óÀ½ºÎÅÍ ÇÐÆÄÀÇ ¿ìµÎ¸Ó¸®°¡ µÉ ÀÚ°ÝÀÌ ¾ø¾ú±â ¶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù. ¿ÀÈ÷·Á Çʸ®Æ÷½º ¿ÕÀÌ BC 348³â ±×¸®½º µµ½Ã±¹°¡ ¿Ã¸°Å佺¸¦ ³ë·«ÁúÇÑ µÚ¿¡ ÀϾ ¾ÆÅ׳×ÀÇ ¹Ý(Úã)¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾Æ °¨Á¤ ¶§¹®À̶ó´Â ÇØ¼®ÀÌ ´õ ±×·² µíÇÏ´Ù. ¾ÆÅ׳׸¦ 12³â µ¿¾È ¶°³ª ÀÖ¾ú´ø Å¿ÀÎÁö ±×´Â ÇöóÅæÀÇ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ÆÀÇ µ¿·áµéº¸´Ù ¿©ÇàÀ» ÇÔ²² ÇÑ »ç¶÷µé, ƯÈ÷ Á¦ÀÚÀÌÀÚ µ¿·áÀÎ ¿¡·¹¼Ò½ºÀÇ Å׿ÀÇÁ¶ó½ºÅ佺¸¦ ´õ ³ôÀÌ Æò°¡Çß´Ù.

Á¦2±â(¿©Çà)

¿¡°Ô ÇØÀÇ ¾Æ½Ã¾Æ ÂÊ¿¡ »õ·Î °Ç¼³µÈ µµ½Ã ¾Æ¼Ò½º¿¡¼­´Â ±×¸®½ºÀÇ ¿ëº´ Ãâ½ÅÀÎ ¾ÆÅ¸¸£³×¿À½ºÀÇ Ç츣¸ÞÀ̾ƽº°¡ Æä¸£½Ã¾Æ ±ºÁÖµéÀÇ ºÎÇÏ ½ÅºÐÀ¸·Î Ãâ¹ßÇÏ¿© ¼Ò¾Æ½Ã¾Æ ºÏ¼­ºÎ Áö¹æÀÇ ÀçÁ¤Àû¡¤Á¤Ä¡Àû Áö¹è±ÇÀ» Àå¾ÇÇß´Ù. Ç츣¸ÞÀ̾ƽº´Â ¾ÆÅ׳×ÀÇ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾Ƹ¦ ¹æ¹®ÇÑ µÚ ±×¸®½ºÀÇ ±Ô¹ü°ú öÇÐÀ» ¾Æ½Ã¾Æ Áö¹æ¿¡ ÀüÆÄÇϱâ À§ÇØ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀÌ¾Æ ºÐ¿øÀ» ¼¼¿ì±â·Î °á½ÉÇϰí ÇöóÅæÀÇ Á¦ÀÚ 2¸íÀ» º¸³»´Þ¶ó°í ¿äûÇß´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â Ä®Äɵ·ÀÇ Å©¼¼³ëÅ©¶óÅ×½º¿Í ÇÔ²² ¾Æ¼Ò½º·Î °¬´Ù. ÀÌ ½Ã±â¿¡ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¡´Á¤Ä¡ÇÐ Politica¡µ Á¦7±ÇÀÇ 12°³ ÀåÀ» ¾´ µíÇÏ´Ù. ÀÌ ±Û¿¡¼­ öÇаú Á¤Ä¡ÇÐÀÇ °ü°è¸¦ ¼³¸íÇϸ鼭, µµ½Ã±¹°¡(Æú¸®½º)ÀÇ ÃÖ°í ¸ñÀûÀº öÇÐÀû »ýȰÀ» ÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â »ç¶÷µé¿¡°Ô ±×·¯ÇÑ Á¶°ÇÀ» ¸¶·ÃÇØÁÖ´Â °ÍÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ±×¸®°í ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ »ýȰÀ» ÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â »ç¶÷Àº ±×¸®½ºÀλÓÀÌ¸ç µû¶ó¼­ ±×¸®½ºÀÎÀº ºñ(Þª)±×¸®½ºÀÎÀ» ³ë¿¹·Î »ï¾Æ ºñõÇÑ ÀÏÀ» ½Ãų ÀÚ°ÝÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. °°Àº ½Ã±â¿¡ Áö±ÝÀº ³²¾Æ ÀÖÁö ¾ÊÀº ¡´¿Õ±Ç¿¡ °üÇÏ¿© On Kingship¡µ¸¦ ½è°í, ÀÌ Ã¥¿¡¼­ ÇöóÅæ°ú ´Þ¸® öÇÐÀÚ¿Í ¿ÕÀÇ ±â´ÉÀ» ºÐ¸íÇÏ°Ô ³ª´©¾ú´Ù. "¿ÕÀÌ Ã¶ÇÐÀÚ°¡ µÇ´Â °ÍÀº ÇÊ¿äÇÏÁö ¾ÊÀ» »Ó ¾Æ´Ï¶ó À¯ÀÍÇÏÁöµµ ¾Ê´Ù. ¿ÀÈ÷·Á ¿ÕÀº ÂüµÈ öÇÐÀÚµéÀÇ Ãæ¾ðÀ» µé¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù. ±×·¡¾ß ¿ÕÀº Àڱ⠿ձ¹À» ÁÁÀº ¸»ÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ÁÁÀº ÇൿÀ¸·Î °¡µæ ä¿ï ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù."

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ÈİßÀÚ Ç츣¸ÞÀ̾ƽº¿Í ÁÁÀº °ü°è¸¦ À¯ÁöÇßÀ¸¸ç ±×ÀÇ Á¶Ä«µþ ÇÇÆ¼¾Æ½º¿Í °áÈ¥ÇÏ¿© µþÀ» ¾ò¾ú´Ù. ¡´Á¤Ä¡ÇСµ¿¡´Â ÀÌ»óÀûÀÎ °áÈ¥ ³ªÀ̸¦ ³²ÆíÀº 37¼¼, ¾Æ³»´Â 18¼¼·Î ±ÔÁ¤ÇÑ ´ë¸ñÀÌ Àִµ¥, À̶§ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ³ªÀ̰¡ 37¼¼¿´´Ù. ÇÇÆ¼¾Æ½º°¡ 18¼¼¿´´ÂÁö´Â ºÐ¸íÇÏÁö ¾Ê´Ù. ÇÇÆ¼¾Æ½º´Â ¿À·¡ »ìÁö ¸øÇß°í ±×³à°¡ Á×Àº µÚ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â Ç츣Çʸ®½º¿Í ÇÔ²² »ì¾ÒÀ¸¸ç ¾Æµé ´ÏÄÚ¸¶ÄÚ½º¸¦ ¾ò¾ú´Ù. ¾Æ¼Ò½º ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ƿ¡¼­ 3³âÀ» º¸³½ µÚ ±ÙóÀÇ ·¹½ºº¸½º ¼¶À¸·Î ¿Å°Ü ¼öµµ ¹ÌÆ¿·¹³×¿¡ Á¤ÂøÇß´Ù. À̰÷¿¡¼­ Ä£±¸ Å׿ÀÇÁ¶ó½ºÅ佺¿Í ÇÔ²² ¾ÆÅ׳×ÀÇ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾Ƹ¦ º»¶° öÇÐ ÇÐÆÄ¸¦ ¼¼¿ü´Ù. ±×¸®°í »ý¹°ÇÐÀ¸·Î °ü½ÉÀÇ ÃÊÁ¡À» µ¹·Á ¼±±¸ÀûÀÎ ¿¬±¸¸¦ Çß´Ù. ±×´Â »ý¹°ÇÐÀ» ¿¬±¸Çϸ鼭 »õ·Î¿î À¯ÇüÀÇ Àΰú°ü°è, Áï ¸ñÀû·ÐÀû Àΰú°ü°è¿¡ ÁÖ¸ñÇß´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º¿¡ µû¸£¸é ½Ä¹°°ú µ¿¹° µî ÀÚ¿¬ÀÇ »ý¸íü´Â ÀÚ¿¬Àû ¸ñÇ¥ ¶Ç´Â ¸ñÀûÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖÀ¸¸ç »ý¸íüÀÇ ±¸Á¶¿Í ¼ºÀåÀº ÀÌ ¸ñÀûÀ» ¾Ë¾Æ¾ß ÃæºÐÈ÷ ¼³¸íÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ »ý¹°Çп¡¼­´Â ÀϹÝÀûÀ¸·Î ¸ñÀû·Ð°ú ÀÌ·ÐÀÌ ¸ðµÎ Áß¿äÇÏÁö¸¸ Àû¾îµµ ¿øÄ¢ÀûÀ¸·Î´Â ÀÌ·ÐÀÌ Ç×»ó °üÂû¿¡ Á¾¼ÓµÈ´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¡´µ¿¹°ÀÇ ¹ß»ý¿¡ °üÇÏ¿© On the Generation of Animals¡µ¿¡¼­ ¹úÀÇ ¹ß»ý ¾ç½Ä¿¡ ´ëÇØ Àß ¸ð¸¥´Ù°í °í¹éÇϸ鼭 ´ÙÀ½°ú °°ÀÌ ¸»Çß´Ù. "»ç½ÇÀÌ ÃæºÐÈ÷ ¹àÇôÁö¸é ½Å·Ú¸¦ ¹Þ¾Æ¾ß ÇÏ´Â °ÍÀº ÀÌ·ÐÀ̶ó±âº¸´Ù´Â °üÂûÀ̸ç, ÀÌ·ÐÀº °üÂû »ç½Ç¿¡ ÀÇÇØ È®ÁõµÇ¾î¾ß¸¸ ½Å·Ú¸¦ ¾òÀ» ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù."

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ½Ä¹°°ú µ¿¹°ÀÇ »ýȰÀ» ¿¬±¸Çϸ鼭 ¿µÈ¥°ú À°Ã¼ÀÇ °ü°èµµ °íÂûÇß´Ù. ¡´¿µÈ¥¿¡ °üÇÏ¿© De anima¡µ¿¡¼­ ±×´Â ¿µÈ¥ÀÌ µ¶¸³ÀûÀ¸·Î Á¸ÀçÇÏ´Â ½ÇüÀ̸ç ÀϽÃÀûÀ¸·Î¸¸ À°Ã¼ ¼Ó¿¡ »ì »ÓÀ̶ó´Â ÇöóÅæÀÇ °ßÇØ¸¦ ¹èôÇß´Ù. ±×´ë½Å ¹°ÁúÀû Á¸ÀçÀÇ ±àÁ¤Àû °¡Ä¡¸¦ ´õ °­Á¶Çϸ鼭 ¿µÈ¥Àº À°Ã¼¿Í º»ÁúÀûÀ¸·Î ÅëÀϵǾî ÀÖ´Â »ý¸íÀÇ ¿ø¸®¶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ±×¸®°í ÇöóÅæÀ» ¾î´À Á¤µµ ¼ö¿ëÇÏ¿© ¿µÈ¥À» À°Ã¼ÀÇ Çü»ó, À°Ã¼¸¦ ¿µÈ¥ÀÇ Áú·á¶ó°í Á¤ÀÇÇß´Ù. BC 343³â¸»(¶Ç´Â BC 342ÃÊ) ±×ÀÇ ³ªÀÌ 42¼¼°æ¿¡ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾ÆÀÇ Çʸ®Æ÷½º 2¼¼ÀÇ ÃÊûÀ¸·Î 13¼¼ µÈ ±×ÀÇ ¾Æµé ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º¸¦ °¡¸£Ä¡±â À§ÇØ Æç¶ó·Î °¬´Ù. Çʸ®Æ÷½º 2¼¼´Â ±×¸®½º ÃÖ°íÀÇ Áö½ÄÀÎ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º¿¡°Ô ¾ÆµéÀ» ÈǸ¢ÇÑ ±º»ç ÁöµµÀڷΠŰ¿ö´Þ¶ó°í ºÎŹÇß´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º¸¦ öÇÐÀ¸·Î °è¸ùµÈ °íÀüÀû ¿ë±â¸¦ »ó¡ÇÏ´Â Àι°·Î ¸¸µé·Á°í ³ë·ÂÇßÀ¸¸ç, ±×¸®½ºÀÎÀÇ ¿ì¼öÇÔ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ±»Àº ¹ÏÀ½À» °¡Áö°í ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º¿¡°Ô ºñ±×¸®½º ¹Ì°³ÀÎÀ» Á¤º¹ÇÏ°í ±×µé°ú ÇǸ¦ ¼¯Áö ¸»¶ó°í °¡¸£ÃÆ´Ù. ÀÌ Ãæ°í¿¡µµ ºÒ±¸ÇÏ°í ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º´Â ±×¸®½ºÀΰú ºñ±×¸®½ºÀÎÀÇ °áÈ¥À» Çã¿ëÇßÀ¸¸ç, Æä¸£½Ã¾Æ ±ÍÁ· °¡¹® Ãâ½ÅÀÇ ¾Æ³»¸¦ ¸Â¾Ò´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º¿¡°Ô º°·Î Å« ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÌÄ¡Áö ¸øÇß´Ù. ƯÈ÷ Á¤Ä¡ À̵¥¿Ã·Î±â ¸é¿¡¼­ µÎ »ç¶÷ »çÀÌ¿¡´Â Å« °Å¸®°¡ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½ºÀÇ Á¤º¹ÀÌ ±×¸®½º ¼¼°è¿¡ ÀÏÀ¸Å°±â ½ÃÀÛÇÑ ±Ùº»Àû º¯È­¸¦ °¨ÁöÇÏÁö ¸øÇß´Ù. ¿ÀÈ÷·Á ±×´Â ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½ºÀÇ Á¦±¹Á¤Ã¥ÀÌ µµ½Ã±¹°¡ÀÇ Á߿伺À» ÁÙÀÎ´Ù°í ¹Ý´ëÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ¹Ý¸é ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º´Â ½º½Â¿¡ ´ëÇÑ °¨»çÀÇ ¶æÀ¸·Î ¾Æ¹öÁö Çʸ®Æ÷½º 2¼¼°¡ ÆÄ±«ÇÑ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ °íÇâ ½ºÅ¸±â·Î½º¸¦ ´Ù½Ã ¼¼¿ü´Ù. ¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾Æ ±ÃÁ¤¿¡¼­ 3³âÀ» º¸³½ µÚ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ½ºÅ¸±â·Î½º·Î µÇµ¹¾Æ¿ÔÀ¸¸ç, ±×°÷¿¡¼­ Å׿ÀÇÁ¶ó½ºÅ佺 µî ÀÚ±âÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ ÇÐÆÄ¿Í °è¼Ó ±³·ùÇß´Ù.

Á¦3±â( ¸®ÄÉÀÌ¿ÂÀÇ Ã¢¼³°ú Áöµµ)

BC 335³â±îÁö ½ºÅ¸±â·Î½º¿¡ ¸Ó¹® µÚ °ÅÀÇ 50¼¼°¡ µÇ¾úÀ» ¶§ ¾ÆÅ׳׷Π´Ù½Ã µ¹¾Æ¿Ô´Ù. À̶§ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ÆÀÇ ÁöµµÀÚ ÀÚ¸®´Â ½ºÆä¿ì½ÃÆ÷½º°¡ Á×Àº µÚ ºñ¾î ÀÖ´Ù°¡ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º¿Í »ý¹°ÇÐÀ» ÇÔ²² ¿¬±¸ÇÑ Ä®Äɵ·ÀÇ Å©¼¼³ëÅ©¶óÅ×½º°¡ À̾î¹Þ¾Ò´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀÌ¾Æ¿Í ¿ÏÀüÈ÷ Àο¬À» ²÷Áö´Â ¾Ê¾ÒÁö¸¸ BC 335³â °æÀïÇпøÀ» ¸®ÄÉÀ̿¿¡ ¿­¾ú´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ Çпø ¾È¿¡ ÀÖ´Â ÁöºØ µ¤ÀÎ »êÃ¥·ÎÀÎ Æä¸®ÆÄÅ佺¿¡¼­ ÇлýµéÀ» °¡¸£ÃƱ⠶§¹®¿¡ ÀÌ ÇÐÆÄ´Â 'Æä¸®ÆÄÅ佺'(áÎé«ùÊ÷ï¶ó°íµµ ÇÔ)¶ó´Â À̸§À» ¾ò¾ú´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ±×µÚ 12³â µ¿¾È ¸¹Àº ÇÐÀÚÀÇ ¿¬±¸¸¦ ÅëÇÕÇÏ¿© ¸®ÄÉÀÌ¿ÂÀ» ¸ðµç ޱ¸ÀÇ Áß½ÉÁö·Î ¸¸µé¾úÀ¸¸ç °úÇаú öÇÐÀÇ ±¤¹üÇÑ ¿µ¿ª¿¡ °ÉÃÄ °­ÀǸ¦ Á¦°øÇß´Ù. ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀÌ¾Æ¿Í ¸®ÄÉÀÌ¿ÂÀÇ °¡Àå Áß¿äÇÑ Â÷ÀÌÁ¡Àº ÇöóÅæÁÖÀÇÀÚµéÀÌ ¼öÇп¡ °ü½ÉÀÇ ÃÊÁ¡À» ¸ÂÃá ¹Ý¸é ¸®ÄÉÀÌ¿ÂÀº »ý¹°Çаú ¿ª»ç¿¡ À̹ÙÁöÇß´Ù´Â Á¡ÀÌ´Ù. BC 323³â ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º ´ë¿ÕÀÌ Á×Àº µÚ ªÀº ±â°£À̳ª¸¶ ¾ÆÅ׳׿¡¼­´Â ¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾Æ¿¡ °­·ÂÈ÷ ¹Ý´ëÇÏ´Â ºÐÀ§±â°¡ Çü¼ºµÇ¾ú´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾Æ¿Í ¿À·§µ¿¾È °ü°è¸¦ ¸Î°í ÀÖ¾ú°í ¾ÆÅ׳׸¦ ¼·Á¤ÇÑ ¸¶Äɵµ´Ï¾Æ À屺 ¾ÈƼÆÄÆ®·Î½º¿Íµµ Ä£Ç߱⠶§¹®¿¡ ½Åº¯ÀÇ À§ÇùÀ» ´À³¢°í ¾ÆÅ׳׸¦ ¶°³ª ¿¡¿ìº¸ÀÌ¾Æ ¼¶ÀÇ Ä®Å°½º¿¡ ÀÖ´Â ¾î¸Ó´ÏÀÇ ¿µÁö·Î °¬´Ù. À̵ëÇØ ±×°÷¿¡¼­ À§À庴À¸·Î Á×¾úÀ¸¸ç, À̶§ ³ªÀÌ´Â 62(¶Ç´Â 63)¼¼¿´´Ù. ±×°¡ ¾ÆÅ׳׸¦ ¶°³­ ±î´ßÀº ¾ÆÅ׳×ÀεéÀÌ Ã¶Çп¡ ´ëÇØ 2¹ø ÁËÁþ´Â °Í(ù¹øÂ°´Â ¼ÒÅ©¶óÅ×½º¸¦ Á×ÀÎ ÀÏÀ» °¡¸®Å´)À» ¸·±â À§Çؼ­¿´´Ù°í ÇÑ´Ù.

Àι°¡¤¼º°Ý ¹× öÇÐÀû À§Ä¡

Èä»ó°ú Á¶°¢À¸·Î ¿ì¸®¿¡°Ô ³¸ÀÍÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ¸ð½ÀÀº Àß »ý±â°í ¼¼·ÃµÇ¾î º¸ÀδÙ. ±×·¯³ª Ãâó°¡ ºÐ¸íÇÏÁö ¾ÊÀº ÇÑ ÀÚ·á¿¡ µû¸£¸é ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â °¡´Ã°í ±ä ´Ù¸®¸¦ °¡Áö°í ÀÖ¾ú°í Çô ªÀº ¼Ò¸®¸¦ ÇßÀ¸¸ç, ÀÌ·± ½ÅüÀÇ °áÇÔÀ» ¸¸È¸Çϱâ À§ÇØ ÁÁÀº ¿ÊÀ» ÀÔ°í °í±Þ ½ÅÀ» ½Å¾ú´Ù°í ÇÑ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ½ºÅ¸±â·Î½º¿¡ ¸¹Àº Àç»êÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ¾ú´ø °Í °°´Ù. ±×´Â Ã¥À» ¸ðÀ¸´Â µ¥ µ·À» ¸¹ÀÌ ½è´Ù. ÇöóÅæÀº ±×ÀÇ ºÎÀ¯ÇÔÀ» ºÎ·¯¿öÇÑ µíÇѵ¥ ±×¸¦ 'Ã¥¹ú·¹'¶ó°í ºÎ¸£±âµµ Çß´Ù. ¾î´À³¯ ÇöóÅæÀÌ ¼ÒÅ©¶óÅ×½ºÀÇ ÃÖÈĸ¦ ´ãÀº ¡´ÆÄÀ̵· Phaidon¡µÀ» ÀоîÁÖ°í ÀÖ¾ú´Âµ¥ Á¦ÀÚµéÀÌ Çϳª µÑ ºüÁ®³ª°¡°í ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º¸¸ ³²¾Ò´Ù´Â ÀÏÈ­°¡ ÀüÇØ¿Â´Ù. ²Ù¹Î À̾߱âÀÎÁöµµ ¸ð¸£Áö¸¸ ÀÌ ÀÏÈ­´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ±×´ç½Ã ¿µÈ¥ºÒ¸ê¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ¼ÒÅ©¶óÅ×½ºÀÇ Çм³¿¡ ±í°Ô ºüÁ® ÀÖ¾úÀ½À» º¸¿©ÁØ´Ù. ±×´Â ÀÌ Çм³¿¡ ÁöÀûÀ¸·Î °ü½ÉÀ» °¡Á³À» »Ó ¾Æ´Ï¶ó Á¤¼­ÀûÀ¸·Îµµ ±íÀÌ ¸Å·áµÇ¾î ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ±×°¡ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀÌ¾Æ ½ÃÀý¿¡ ¾´ Ãʱ⠴ëÈ­Æíµé(Áö±ÝÀº ´ÜÆí¸¸ ³²¾Æ ÀÖÀ½)Àº Çö¼¼ÀÇ ¹«°¡Ä¡ÇÔ°ú ³»¼¼¿¡ °üÇÑ »ç»óµµ ´ã°í ÀÖ´Ù.

±×¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÏÈ­µéÀ» »ìÆìº¸¸é ±×´Â ģöÇÏ°í ´ÙÁ¤ÇÑ ¼º°ÝÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ¾úÀ¸¸ç Àß³­ üÇÏ´Â ¼º°ÝÀº º°·Î º¸ÀÌÁö ¾Ê´Â´Ù. À¯¾ðÀå¿¡´Â ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ÇູÇÑ °¡Á¤»ýȰ¿¡ °üÇØ À̾߱âÇϰí Àڽİú ³ë¿¹¿¡ ´ëÇØ ±íÀÌ ¹è·ÁÇÑ ´ë¸ñµµ ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ °³ÀÎÀûÀÎ ÇູÀº ¾ö¹ÐÇÑ Àǹ̿¡¼­ ±×ÀÇ ¸¶Áö¸· ¹®¿¹ ÀÛǰÀÎ ¡´Ã¶Çп¡ °üÇÏ¿© On Philosophy¡µ¿¡ Àß ³ªÅ¸³ª ÀÖ´Ù. BC 348³â°æ ÀÌ ÀÛǰÀ» ¿Ï¼ºÇÑ µÚ ±×´Â ¿¬±¸, ±³À°, Àü¹®Àû ³í¹® ÁýÇÊ µî¿¡ Èû½è´Ù. ¡´Ã¶Çп¡ °üÇÏ¿©¡µ´Â ±× µÚÀÇ °í´ë»ç»ó¿¡ Å« ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÌÃÆ´Ù. ÀÌ ÀúÀÛÀº öÇÐÀ» ÇϳªÀÇ Àü¹®Á÷¾÷À¸·Î È®¸³ÇÑ Ã¥ÀÌ´Ù. ÇöÀç ³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â ´ÜÆí¿¡ µû¸£¸é, ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â öÇÐÀÚÀÇ Æ¯¼öÇÑ ¿ªÇÒ¿¡ ´ëÇØ Á¤ÀǸ¦ ³»¸®°í ÀÖ´Ù. ¹®¸íÀÇ ¹ß´Þ»ç¸¦ 5´Ü°è·Î ³ª´©°í öÇÐÀÇ µîÀåÀ» ±× ÀýÁ¤À¸·Î º»´Ù. ù¹øÂ° ´Ü°è´Â »ç¶÷µéÀÌ ÇʼöǰÀ» ¸¸µå´Â µ¥ Àü·ÂÇÏÁö ¾ÊÀ» ¼ö ¾ø´Â ´Ü°èÀÌ´Ù. 2¹øÂ° ´Ü°è¿¡¼­´Â »ýȰÀ» ¼¼·ÃµÇ°Ô ¸¸µå´Â ¿¹¼úÀÌ ³ªÅ¸³ª°í, 3¹øÂ° ´Ü°è¿¡¼­´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ »ý°¢ÇÑ ´ë·Î ÈǸ¢ÇÑ »ýȰÀ» ÇÏ´Â µ¥ ¼±°á ¿ä°ÇÀÎ Á¤Ä¡±â¼úÀÌ ³ªÅ¸³­´Ù. 4¹øÂ° ´Ü°è¿¡¼­ Áú¼­ÀÖ´Â ±¹°¡°¡ ³ªÅ¸³²À¸·Î½á ÁöÀû È£±â½ÉÀ» ä¿ï ¿©À¯°¡ »ý±â°í, Á¸ÀçÇÏ´Â »ç¹°ÀÇ ¹°ÁúÀû ¿øÀο¡ ´ëÇÑ Å½±¸°¡ ÀÌ·ç¾îÁø´Ù. 5¹øÂ° ´Ü°è¿¡¼­ »ç¶÷µéÀÇ Á¤½ÅÀº ¹°Áú¼¼°è¸¦ ³Ñ¾î »ç¹°ÀÇ Çü»óÀΰú ¸ñÀûÀÎÀ» ÆÄ¾ÇÇϰí, ÀÌ ´Ü°è¿¡¼­ ÀÚ¿¬Ã¶ÇÐÀº ½ÅÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀ¸·Î ÀÌÇàÇÑ´Ù.

ÀÌ ½ÅÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀº º°µéÀÇ ½Å¿¡ ÃÊÁ¡À» ¸ÂÃß¾ú´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾ÆÅ׳׿¡ ÀÖÀ» ¶§ õüÀÇ ¿ÏÀüÇÑ Áú¼­¸¦ ã¾Æ³»±â À§ÇØ ¿À·§µ¿¾È ³ë·ÂÇß´Ù. ±×¸®°í ÀÌ ¿ÏÀü¼ºÀº ÇöóÅæÀÇ ÀǵµÃ³·³ ¼öÇÐÀû Ãß»óÈ­·Î´Â È®ÁõÇÒ ¼ö ¾ø°í ´«¿¡ º¸À̴ õü ÀÚü¸¦ ½ÅÀÇ ±¸ÇöÀ¸·Î º¼ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù°í »ý°¢Çß´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ÀÌ¿Í °°ÀÌ ½Å°ú ±×ÀÇ ÀÛǰÀÎ ¹°ÁúÀû ¿ìÁÖ°¡ Ä£¹ÐÇÑ °ü°è¸¦ ¸Î°í ÀÖ´Ù°í º½À¸·Î½á Çö¼¼ÀÇ °¡Ä¡¸¦ Àû±ØÀûÀ¸·Î ÀÎÁ¤Çß´Ù. ¶Ç ¿µÈ¥Àº À°Ã¼ ¼Ó¿¡ °¤Çô ÀÖ°í µû¶ó¼­ ÀÚÀ¯·Î¿öÁö·Á¸é ¹°Áú°úÀÇ ¿¬°á°í¸®¸¦ ²÷¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â ÇöóÅæÀÇ Çм³µµ °ÅºÎÇß´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¹Ù·Î ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ °üÁ¡ ¶§¹®¿¡ »ç»ó»ç¿¡¼­ µ¶Ã¢Àû À§Ä¡¸¦ Â÷ÁöÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù.

ÀúÀÛ

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ÀúÀÛÀº µÎ ºÎ·ù·Î ³ª´©¾îÁø´Ù. ù¹øÂ° ºÎ·ù´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¹ßÇ¥ÇßÁö¸¸ Áö±ÝÀº ¾ø¾îÁø ÀúÀÛµéÀ̰í, 2¹øÂ° ºÎ·ù´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¹ßÇ¥ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò°í ¹ßÇ¥ÇÒ »ý°¢µµ ¾ø¾úÁö¸¸ ´Ù¸¥ »ç¶÷ÀÌ ¸ðÀ¸°í ÆíÁýÇÏ¿© Áö±Ý±îÁö ³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â ÀúÀÛµéÀÌ´Ù. ù¹øÂ° ºÎ·ù¿¡´Â ±× ÀÚ½ÅÀÌ '´ëÁß¿ë'(exoteric)ÀÌ ¶ó°í ºÎ¸¥ ÀúÀÛ, Áï ÀϹݴëÁßÀ» À§ÇØ ´ëȭü ¶Ç´Â ±×¹ÛÀÇ À¯ÇàÇÏ´Â ¹®ÇÐÇü½ÄÀ¸·Î ¾´ Ã¥, '±â¾ï¿ë'(hypomnematic)À̶ó°í ºÎ¸¥ ³ëÆ®¿Í ´õ ³ª¾Æ°¡ ¿¬±¸¸¦ À§ÇÑ ÀÚ·á¸ðÀ½ÀÌ Æ÷ÇԵȴÙ. ÀÌÁß ÇöÀç ³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â °ÍÀº ´ÜÆíµé»ÓÀÌ´Ù. ¸¶Áö¸·À¸·Î '°­ÀÇ¿ë'(acroamatic)À̶ó°í ºÎ¸¥ ÇöÀç °ÅÀÇ ¿ÏÀüÇÏ°Ô ³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â ÀúÀÛ ¶Ç´Â ³í¹®Àº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ Çпø¿¡¼­ »ç¿ëÇϱâ À§ÇÑ °ÍÀ̾úÀ¸¸ç °£°áÇÏ°í °³¼ºÀÖ´Â ¹®Ã¼·Î ¾º¾î ÀÖ´Ù. °í´ë ÈĹݱ⿡ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ±ÛÀº ¼ö¹é ±ÇÀÇ µÎ·ç¸¶¸®¿´´Ù°í Çϴµ¥, ÇöÀç ³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â °ÍÀº 30±ÇÀÇ 2,000Âʰ¡·®ÀÌ´Ù. °í´ëÀÇ Ã¥¸ñ·ÏÀ» º¸¸é ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ÀúÀÛÀº ÃÑ 170¿© ±Ç¿¡ ´ÞÇß´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¹ßÇ¥ÇßÀ¸³ª ¾ø¾îÁø ÀúÀÛ

¾ø¾îÁø ´ëÁß¿ë ÀúÀÛ¿¡´Â ¼öÇʰú ÇöóÅæ½ÄÀÇ ´ëÈ­Æí»Ó¸¸ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ½Ã¿Í ÆíÁöµµ ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ ¾ø¾îÁø ´ëÁß¿ë ÀúÀÛÀ» À籸¼ºÇÏ·Á´Â ÇÐÀÚµéÀº ¿©·¯ °¡Áö ³­Á¦¿¡ ºÎµúÃÆ´Ù. ¿¹¸¦ µé¾î ¾ø¾îÁø ´ëÈ­ÆíÀº ÇöÁ¸ÇÏ´Â ±Û ¼Ó¿¡ µé¾î ÀÖ´Â Çм³°ú »ó´çÈ÷ ´Ù¸¥ µíÇÏ´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ´ëÈ­Æí ¡´Çູ·Ð Eudemus¡µ¿¡ °üÇØ ÇöÀç ¹àÇôÁø °ÍÀ̳ª ¡´¿µÈ¥¿¡ °üÇÏ¿©¡µ´Â ¿µÈ¥°ú À°Ã¼ÀÇ °ü°è¸¦ ºÎÀÚ¿¬½º·¯¿î °áÇÕ, ¿¹ÄÁ´ë Ƽ·¹´Ï¾Æ ÇØÀûÀÌ Æ÷·Î¸¦ ½Ãü¿Í ¹­¾î °¡ÇÑ °íÅë¿¡ ºñÀ¯ÇÑ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ÇöÁ¸ÇÏ´Â ±Û¿¡¼­ ÇöóÅæÁÖÀǸ¦ ÁöÁöÇÏ´Â µ¿·áµé¿¡°Ô ¿µÈ¥°ú À°Ã¼¸¦ ¼­·Î ÀûÀ¸·Î ¸¸µç´Ù°í ºñÆÇÇß´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ¸Æ¶ô¿¡¼­ 2¼¼±â¸»¿¡ Ȱµ¿ÇÑ ±ÇÀ§ ÀÖ´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º ÇØ¼®°¡ ¾ÆÇÁ·Îµð½Ã¾Æ½ºÀÇ ¾Ë·º»êµå·Î½º´Â Ȥ½Ã ±×°¡ '2°¡Áö Áø¸®', Áï ÀϹÝÀÎÀ» À§ÇÑ '´ëÁß¿ë' Áø¸®¿Í ¸®ÄÉÀÌ¿ÂÀÇ Á¦ÀÚµéÀ» À§ÇÑ 'ºñÀü¿ë'(ÝúîîéÄ esoteric) Áø¸®¸¦ µû·Î ¸»ÇÑ °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ò±î¶ó´Â Àǹ®À» Á¦±âÇß´Ù. ¿À´Ã³¯ ÇÐÀÚµéÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ´ëÁß¿ë ÀúÀÛÀÌ ´ëºÎºÐ ÇöóÅæÀÇ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ƿ¡ ÀÖ´ø Ãʱ⠴ܰ迡 ³ª¿Â °ÍÀÌ°í µû¶ó¼­ ÀÌ ÀúÀÛÀº ±×ÀÇ '´ëÁß¿ë' »ç»óº¸´Ù´Â '¹Ì¼÷ÇÑ' »ç»óÀ» º¸¿©Áشٴ Á¡¿¡ µ¿ÀÇÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ¾ø¾îÁø ÀúÀÛ Áß Áß¿äÇÑ °ÍÀ¸·Î´Â ÇöóÅæÀÇ ¡´ÆÄÀ̵·¡µÀÇ ÀüÅëÀ» ÀÕ´Â ¡´Çູ·Ð¡µ, ³ªÁß¿¡ ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐ Metaphysica¡µ¿¡¼­ ¼³¸íÇÏ´Â ÁÖÁ¦µéÀ» ´ãÀº ÀÏÁ¾ÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ °­·ÉÀÎ ¡´Ã¶Çп¡ °üÇÏ¿©¡µ, öÇÐÀû »ýȰÀ» ±ÇÇÏ´Â ¡´ÇÁ·ÎÆ®·¹ÇÁƼÄÚ½º Protrepticus¡µ, ¡´±×¸±·Î½º Gryllus¡µ ¶Ç´Â ¡´¼ö»çÇп¡ °üÇÏ¿© Rhetorica¡µ, ¡´Á¤Ä¡ÇСµ°ú ºñ½ÁÇÑ ÁÖÁ¦¸¦ ´Ù·é ¡´Á¤ÀÇ¿¡ °üÇÏ¿© On Justice¡µ, ÇöóÅæÀÇ Çü»ó·ÐÀ» ºñÆÇÇÑ ¡´À̵¥¾Æ¿¡ °üÇÏ¿© On Ideas¡µ µîÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù.

³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â ÀúÀÛ

ÇöÁ¸ÇÏ´Â ÀúÀÛÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ³²±ä ¼ö°í(â¢ÍÃ)¸¦ ¹ÙÅÁÀ¸·Î ¸¸µé¾îÁ³´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ÀÌÁß ¸¹Àº °ÍÀ» °­ÀÇ ³ëÆ®·Î »ç¿ëÇÑ °Í °°´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ÀúÀÛÀ» óÀ½ ÆíÁý¡¤Ãâ°£ÇÑ »ç¶÷Àº BC 60³â°æ ¸®ÄÉÀÌ¿ÂÀ» ¸¶Áö¸·À¸·Î À̲ö ·Îµ¥½ºÀÇ ¾Èµå·Î´ÏÄÚ½º¿´´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º ÀÚ½ÅÀÌ ÆíÁýÀ» ÇÏÁö ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù´Â »ç½ÇÀº ±×ÀÇ »ç»óÀ» ÇØ¼®ÇÏ´Â µ¥ Áß¿äÇÑ ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÌÃÆ´Ù. ¿¹¸¦ µé¾î ±×´Â ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµÀ̶ó´Â Ã¥À» ¾²Áö ¾Ê¾Ò°í, 10¿© ÆíÀÇ ÂªÀº ³í¹®À» ½èÀ» »ÓÀÌ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª Èļ¼ÀÇ ÆíÁýÀÚµéÀº ÀÌ ³í¹®À» ¸ð¾Æ ¡´ÀÚ¿¬ÇÐ Physica¡µ ´ÙÀ½¿¡ Àоî¾ß ÇÑ´Ù´Â ¶æ¿¡¼­ ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµÀ̶ó°í À̸§ ºÙ¿´´Ù. ±×·¯¹Ç·Î ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµ°ú ±×¹ÛÀÇ ¸î¸î ÀúÀÛÀº »ç»óÀÇ Àϰü¼ºÀ̳ª ¶Ñ·ÇÇÑ ¿¬¼Ó¼ºÀÌ ¾ø¾î º¸ÀδÙ. ¶Ç ¸®ÄÉÀÌ¿ÂÀÇ ÇлýÀ̳ª ±¸¼º¿øÀÌ ¶â¾î°íÄ£ °ÍÀ¸·Î º¸À̴ ǥÇöµéµµ ÀÖ´Ù. ¾Èµå·Î´ÏÄÚ½º´Â ¼±¹è ÆíÁýÀÚµéÀÇ µµ¿òÀ» ¹Þ¾Æ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ÀúÀÛÀ» ³í¸®Àû¡¤±³ÈÆÀû ¼ø¼­·Î ÆíÁýÇß´Ù. ±×°á°ú ³í¹®ÀÇ ½Ã°£Àû ¼ø¼­°¡ ¹«½ÃµÇ¾ú°í ¼­·Î ´Ù¸¥ ½Ã±â¿¡ ¾´ ³í¹®µéÀÌ ÇÔ²² ¹­¿© ÀÖ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ³í¹®µéÀº ¿¬±¸Çϴ öÇÐÀÚÀÇ ¸ð½ÀÀ» Àß º¸¿©ÁØ´Ù. ±×´Â ´Ù·ç¾î¾ß ÇÒ ¹®Á¦¸¦ Á¤ÀÇÇϰí, ¼±¹è »ç»ó°¡µéÀÇ °ßÇØ¸¦ Æò°¡Çϰí, ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ¿¹ºñÀû ÀǰßÀ» Á¤½ÄÈ­ÇÑ µÚ, ¿©·¯ ³­Á¡°ú ¹Ý·Ð¿¡ ºñÃß¾î ÀÌ ÀǰßÀ» ¼öÁ¤ÇÒ Çʿ䰡 ÀÖ´ÂÁö °ËÅäÇϰí, ´Ù¸¥ °üÁ¡À» ÁöÁöÇÏ´Â ³íÁõÀ» ´Ù½Ã µè°í ³­ ´ÙÀ½ °ðÀ̾î Àڱ⠹®Á¦ÀÇ °¡Àå ÀûÀýÇÑ ÇØ´äÀ» ã¾Æ³½´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ µ¶ÀÚµéÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¾î¶² Çм³À» µ¶´ÜÀûÀ¸·Î Á¦½ÃÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù°í »ý°¢ÇÏÁö ¾Ê°í, ³­°ü¡¤¸ð¼ø¡¤¿ª¼³ µé¿¡¼­ ¹þ¾î³ª ÇϳªÀÇ Àü¸Á ¶Ç´Â ½Ä°ßÀ» °è¹ßÇÏ·Á ¿¬±¸Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù°í »ý°¢ÇÑ´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º »ç»óÀÇ ÁøÈ­¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÌ·Ð

¿¹°ÅÀÇ ¹ß´ÞÀÌ·Ð

20¼¼±â ÀÌÀü ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ÇöÁ¸ÇÏ´Â ³í¹®µéÀº ±×ÀÇ ÁøÂ¥ »ç»óÀ» º¸¿©ÁÖ´Â ±Û·Î ÇØ¼®µÇ¾ú´Ù. ±×¸®°í ¹ß·»Æ¾ ·ÎÁ¦Ã³·³ ¾ø¾îÁø ´ëÈ­ÆíµéÀÌ ¸ðµÎ °¡Â¥¶ó´Â ÁÖÀåµµ ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ÇØ¼®ÀÇ ¹Ø¹ÙÅÁ¿¡´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÃ³·³ ¾ö¹ÐÇϰí ü°èÀûÀÎ Á¤½ÅÀ» °¡Áø »ç¶÷ÀÌ Àϰü¼º¾ø´Â »ç»óÀ» Á¦½ÃÇßÀ» ¸® ¾ø´Ù´Â °¡Á¤ÀÌ ±ò·Á ÀÖ¾ú´Ù. ±×·¯³ª 20¼¼±â Àü¹Ý µ¶ÀÏÀÇ º£¸£³Ê ¿¹°Å´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º »ç»óÀÌ ´Ü°èÀûÀ¸·Î ¹ß´ÞÇß´Ù´Â ÀÌ·ÐÀ» Á¦½ÃÇß´Ù. ¿¹°Å´Â ¿ª»ç¹ß»ý·ÐÀû ¹æ¹ý·ÐÀ» ÀÌ¿ëÇÏ¿© ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ¾ø¾îÁø ÀúÀÛ ´ëºÎºÐÀº ±×°¡ ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ƿ¡¼­ ÇöóÅæÀÇ ¿µÇâÀ» °­ÇÏ°Ô ¹ÞÀ» ¶§ Áö´Ñ »ç»óÀ» º¸¿©Áشٰí ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¿¹°Å¿¡ µû¸£¸é ¿µÈ¥ºÒ¸ê°ú °°Àº ÁÖÁ¦¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ¼±È£, ¹°Áú¼¼°è¿¡ ´ëÇÑ °æ¸ê, À̵¥¾ÆÀÇ '»ó±â'(ßÌÑÃ) ÀÌ·Ð, ÁöÇýÀÇ ¿ìÀ§, ±Ý¿åÁÖÀÇ, ½ÅÀÇ Á¸Àç ÀÎÁ¤ µî Ãʱ⠻ç»óÀº ÇöóÅæÀûÀ̾úÀ¸¸ç, ±× µÚ¿¡ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â Á¡Â÷ ÇöóÅæÀÇ °ßÇØ¿Í ¸Ö¾îÁ® °ü³ä·ÐÀ» ¹ö¸®°í °æÇèÁÖÀÇ·Î ³ª¾Æ°¬´Ù.

¿¹°ÅÀÇ ¹ß´ÞÀÌ·ÐÀ» ºñÆÇÇÏ´Â »ç¶÷µéÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º ÀúÀÛÀÇ Á¤È®ÇÑ ¿¬´ë¸¦ °áÁ¤ÇÒ ¼ö ¾ø´Ù´Â Á¡À» ÁöÀûÇß´Ù. µû¶ó¼­ ¾î´À ³í¹®ÀÌ ¾î´À ½ÃÁ¡¿¡ ¾´ °ÍÀÎÁö¸¦ ¾Ë ¼ö ¾øÀ¸¹Ç·Î ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ Ãʱ⠻ç»ó¸¸ÀÌ ÇöóÅæ°ú ÀÏÄ¡ÇÑ´Ù´Â °¡Á¤Àº Áõ¸íÇÒ ¼ö ¾ø´Ù°í ºñÆÇÇß´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ¿¹°ÅÀÇ ÀÌ·ÐÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ½É¸®Çаú °ü·ÃÇØ¼­´Â Ÿ´ç¼ºÀ» Áö´Ï°í ÀÖ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â Ãʱ⿡ ¿µÈ¥À» À°Ã¼¿Í ºÐ¸®µÈ ½Çü·Î ¹¦»çÇß°í, À°Ã¼¸¦ ¿µÈ¥ÀÇ µµ±¸·Î º¸´Â Áß°£ ´Ü°è¸¦ °ÅÃÄ ¸¶Áö¸·¿¡´Â ¿µÈ¥À» À°Ã¼ÀÇ Çü»ó ¶Ç´Â Çö½ÇÅ·Πº½À¸·Î½á ¿µÈ¥°ú À°Ã¼ÀÇ ½ÇüÀû ÅëÀÏÀ» ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º »ç»óÀÇ ¹ß´Þ°ú ü°èÈ­¿¡ °üÇÑ ÃÖ±ÙÀÇ ºÐ¼®

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º ¿¬±¸ÀÚµéÀº ´ëü·Î ±×ÀÇ »ç»óÀÌ ´Ü°èÀûÀ¸·Î ¹ß´ÞÇß´Ù°í º¼ ±Ù°Å°¡ ÀÖÁö¸¸ º¯È­ÀÇ ½ÃÁ¡°ú Á¤µµ¸¦ °áÁ¤ÇÏ´Â µ¥´Â ¹®Á¦°¡ ÀÖ´Ù°í ÇÑ´Ù. Çö´ë ÇØ¼®°¡µéÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ °æÇèÀû Áö½Ä°ú ¹°ÁúÀÇ ¿ªµ¿Àû Ãø¸éÀ» Áß½ÃÇÏ°Ô µÇ¸é¼­ ÇöóÅæÀÇ °ü³ä·ÐÀÇ ¸ðµç Ãø¸éÀ» °ÅºÎÇÑ °ÍÀº ¾Æ´Ï¶ó´Â Á¡¿¡´Â µ¿ÀÇÇÑ´Ù. ¿ÀÈ÷·Á ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â »ý¹°Çп¡¼­´Â ½ÇÇèÀûÀ¸·Î ¿¬±¸Çϸ鼭µµ ¹°¸®Çп¡¼­´Â Áö°¢°ú »çÀ¯, »ç¹°ÀÇ ¿ì¿¬Àû Ư¼º°ú º»¼º »çÀÌÀÇ Â÷À̸¦ °è¼Ó ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º ¿øÀüÀÇ °³°ü

³í¸®Çп¡ °üÇÑ ÀúÀÛ

³í¸®ÇÐÀ̶ó´Â ¿ë¾î´Â ÀÌ¹Ì ¾ÆÄ«µ¥¸ÞÀ̾ÆÀÇ Å©¼¼³ëÅ©¶óÅ×½º°¡ ¸¸µé¾úÁö¸¸ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¾ð¾î(·Î°í½º)¿¡ ¸¹Àº Àǹ̸¦ ºÎ¿©ÇÏ¿© À̸¦ Àΰ£¸¸ÀÇ Æ¯Â¡À¸·Î °­Á¶Çϰí Àΰ£À» À̼ºÀû µ¿¹°·Î Á¤ÀÇÇß´Ù. ¿©±â¼­ À̼ºÀû µ¿¹°Àº ±×¸®½º¾î·Î '¾ð¾î¡¤¸»' ¶Ç´Â '´Ü¾î'¸¦ °¡Áø µ¿¹°À̶ó´Â ¶æÀÌ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ³í¸®ÇÐ ³í¹®µéÀº ¡´¿À¸£°¡³í Organon¡µ('µµ±¸'¶ó´Â ¶æ)À̶ó´Â ÀúÀÛ ¼Ó¿¡ ¸ð¿© ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ Á¦¸ñÀº ÈÄ´ëÀÇ ÇØ¼®°¡µéÀÌ ºÙÀÎ °ÍÀε¥, À̵éÀº ¼Ò¿äÇÐÆÄÀÇ ÀüÅë¿¡ µû¶ó ³í¸®ÇÐÀ» öÇÐÇÏ´Â ¼ö´ÜÀ¸·Î »ý°¢Çß´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ³í¸®ÇÐÀ» °úÇÐÀÇ ºÐ·ùü°è ¼Ó¿¡ ³ÖÁö ¾Ê°í °¢ Áö½ÄºÐ¾ß¸¦ ¿¬±¸Çϱâ Àü¿¡ ¸ÕÀú ÇØ¾ß ÇÒ ¿¹ºñÇй®À¸·Î ¿©°å´Ù. ±×°¡ ³í¸®Çп¡ Á÷Á¢ ºÙÀÎ À̸§Àº 'ºÐ¼®·Ð'(analytica)À̾ú´Ù.

¡´¿À¸£°¡³í¡µÀº ¡´¹üÁÖ·Ð Categoriae¡µ¡¤¡´Çؼ®·Ð De interpretatione¡µ¡¤¡´ºÐ¼®·Ð Àü¼­ Analytica priora¡µ¡¤¡´ºÐ¼®·Ð Èļ­ Analytica posteriora¡µ¡¤¡´ÅäÇÇÄ« Topica¡µ¡¤¡´±Ëº¯·Ð Sophistici elenchi¡µ µîÀÇ ³í¹®À¸·Î ±¸¼ºµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ ³í¹®µéÀÇ ¹è¿­ ¼ø¼­´Â ¿¬´ëº¸´Ù ü°è¿¡ µû¸¥ °ÍÀ¸·Î º¸À̸ç, ÁýÇÊ¿¬´ë¿¡ µû¸¥ ¼ø¼­¸¦ È®Á¤ÇÏ´Â ÀÏÀº °ÅÀÇ ºÒ°¡´ÉÇÏ´Ù. ¡´¹üÁַСµÀÌ ½ÇÁ¦ÀÇ »ç¹° ¶Ç´Â »ç¹°ÀÇ º»¼º¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÌ·ÐÀÎÁö ¾Æ´Ï¸é ¸» ¶Ç´Â Ç¥Çö¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÌ·ÐÀÎÁö´Â ºÐ¸íÇÏÁö ¾Ê´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¹üÁÖ·ÐÀ» ½ÇÀç¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÌ·ÐÀ¸·Î »ç¿ëÇÏ¿© ÇöóÅæÀÇ Çü»óÀÌ·ÐÀ» ºñÆÇÇß´Ù. ±×¿¡ µû¸£¸é ÇöóÅæÀº ¿¹¸¦ µé¾î ¾Æ¸§´Ù¿ò ¶Ç´Â ÁöÇý¿Í °°Àº Áú¿¡ ½Çü¼ºÀ» ºÎ¿©ÇÔÀ¸·Î½á ½Çü ¹üÁÖ¿Í ±×¹ÛÀÇ ¹üÁÖ¸¦ È¥µ¿Çß´Ù. ¡´¹üÁַСµ 5Àå¿¡¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ½Çü ¹üÁÖ ¾È¿¡¼­µµ 'Á¦1½Çü'¿Í 'Á¦2½Çü'¸¦ ±¸ºÐÇß´Ù. Á¦1½Çü´Â ÀÌ »ç¶÷, Àú ¸», ÀÌ µ¹ µîÀÇ °³Ã¼À̸ç, Á¦2½Çü´Â ÀÌ °³Ã¼°¡ ¼ÓÇÑ Á¾(ðú)°ú À¯(×¾)ÀÌ´Ù.

ÀÌ¿Í °°ÀÌ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â Á¾°ú À¯¸¦ ÆÄ»ýµÈ Á¾·ùÀÇ ½Çü·Î º¸¾Ò´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµ¿¡¼­´Â Á¾°ú À¯°¡ 1Â÷Àû ½Çü·Î ³ªÅ¸³­´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ °ßÇØ´Â ºÐ¸íÇÏÁö ¾ÊÀ¸¸ç, ±×·¡¼­ ¸î¸î ÇÐÀÚµéÀº ±×°¡ ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµ¿¡¼­ ÇöóÅæÀû Á¸Àç·ÐÀ¸·Î µÇµ¹¾Æ°¬´Ù°í ÇØ¼®ÇÑ´Ù. ¡´Çؼ®·Ð¡µ¿¡¼­´Â ¿ì¼± 'À̸§'¡¤'µ¿»ç' µî ¹®ÀåÀ» ±¸¼ºÇÏ´Â ´Ü¼øÇÑ ºÎºÐµé¿¡ °üÇØ ³íÀÇÇÑ ´ÙÀ½ ´Ù¾çÇÑ Á¾·ùÀÇ ¿ÏÀüÇÑ ¹®Àåµé°ú ÀÌµé »çÀÌ¿¡ ¼º¸³ÇÏ´Â ³í¸®Àû °ü°è(¹Ý´ë¡¤¸ð¼ø¡¤ÇÔ¾ð)¸¦ °ËÅäÇÑ´Ù. ¶Ç '¾ç»ó' ¹®Àå('¡¦¡¦Àº °¡´ÉÇÏ´Ù', '¡¦¡¦Àº ÇÊ¿¬ÀûÀÌ´Ù')¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ¼±±¸ÀûÀÎ ¼³¸í°ú '¹Ì·¡ÀÇ ¿ì¿¬'¿¡ ´ëÇÑ À¯¸íÇÑ ³íÀÇ(¸¸ÀÏ ³»ÀÏ ÇØÀüÀÌ ÀÖÀ» °ÍÀ̶ó´Â Á¡ÀÌ ÀÌ¹Ì ÂüÀ̶ó¸é, ¾î¶»°Ô ±× ÇØÀüÀ» ¿ì¿¬Àû »ç°ÇÀ¸·Î º¼ ¼ö Àִ°¡? ¸¸ÀÏ Áø¸®°¡ ÀÌ¹Ì °áÁ¤µÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù¸é ±× ÇØÀüÀº È®Á¤ÀûÀ̰í ÇÊ¿¬ÀûÀΰ¡? ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ´ë´äÀº ¹Ì·¡¿¡ °üÇÑ Æ¯Á¤ À¯ÇüÀÇ ¹®ÀåÀº Âüµµ ¾Æ´Ï°í °ÅÁþµµ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó´Â °ÍÀÓ)¸¦ Æ÷ÇÔÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù. ¡´ÅäÇÇÄ«¡µ´Â ÁÖ·Î ¾î¶² ÁÖÀåÀ» È®ÀÎÇϰųª ¹Ý¹ÚÇÒ ³íÁõÀ» ¾î¶»°Ô ãÀ» °ÍÀΰ¡¸¦ ´Ù·é´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ ÀÌ ³í¹®Àº ³í¸®ÇÐÀÇ ÀÏ¹Ý ¹ýÄ¢ ¶Ç´Â ±ÔÄ¢À» ¼³¸íÇϰí ÀÖ´Ù.

¡´±Ëº¯·Ð¡µÀº °ÑÀ¸·Î º¸¸é Ÿ´çÇÑ °Í °°Áö¸¸ ½ÇÀº ¿À·ùÀÎ Ã߷бÔÄ¢À» ¹àÈù´Ù. ¿À·ù³íÁõÀÇ ¿¹·Î´Â '¼±°á¹®Á¦ ¿ä±¸ÀÇ ¿À·ù' ¶Ç´Â ¼øÈ¯³íÁõ(¿¹ÄÁ´ë ¿µÈ¥Àº ºÒ¸êÀ̱⠶§¹®¿¡ ¿µÈ¥Àº À°Ã¼°¡ Á×Àº µÚ¿¡µµ °è¼Ó Á¸ÀçÇÑ´Ù´Â 'Áõ¸í'), ÈİDZàÁ¤ÀÇ ¿À·ù(¿¹ÄÁ´ë ¸¸ÀÏ ¾î¶² »ç¶÷ÀÌ ¼ú²ÛÀ̶ó¸é ±×´Â °¡³­ÇÒ °ÍÀÌ´Ù, ÇÇÅÍ´Â °¡³­ÇÏ´Ù, ±×·¯¹Ç·Î ÇÇÅÍ´Â ¼ú²ÛÀÌ´Ù¶ó´Â ³íÁõ), ³íÁ¡ÀÏÅ»ÀÇ ¿À·ù(¹®Á¦°¡ µÇ´Â °á·ÐÀ» Áõ¸íÇÏ´Â ´ë½Å ¹«°üÇÑ »ç½Ç¿¡ ÁÖÀǸ¦ µ¹¸²À¸·Î½á ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ³íÁ¡À» µÞ¹ÞħÇÏ´Â ³íÁõ) µîÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù.

¡´ºÐ¼®·Ð Àü¼­¡µÀÇ °¡Àå Å« ¾÷ÀûÀº ¿À´Ã³¯ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ »ï´Ü³í¹ý·ÐÀ̶ó°í ¾Ë·ÁÁø ³í¸®ÇРü°è¸¦ ¹ß´Þ½ÃŲ Á¡ÀÌ´Ù. »ï´Ü³í¹ýÀ̶õ ¼¼ ¸íÁ¦(µÎ ÀüÁ¦¿Í ÇÑ °á·Ð)·Î ±¸¼ºµÈ ³íÁõÇü½ÄÀ̸ç, Ÿ´çÇÑ »ï´Ü³í¹ýÀÇ ¿¹´Â ´ÙÀ½°ú °°´Ù. '¸ðµç ±×¸®½ºÀÎÀº »ç¶÷ÀÌ´Ù¡¤¸ðµç »ç¶÷Àº Á״´١¤¸ðµç ±×¸®½ºÀÎÀº Á״´Ù.' ¡´ºÐ¼®·Ð Àü¼­¡µ´Â ³î¶ó¿ï Á¤µµ·Î ¾ö¹ÐÇϰí Á¤±³ÇÏ°Ô »ï´Ü³í¹ýÀÇ ´Ù¾çÇÑ Çü½ÄÀ» °ËÅäÇÑ´Ù. ¡´ºÐ¼®·Ð Èļ­¡µ¿¡¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ³í¸®ÇÐ ÀÌ·ÐÀ» °úÇаú ÀνķÐÀÇ ¸ñÀû¿¡ ÀÀ¿ëÇÏ·Á ÇÑ´Ù. °úÇÐÁö½ÄÀÇ ÀûÀýÇÑ ±¸Á¶¸¦ ³íÀÇÇϸ鼭, °¢°¢ÀÇ °úÇÐÀº Á¦1¿ø¸®, Áï °ø¸®¿Í ¿©±â¼­ ¿¬¿ªµÈ Á¤¸®·Î ±¸¼ºµÇ¾î¾ß ÇÑ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ¸Æ¶ô¿¡¼­ ¡´ºÐ¼®·Ð Èļ­¡µ Á¦2±ÇÀº ÁÖ·Î 'Á¤ÀÇ'(ïÒëù) ÀÌ·ÐÀ» ´Ù·é´Ù.

ÀÚ¿¬Ã¶Çп¡ °üÇÑ ÀúÀÛ

¡´ÀÚ¿¬ÇСµ¿¡¼­´Â ÀÚ¿¬ ¹°Ã¼ ÀϹÝ, Áï Çüü¸¦ °¡Áø ¸ðµç °ÍÀ» ´Ù·ç°í, Ư¼öÇÑ Á¾·ùÀÇ ¹°Ã¼´Â ¡´Çϴÿ¡ °üÇÏ¿© On the Heavens¡µ¡¤¡´±â»óÇÐ Meteorology¡µ µîÀÇ ±Û¿¡¼­ ´Ù·é´Ù. ¡´ÀÚ¿¬ÇСµ Á¦1±ÇÀº ÀÚ¿¬ ¹°Ã¼¸¦ ±¸¼ºÇÏ´Â º»ÁúÀû ¿ä¼Òµé, Áï 'Áú·á'¿Í 'Çü»ó'À» ´Ù·é´Ù. Áú·á´Â º¯È­¸¦ °ÅÄ¡´õ¶óµµ °è¼Ó Á¸ÀçÇÏ´Â ±âüÀ̰í Çü»óÀº º¯È­ÀÇ ¼ºÁúÀ» °áÁ¤Çϴ Ư¡ÀÌ´Ù. Á¦2±ÇÀº ÁÖ·Î ÀÚ¿¬ÇÐÀÚµéÀÌ ¿¬±¸ÇÏ´Â ´Ù¾çÇÑ À¯ÇüÀÇ ¿øÀÎÀ» ´Ù·é´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ ¿øÀÎÀ¸·Î´Â Áú·áÀΡ¤Çü»óÀÎ À̿ܿ¡ ¾î¶² °ÍÀÌ Á¸ÀçÇÏ´Â ¸ñÀûÀΰú ¾î¶² °ÍÀ» Á¸ÀçÇÏ°Ô ÇÏ´Â ÀÛ¿ëÀÎ µîÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù. Á¦3~7±ÇÀº ¿îµ¿°ú °ø°£¡¤À§Ä¡¡¤½Ã°£¡¤Å©±â¡¤¿¬¼Ó¼º µî ¿îµ¿°ú °ü·ÃµÈ °³³äÀ» ´Ù·é´Ù. Á¦8±ÇÀÇ ÁÖÁ¦´Â ¿øµ¿ÀÚ(ê«ÔÑíº)ÀÌ´Ù. ¿øµ¿ÀÚ¶õ ±× ÀÚü°¡ ÀÚ¿¬ ¹°Ã¼´Â ¾Æ´ÏÁö¸¸ ¸ðµç ÀÚ¿¬ ¹°Ã¼¸¦ ¿îµ¿ÇÏ°Ô ¸¸µå´Â ¿øÀÎÀ̸ç, ºÎµ¿¼º¡¤¿µ¿ø¼º µîÀÇ ¼Ó¼ºÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¡´ÀÚ¿¬ÇСµ¿¡¼­ ³íÀÇÇÑ ÀϹݿø¸®¸¦ ¿ìÁÖ Àüü¸¦ ´Ù·ç´Â ¡´Çϴÿ¡ °üÇÏ¿©¡µ(¿©±â¼­ ±×´Â ¿ìÁÖ°¡ °ø°£ ¸é¿¡¼­ À¯ÇÑÇÏÁö¸¸ ½Ã°£ ¸é¿¡¼­ ¿µ¿øÇÏ´Ù°í ³íÁõÇÔ)¿Í ¿ìÁÖÀÇ »ý¸í ¾ø´Â ºÎºÐÀ» ´Ù·ç´Â ¡´»ý¼º°ú ¼Ò¸ê¿¡ °üÇÏ¿© On Generation and Corruption¡µ¡¤¡´±â»óÇСµ µî¿¡µµ Àû¿ëÇÑ´Ù. ¡´»ý¼º°ú ¼Ò¸ê¿¡ °üÇÏ¿©¡µ´Â 4¿ø¼Ò(È롤°ø±â¡¤ºÒ¡¤¹°)¿Í ±× »óÈ£°ü°è¸¦ ´Ù·é´Ù. ƯÈ÷ ±×´Â ÇÑ ¿ø¼Ò°¡ ´Ù¸¥ ¿ø¼Ò¸¦ º¯ÇÏ°Ô Çϰųª ´Ù¸¥ ¿ø¼Ò·Î º¯ÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¡´±â»óÇСµÀº ¿¹ÄÁ´ë Çý¼º¡¤°­¡¤¿¬¼Ò¡¤¹«Áö°³ µî Àâ´ÙÇÑ ¹®Á¦¸¦ ´Ù·é´Ù. ¿©±â¼­ ±×´Â ÀÚ¿¬ÇÐÀÇ ÀϹݿø¸®¿Í ¿ø¼Ò·Ð¿¡¼­ ÇÑ °ÉÀ½ ´õ ³ª¾Æ°¡ Áö±¸°¡ Ç×»ó ÀÏÁ¾ÀÇ 'Áõ¹ß'(¼öÁõ±â³ª ¿¬±â¿Í °°ÀÌ ½À±â°¡ ÀÖ´Â °Íµµ ÀÖ°í ¾ø´Â °Íµµ ÀÖÀ½)À» Çϰí ÀÖ´Ù°í °¡Á¤Çϰí, À§ÀÇ ´Ù¾çÇÑ Çö»óÀ» ÀÌ Áõ¹ß·Î ¼³¸íÇÏ·Á ÇÑ´Ù.

»ý¹°Çаú µ¿¹°ÇÐ ÀúÀÛ¿¡µµ ¡´ÀÚ¿¬ÇСµÀÇ ¿ø¸®´Â ºÐ¸íÇÏ°Ô ³ªÅ¸³­´Ù. ¡´µ¿¹°»ç History of Animals¡µ´Â ¼­·Î ´Ù¸¥ µ¿¹° Á¾¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ±â¼úÀÌ ÁÖ³»¿ëÀÌ´Ù. ÀÌÁß °©°¢·ù µ¿¹°Á¾¿¡ ´ëÇÑ °ÍÀ» ºñ·ÔÇÑ ¸î °¡Áö ±â¼úÀº ³î¶ó¿ï Á¤µµ·Î »ó¼¼Çϰí Á¤È®ÇÏ´Ù. ¸î¸î ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º ¿¬±¸ÀÚ´Â ¡´µ¿¹°»ç¡µ°¡ 1Â÷ ÀÚ·áµéÀ» ¸ðÀº °ÍÀÏ »Ó ü°èÈ­ÇÏÁö´Â ¾Ê¾Ò´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇÑ´Ù. ÇÑÆí ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¡´µ¿¹°»ç¡µ¿¡¼­ »ý¹° ºÐ·ùÇÐÀ» ¼¼¿ì·Á Çß°í ±×·¡¼­ µ¿¹°¼¼°è¸¦ À¯(×¾)¿Í Á¾(ðú)À¸·Î ³ª´©¾ú´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇÏ´Â ÇÐÀÚµµ ÀÖ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª ¡´µ¿¹°ÀÇ ½Åü ºÎºÐ Parts of Animals¡µ¡¤¡´µ¿¹°ÀÇ »ý¼º Generation of Animals¡µÀº ºñ·Ï ¸¹Àº °æÇèÀڷḦ ´ã°í ÀÖÁö¸¸ °úÇÐÀû ¼³¸í ü°è¸¦ ¼¼¿ì·Á´Â Àǵµ¸¦ °¡Áø ±ÛÀÌ´Ù.

±×´Â µ¿¹°ÀÇ ¿©·¯ ±â°ü°ú ±×¹ÛÀÇ '½Åü ºÎºÐ'ÀÇ ¼ºÁú¡¤±â´É µîÀ» ´Ü¼øÈ÷ ±â¼úÇÏÁö ¾Ê°í '¼³¸í'ÇÏ·Á ÇÑ´Ù. ¹Ù·Î ¿©±â¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ¸ñÀû·ÐÀû ¼³¸íÀÌ ¶Ñ·ÇÇÏ°Ô ³ªÅ¸³­´Ù. "ÀÚ¿¬Àº ¾µµ¥¾ø´Â ÁþÀ» ÇÏÁö ¾Ê´Â´Ù"¶ó°í ¸»ÇßÀ¸¸ç, ºÐ¸íÇÏ°Ô Ç¥ÇöÇÏÁö´Â ¾Ê¾ÒÁö¸¸ µ¿¹°ÀÇ ¸ðµç Ư¡À» ±â´ÉÀûÀ¸·Î ¼³¸íÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇϱ⵵ Çß´Ù. ¡´µ¿¹°ÀÇ »ý¼º¡µÀº ƯÈ÷ »ý½Ä°ú ¼ºÀåÀÇ ¹®Á¦¸¦ ´Ù·é´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ °¡Àå ¹«¸£ÀÍÀº ÀÌ °úÇÐÀúÀÛ¿¡´Â ±×ÀÇ ¹æ¹ýÀÇ Àå´ÜÁ¡ÀÌ Àß ³ªÅ¸³ª ÀÖ´Ù. ±×´Â Á¶½É½º·´°í Á¤È®Çϸç, ÀÌ·ÐÀû ¼³¸íÀ» Á¦½ÃÇϸ鼭µµ ÀÌ·ÐÀÌ °üÂûÀ» ¿Ö°î½ÃŰÁö ¾ÊÀ¸·Á ÇÑ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª Áö½Ä°ú »õ Áö½ÄÀ» ¾ò´Â ±×ÀÇ ¼ö´ÜÀº ºÐ¸íÈ÷ ÇѰ踦 °¡Áö°í ÀÖÀ¸¸ç µû¶ó¼­ Àû¾îµµ ¸î¸î ÀÌ·ÐÀû °³³äÀº °ÅÄ¥°í ºÎÀûÀýÇÏ´Ù. ±×¹Û¿¡ »ý¹°ÇÐ ÀúÀÛÀ¸·Î´Â ¡´µ¿¹°ÀÇ ¿îµ¿ Movement of Animals¡µ¡¤¡´µ¿¹°ÀÇ Áøº¸ Progression of Animals¡µ µî 2ÆíÀÇ ÂªÀº ³í¹®ÀÌ ÀÖ´Ù. ¿©±â¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â µ¿¹°ÀÇ ¿òÁ÷ÀÓ¿¡ ´ëÇÑ »ý¸®ÇÐÀû ¼³¸í°ú ½É¸®ÇÐÀû ³íÀǸ¦ °áÇÕÇÏ·Á Çß´Ù.

½É¸®Çп¡ °üÇÑ ÀúÀÛ

°¨°¢ »ýȰ°ú ÁöÀû »ýȰ¿¡¼­ ÀÛ¿ëÇÏ´Â ´Éµ¿Àû ¿ø¸®¿Í ¼öµ¿Àû ¿¬¼Óü »çÀÌÀÇ °ü°è ¶Ç´Â Çü»ó°ú Áú·áÀÇ °ü°è¸¦ °ËÅäÇÏ´Â ÀúÀÛÀº ¡´¿µÈ¥¿¡ °üÇÏ¿©¡µÀÌ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¿µÈ¥ÀÇ º»¼º¿¡ °üÇÑ ÇöóÅæÀÇ ÃÊ¿ùÁÖÀÇÀû À̷аú ¼ÒÅ©¶óÅ×½º ÀÌÀüÀÇ À¯¹°·ÐÀû ÀÌ·ÐÀ» ¸ðµÎ °ÅºÎÇÑ´Ù. ¿µÈ¥Àº »ý¸íüÀÇ Çü»óÀ¸·Î¼­ Áú¼­ÀÖ´Â ±â´ÉÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ÀÌ ±â´ÉÀº ¾çÀ°¡¤Áö°¢¡¤Áö¼º µîÀÌ´Ù. ¾çÀ° ±â´ÉÀº ¸ðµç »ý¸íü¿¡ °øÅëÀûÀÎ ±â´ÉÀÌ¸ç º¸°í, µè°í, ³¿»õ ¸Ã°í, ¿òÁ÷ÀÌ´Â ¿ªÇÒÀ» ´ã´çÇÑ´Ù. Áö¼º ±â´ÉÀº Àΰ£¿¡°Ô¸¸ ÀÖ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â Áö°¢ ¾ç½ÄÀ» ÀÚ¼¼È÷ ¼³¸íÇß°í, »çÀ¯¿¡ ´ëÇØ¼­µµ '¼öµ¿' Áö¼º°ú '´Éµ¿' Áö¼ºÀ» ±¸ºÐÇÏ´Â ¾î·Æ±â·Î ¼Ò¹®³­ ¼³¸íÀ» Á¦½ÃÇß´Ù. ÀÌ ÀúÀÛÀº µ¿¹°ÀÇ ¿òÁ÷ÀÓ°ú ±× ÀüÁ¦Á¶°ÇÀÎ »ó»ó¡¤¿å¸Á µî¿¡ ´ëÇØ¼­µµ ³íÀÇÇß´Ù.

ÇüÀÌ»óÇп¡ °üÇÑ ÀúÀÛ

ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀº ±× ÁÖÁ¦ ¸é¿¡¼­ ÀǰßÀÌ ÀÏÄ¡ÇÏÁö ¾Ê´ø ºÐ¾ß¿´´Âµ¥ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ÀÌ ºÐ¾ßÀÇ ¿¬±¸¸¦ Çõ½ÅÇß´Ù. ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµ¿¡´Â ±×°¡ ¶§·Î´Â 'ÁöÇý'¶ó ºÎ¸£°í ¶§·Î´Â 'Á¦1öÇÐ' ¶Ç´Â ½ÉÁö¾î '½ÅÇÐ'À̶ó ºÎ¸¥ Çм³ÀÌ ¼³¸íµÇ¾î ÀÖ´Ù. ÀÌ Çм³ÀÇ °úÁ¦´Â ½ÇÀçÀÇ °¡Àå ÀϹÝÀû¡¤Ãß»óÀû Ư¡°ú º¸ÆíŸ´ç¼ºÀ» Áö´Ñ ¿ø¸®¸¦ ±â¼úÇÏ´Â °ÍÀÌ´Ù. ³Î¸® ¾Ë·ÁÁø ´ë·Î ±×´Â ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀ» 'Á¸Àç·Î¼­ÀÇ Á¸Àç'¸¦ ¿¬±¸ÇÏ´Â Çй®À̶ó°í Çߴµ¥, ÀÌ ¸»Àº Á¸ÀçÇÏ´Â °ÍÀ̶ó¸é ¸ðµÎ ÃæÁ·ÇØ¾ß ÇÏ´Â ÀϹÝÁ¶°Ç, ´Þ¸® ¸»Çؼ­ Á¸ÀçÇÏ´Â ¸ðµç °Í¿¡ °üÇØ ÂüÀÎ °ÍÀ» ¿¬±¸ÇÑ´Ù´Â ¶æÀÌ´Ù.

¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµ Á¦1±Ç¿¡¼­´Â ¼±¹è öÇÐÀÚµéÀÌ »ç¿ëÇϰųª ³íÀÇÇÑ ¼³¸í Çü½ÄÀ» Á¶»ç¡¤¿¬±¸Çϰí ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ '4¿øÀÎ' ÀÌ·ÐÀÌ ¼³¸í¹®Á¦¿¡ °üÇÑ ¿Ã¹Ù¸¥ ÀÌ·ÐÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ÀÌ Á¶»ç¡¤¿¬±¸´Â ¼ÒÅ©¶óÅ×½º ÀÌÀü öÇÐÀÚµé°ú ÇöóÅæ öÇÐÀÇ ¸î °¡Áö Ãø¸é¿¡ °üÇÑ Á¤º¸¸¦ Á¦°øÇÏ´Â ±ÍÁßÇÑ ÀÚ·áÀÌ´Ù. Á¦2±ÇÀº °úÇÐÀÇ ¿ø¸®¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÂªÀº ³í¹®À̰í, Á¦3±ÇÀº ÇüÀÌ»óÇÐÀÇ ¼ö¼ö²²³¢ ¶Ç´Â '¾ÆÆ÷¸®¾ÆÀÌ'(aporiai)¸¦ ³ª¿­ÇÑ ±ÛÀÌ´Ù. Á¦4±Ç¿¡¼­´Â 'Á¦1öÇÐ'ÀÌ Á¸ÀçÀÇ Á¶°Ç¿¡ ´ëÇÑ ÀϹÝÀû ¿¬±¸¶ó°í ¼³¸íÇϰí, ¸ð¼øÀ²('P¿Í ºñP°¡ ¸ðµÎ ÂüÀº ¾Æ´Ï´Ù')°ú ¹èÁß·ü('P°¡ ÂüÀ̰ųª ¾Æ´Ï¸é ºñP°¡ ÂüÀÌ´Ù')À» ¿ËÈ£ÇÑ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º öÇÐ »çÀüÀ̶ó°í ºÒ¸®´Â Á¦5±Ç¿¡¼­´Â Áß¿äÇϸ鼭µµ ¸ðÈ£ÇÑ ¾à 40°³ÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ ¿ë¾î¸¦ ºÐ¼®ÇÑ´Ù. Á¦6±ÇÀÇ ÁÖÁ¦´Â Á¦4±Ç°ú °°´Ù.

Á¦7~9±ÇÀº ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ¾´ °¡Àå ¾î·Á¿î ±Û °¡¿îµ¥ ÇϳªÀÌ¸ç µû¶ó¼­ ¿ä¾àÇÒ ¼ö ¾ø´Ù. Çٽɹ®Á¦´Â ½Çü¶õ ¹«¾ùÀΰ¡, ¼¼°èÀÇ ±âº» ±¸¼º¹°Àº ¹«¾ùÀ̸ç, µ¶¸³ÀûÀ¸·Î Á¸ÀçÇÏ°í ¿ì¸®°¡ Àνġ¤Á¤ÀÇÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â °ÍÀº ¹«¾ùÀΰ¡ µîÀÌ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ³íÀÇ´Â ¸Å¿ì º¹ÀâÇÏ°Ô ²¿¿© ÀÖÀ¸¸ç, Áú·á¿Í Çü»ó, ½Çü¿Í º»Áú, º¯È­¿Í ¹ß»ý, Çö½ÇÅÂ¿Í °¡´ÉÅ µî¿¡ ÃÊÁ¡À» ¸ÂÃá´Ù. °á·ÐÀº ½Çü¶õ ¾î¶² Àǹ̿¡¼­´Â Çü»óÀ̶ó´Â °ÍÀÎ µíÇÏ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª À̶§ Çü»óÀº ÇöóÅæ½ÄÀÇ Ãß»óÀû Çü»óÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ±¸Ã¼ÀûÀÌ°í Æ¯¼öÇÑ Çü»óÀÌ´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ Çü»óÀº ¿¹ÄÁ´ë 'ÀÌ »ç¶÷', 'Àú ¸»' ¶Ç´Â 'ÀÌ Âü³ª¹«' µîÀÇ Ç¥ÇöÀÌ Áö½ÃÇÏ´Â °ÍÀÌ´Ù. Á¦10±ÇÀº ÅëÀϼº¡¤¿¬¼Ó¼º¡¤µ¿Àϼº µî 'ÀÏÀÚ'(ìéíº)¿¡ °üÇÑ µ¶¸³ÀûÀÎ ³í¹®ÀÌ´Ù. Á¦11±ÇÀº ¡´ÀÚ¿¬ÇСµ¡¤¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµÀÇ ¾ÕºÎºÐÀ» ¿ä¾àÇÏ´Â ±ÛÀÌ´Ù. Á¦12±Ç¿¡¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â '¸ñÀû·Ð'À» Á¦½ÃÇÑ´Ù. ¼¼°è¸¦ ¼³¸íÇϱâ À§Çؼ­´Â ¾ó¸¶³ª ¸¹Àº ¿øÀÎÀ» ¼³Á¤ÇØ¾ß ÇÏ´ÂÁö¸¦ ¹¯°í, °á±¹ ½Å ¶Ç´Â ¿òÁ÷ÀÌÁö ¾Ê´Â Á¦ÀÏ ¿øµ¿ÀÚ¶ó´Â »ý°¢¿¡ µµ´ÞÇÑ´Ù. Á¦13¡¤14±Ç¿¡¼­´Â ¼öÇÐÀû ´ë»óÀÇ º»¼º¿¡ ´ëÇØ ±æ°Ô ³íÀÇÇÑ´Ù.

À±¸®Çаú Á¤Ä¡Çп¡ °üÇÑ ÀúÀÛ

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â À̷аúÇаú ½Çõ°úÇÐÀÇ ¸ñÀûÀÌ °áÁ¤ÀûÀ¸·Î ´Ù¸£´Ù°í °­Á¶Çϸ鼭, ½Çõ°úÇÐÀº ¹«¾ùÀΰ¡¸¦ ÇàÇϰųª ¸¸µé±â À§ÇÑ Çй®ÀÌÁö ±×°ÍÀ» »ç°íÇϰí Á¤ÀÇÇÏ°í ¾Ë±â À§ÇÑ Çй®ÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¡´´ÏÄÚ¸¶ÄÚ½º À±¸®ÇÐ Ethica Nicomachea¡µ ù ºÎºÐ¿¡¼­ ¿Ö ½Çõ°úÇÐÀÌ À̷аúÇи¸Å­ Á¤È®¼ºÀ» °¡Áú ¼ö ¾ø´ÂÁö¸¦ ¼³¸íÇϴµ¥, ±× ÀÌÀ¯´Â ½Çõ°úÇÐÀÇ ÁÖÁ¦°¡ Á¤È®ÇÏ°Ô Á¤ÀÇÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â °Í¿¡ ÇÑÁ¤µÇÁö ¾Ê°í ½À°ü¡¤±â¼ú¡¤Á¦µµ µî±îÁö Æ÷ÇÔÇϱ⠶§¹®ÀÌ´Ù. ±×¸®°í »ý¹°ÇÐÀû Á¤Àdzª ½É¸®ÇÐÀû Á¤Àǰ¡ ¾Æ¹«¸® Á¤È®ÇÏ´õ¶óµµ »ç¶÷Àº ȯ°æ¡¤±³À°¡¤°¡Á·¡¤Àç»ê¡¤½ÅºÐ, ½ÉÁö¾î ¿©°¡ ¹æ½Ä µî¿¡ µû¶ó ´Ù¾çÇÏ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. °³Àο¡°Ô ¿µÇâÀ» ¹ÌÄ¡´Â µµ´ö¹®Á¦µéÀº ¼­·Î ºÐ¸®ÇÒ ¼ö ¾øÀ» »Ó ¾Æ´Ï¶ó Á¤Ä¡¹®Á¦¿Íµµ ºÐ¸®ÇÒ ¼ö ¾ø´Ù°í ¼³¸íÇß´Ù. ±×·¯¹Ç·Î ¡´´ÏÄÚ¸¶ÄÚ½º À±¸®ÇСµ¡¤¡´Á¤Ä¡ÇСµÀº µ¶ÀÚÀûÀÎ ÁÖÁ¦¸¦ ´Ù·ç´Â ¼­·Î ºÐ¸®µÈ °úÇÐÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó °øÅëÀÇ ¿µ¿ªÀ» ¼­·Î ´Ù¸¥ °üÁ¡¿¡¼­ ´Ù·ç¸é¼­ »óÈ£º¸¿ÏÇÑ´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â °³ÀεéÀÇ °¡´ÉŸ¦ ¹ÙÅÁÀ¸·Î »ï¾Æ µµ´ö¹®Á¦¸¦ ´Ù·ç¾úÁö¸¸, ÀÌ °¡´ÉŸ¦ Çö½ÇÈ­ÇÏ°í ½ÇõÇÏ´Â ´É·ÂÀº Á¤Ä¡»óȲ¿¡ ÀÇÁ¸ÇÑ´Ù°í »ý°¢Çß´Ù. ±×·¡¼­ ¡´´ÏÄÚ¸¶ÄÚ½º À±¸®ÇСµ Á¦1±Ç¿¡¼­ Á¤Ä¡Ã¶ÇÐÀÇ ±¤¹üÇÑ ¸Æ¶ôÀ» µµ´öÀûÀ¸·Î °í·ÁÇÏ´Â µ¥¼­ Ãâ¹ßÇÏ¿©, Á¦10±Ç¿¡¼­´Â Çູ°ú ¸í»ó»ýȰÀ» °ËÅäÇÑ µÚ µµ´ö¹®Á¦¿¡ ´ëÇØ ¹ýÀÌ ±â¿©ÇÒ ¼ö ÀÖ´Â Á¡À» ¾ð±ÞÇϸ鼭 ³¡³½´Ù. ÀÌ ÁöÁ¡ÀÌ À±¸®Çп¡¼­ Á¤Ä¡ÇÐÀ¸·Î ³Ñ¾î°¡´Â °÷ÀÌ´Ù. À±¸®Çп¡¼­ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ »ç¿ëÇÑ Á¢±Ù¹ýÀº ¸ñÀû·ÐÀÌ´Ù. Áï µµ´öÀûÀ¸·Î Àý´ëÀûÀÎ ¾î¶² °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó ¹«¾ùÀÌ Àΰ£ÀÇ ¼±À» À§ÇØ ¹Ù¶÷Á÷ÇѰ¡¸¦ ±âÁØÀ¸·Î À±¸®¹®Á¦¸¦ À̾߱âÇÑ´Ù. ÀÌ·¯ÇÑ Á¢±Ù¹ý ¶§¹®¿¡ ´Ù¾çÇÑ Á¾·ùÀÇ ¼±À» °ËÅäÇÏ°í ¸¶Ä§³» Çູ¿¡ À̸£´Â ÃÖ°í¼±À» ±ÔÁ¤ÇÑ´Ù. ±×¸®°í ÇູÀ̶ó´Â ¸»½é ¸¹Àº °³³äÀ» ¸é¹ÐÈ÷ °ËÅäÇÑ µÚ ÇູÀ» ´ö(arete)°ú ÀÏÄ¡ÇÏ´Â ¿µÈ¥ÀÇ È°µ¿À̶ó°í Á¤ÀÇÇÑ´Ù.

±×´Â µµ´öÀû ´ö°ú ÁöÀû ´öÀ» ±¸ºÐÇÏ°í °¢°¢Àº ¿µÈ¥ÀÇ ºñÇÕ¸®Àû Èû°ú ÇÕ¸®Àû Èû¿¡ ÀÇÇØ ±ÔÁ¤µÈ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇÑ´Ù. ±×·¯³ª Àΰ£Àº ž ¶§ºÎÅÍ ÀÌ ´öÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖ´Â °ÍÀÌ ¾Æ´Ï¶ó »ì¾Æ°¡¸é¼­ ´öÀ» °³¹ßÇÒ ´É·Â ¶Ç´Â ¼ºÇâÀ» °¡Áö°í ÀÖÀ» »ÓÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇÑ´Ù. ¿¹¸¦ µé¾î ¾î¸°À̴ óÀ½¿¡´Â ÀÚ±â ÇൿÀÇ µµ´öÀû ¿ì¼öÇÔÀ» ±ú´ÝÁö ¸øÇÑ Ã¤ ºÎ¸ðÀÇ ¸í·É¿¡ µû¶ó °ÅÁþ¸»À» ÇÏÁö ¾ÊÁö¸¸ °á±¹ Âü¸»À» ÇÏ´Â ½À°üÀÌ ±×ÀÇ µµ´ö¼ºÀÇ »Ñ¸® ±íÀº ÀϺΰ¡ µÈ´Ù.

±× ´ÙÀ½ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ´ö°ú ¾ÇÀ» ±¸ºÐÇÏ°í ´öÀ» 'Áß¿ë'À¸·Î Á¤ÀÇÇÑ´Ù. ¿¹¸¦ µé¾î ¿ë±â´Â ¸¸¿ë°ú ºñ°Ì »çÀÌÀÇ Áß¿ëÀÌ´Ù. ±×´Â ÃÖ°í¼±À» Á¤ÀÇÇϸ鼭 ÀÌ ³íÀǸ¦ ³¡¸Î´Âµ¥, ÇູÀÌ ´ö¿¡ µû¸¥ Ȱµ¿À̱⠶§¹®¿¡ ÃÖ°í¼±Àº »ç¶÷ÀÇ ÃÖ°í´ö, Áï À̼ºÀû Ȱµ¿¿¡ µû¸¥ »îÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇÑ´Ù. ¡´Á¤Ä¡ÇСµÀº Àΰ£ Çൿ°ú °øµ¿Ã¼ÀÇ ¹®Á¦¸¦ ´Ù·é´Ù. ±×´Â Àΰ£ÀÌ 'º»¼ºÀûÀ¸·Î' Á¤Ä¡Àû µ¿¹°À̶ó´Â ÀüÁ¦¿¡¼­ Ãâ¹ßÇÏ¿© ±¹°¡¿¡ °üÇÑ ÀÌ·ÐÀ» ¼¼¿ì°í ´Ù¾çÇÑ À¯ÇüÀÇ ¹ýÁ¦µµ¸¦ ±¸ºÐÇÑ´Ù. Á¤Ä¡Àû ºÒ¾ÈÁ¤°ú Çõ¸íÀÇ ¼ºÁú°ú ¿øÀο¡ °üÇÑ ³íÀǵµ ÀÖÀ¸¸ç, ¸¶Áö¸· 2±ÇÀº ÁÖ·Î ±³À° ¹®Á¦¸¦ ´Ù·ç°í ÀÖ´Ù.

¿¹¼ú°ú ¼ö»çÇп¡ °üÇÑ ÀúÀÛ

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º´Â ¼ö»çÇÐÀÇ ¸ñÀû ¶Ç´Â ¸ñÀûÀÎÀ» ¼³µæÀ̶ó°í ÁÖÀåÇÑ´Ù. ¼ö»çÇеµ ³í¸®Çаú ¸¶Âù°¡Áö·Î °úÇÐü°è ¼Ó¿¡ Æ÷ÇÔµÇÁö ¾ÊÀ¸¸ç µû¶ó¼­ ƯÁ¤ÀÇ ÁÖÁ¦, ´ÜÀÏÇÑ ¹æ¹ý, ÀÏ·ÃÀÇ ¿ø¸®¸¦ °®Áö ¾Ê´Â´Ù. ±×¿¡ µû¸£¸é ¼³µæÀÇ ¾ç½ÄÀº ¼³µæÀÚ ÀÚ½ÅÀÇ ¼º°Ý¿¡ µû¸¥ ¼³µæ·Â, ¿øÇÏ´Â °¨Á¤À» ûÁß¿¡°Ô ÀÏÀ¸Å°´Â °Í, Áõ¸í ¶Ç´Â °ÑÄ¡·¹ Áõ¸í µî 3°¡ÁöÀÌ´Ù. ¡´½ÃÇÐ Poetica¡µ¿¡¼­ ±×´Â ½Ã¿Í ¿ª»ç¸¦ ºñ±³Çϸ鼭 ½Ã°¡ ¿ª»çº¸´Ù ´õ öÇÐÀûÀÌ°í µû¶ó¼­ ´õ Å« °¡Ä¡¸¦ Áö´Ñ´Ù°í ÁÖÀåÇß´Ù. ¿ª»ç´Â °³º°ÀÚ, Áï Æ¯Á¤ »ç°ÇÀ̳ª ƯÁ¤ Àι°À» ´Ù·é´Ù. ¹Ý¸é ½Ã´Â ºñ·Ï ÀÚ¿¬À» ¸ð¹æÇÏÁö¸¸ º¸ÆíÀÚ¿¡ °¡±î¿î À¯Çü°ú »óȲÀ» âÁ¶ÇÑ´Ù. ¡´½ÃÇСµ Áß ÇöÀç ³²¾Æ ÀÖ´Â À¯ÀÏÇÑ ´ÜÆíÀº ºñ±ØÀ» ºÐ¼®ÇÏ´Â ºÎºÐÀ̸ç, ¿©±â¼­ ºñ±ØÀÇ ¸ñÀûÀº µ¿Á¤°ú µÎ·Á¿òÀ» ÅëÇØ °¨Á¤À» Á¤È­ÇÏ´Â °Í, Áï 'īŸ¸£½Ã½º'¶ó°í ¸»ÇÑ´Ù.

¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º ÀúÀÛÀ» Àд ¹æ¹ý

±«Å×´Â ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀ» ÇǶó¹Ìµå¿¡ ºñÀ¯Çß´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º öÇÐÀÇ °¢ ºÎºÐÀº ´Ù¸¥ ºÎºÐÀ» ÀÌÇØÇÏ´Â µ¥ µµ¿òÀ» ÁØ´Ù. ±×·¯¹Ç·Î ¿ì¸®´Â ±×ÀÇ ÀúÀÛÀ» óÀ½ºÎÅÍ È®½ÇÈ÷ ÀÌÇØÇϸ鼭 ÀÐÀ» ¼ö ¾ø°í, ±âº»ÀûÀÎ °³³ä°ú ¹æ¹ýÀ» ¾Ë¾Æ³»±â À§ÇØ µÇÇ®ÀÌÇØ¼­ Àоî¾ß ÇÑ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ºÐ¼®¹æ½ÄÀ» ÀÍÈù µÚ¿¡´Â ¡´¿À¸£°¡³í¡µ¿¡ ÀÖ´Â ³í¸®ÇÐ ºÎºÐ°ú ¡´ÀÚ¿¬ÇСµ¿¡ ÀÖ´Â °ø°£¡¤½Ã°£¡¤¿îµ¿·ÐÀ» Àд °ÍÀÌ ÁÁ´Ù. ±× ´ÙÀ½À¸·Î ¡´ÇüÀÌ»óÇСµ¡¤¡´¿µÈ¥¿¡ °üÇÏ¿©¡µ¿¡ ÀÖ´Â Á»´õ º¹ÀâÇÑ »ç»óÀ» ¸¸³ªº¸°í, À±¸®Çаú ¹®ÇÐÀÌ·Ð ¿¬±¸¿¡¼­ ³ª¿Â °á·ÐÀ» ±× ÅëÂû·Â¡¤ºÐº°·Â¡¤³íÁõ·Â µî¿¡ ºñÃß¾î °ËÅäÇØº½Á÷ÇÏ´Ù. ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º°¡ ³»¸° °á·Ð¿¡ Á¢±ÙÇØº¸¸é ±×´Â ÇϳªÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐÀ» Á¦½ÃÇÑ Àι°·Î¼­ Áß¿äÇÒ »Ó ¾Æ´Ï¶ó Á¤½ÅÀ» °¥°í´Û´Â µ¥ µµ¿òÀ» ÁØ »ç¶÷À¸·Î¼­µµ Áß¿äÇÏ´Ù´Â Á¡ÀÌ ¹àÇôÁú °ÍÀÌ´Ù.

A. H. Amadio ±Û

¡¡

10 Major Works

MAJOR WORKS

LOGIC: These six works are known collectively as the Organon: Kategoriai (Categories); Peri hermeneias (Latin trans., De Interpretatione; Eng. trans., On Interpretation); Analytika protera (Prior Analytics); Analytika hystera (Posterior Analytics); Topika (Topics); and Peri sophistikon elegchon (Sophistical Refutations).

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY AND NATURAL SCIENCE: Physike (Physics); Peri ouranou (On the Heavens); Peri geneseos kai phthoras (On Generation and Corruption; On Coming to Be and Passing Away); Meteorologika (Meteorology); Peri kosmou (spurious; Latin trans., De mundo; Eng. trans., On the Universe); Peri ta zoa historiai (History of Animals); Peri zoon morion (Parts of Animals); Peri zoon kineseos (Movement of Animals); Peri poreias zoon (Progression of Animals); Peri zoon geneseos (Generation of Animals); and the works collectively known as the Parva Naturalia: Peri aistheseos (On the Senses and Their Objects; On Sense and Sensible Objects); Peri mnemes kai anamneseos (On Memory and Recollection); Peri hypnou kai egregorseos (On Sleep and Waking); Peri enypnion (On Dreams); Peri tes kath hypnon mantikes (On Divination in Sleep; On Prophecy in Sleep); Peri makrobiotetos kai brachybiotetos (On Length and Shortness of Life); Peri neotetos kai geros (On Youth and Old Age); Peri zoes kai thanatou (On Life and Death); Peri anapnoes (On Respiration); and Peri pneumatos (spurious; On Breath).

PSYCHOLOGY: Peri psyches (Latin trans., De anima; Eng. trans., On the Soul).

METAPHYSICS: Ta meta ta physika (Metaphysics).

ETHICS AND POLITICS: Ethika Nikomacheia (Nichomachean Ethics); Ethika Eudemeia (Eudemian Ethics); Ethika megala (spurious; Latin and Eng. trans., Magna moralia); Peri areton kai kakion (spurious; On Virtues and Vices); Politika (Politics); Oikonomika (spurious; Economics); and Athenaion politeia (incomplete; Constitution of Athens).

AESTHETICS AND LITERATURE: Techne rhetorike (Rhetoric); Rhetorike pros Alexandron (spurious; Rhetoric to Alexander); and Peri poietikes (incomplete; Poetics).

OTHER WORKS: These remain in the corpus but are believed by scholars to be falsely attributed to Aristotle: Peri chromaton (On Colours); Peri akouston (On Things Heard); Physiognomonika (Physiognomonics); Peri phyton (On Plants); Peri thaumasion akousmaton (On Marvellous Things Heard); Mechanika (Mechanics); Problemata (Problems); Peri atomon grammon (On Indivisible Lines); Anemon theseis kai prosegoriai (The Situations and Names of Winds); and Peri Melissou, peri Xenophanous, peri Gorgiou (On Melissus, Xenophanes, Gorgias).

TEXTS: The standard edition of the Greek text is the Berlin Academy edition, Aristotelis Opera, ed. by Immanuel Bekker, 5 vol. (1831-70, reissued 5 vol. in 4, 1960-61); and the standard edition of the fragments is Aristotelis qui Ferebantur Librorum Fragmenta, ed. by Valentin Rose (1870, reissued 1967). For most works these texts have been superseded by more recent editions, notably by the volumes of the Teubner series, the Oxford Classical Text series, the Loeb Classical Library series (with English translations), and the Budé series (with French translations). The medieval Latin translations of Aristotle are being printed in Aristoteles Latinus, ed. by L. Minio-Paluello (1939- ); see also Aristotelis opera cum Averrois commentariis, 9 vol. in 11 (1562-74, reissued 1962). In addition there is much useful information of a textual nature in the early Greek commentaries, the most important of which have been published in Commentaris in Aristotelem Graeca, 23 vol. in 46 (1882-1909). An invaluable aid to the study of Aristotle is Hermann Bonitz, Index Aristotelicus (1870, reprinted 1955).

RECOMMENDED EDITIONS: Numerous English translations of the major treatises are available. The standard complete edition is Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, 2 vol. (1984). Of the many editions of and commentaries on individual works, the following may be mentioned: J.L. Ackrill (trans.), Categories, and De Interpretatione (1963, reprinted 1978); W.D. Ross (ed.), Prior and Posterior Analytics (1949, reprinted 1957); Jonathan Barnes (trans.), Aristotle's Posterior Analytics (1976); W.D. Ross (ed.), Physics (1950, reprinted 1977); W. Charlton (trans.), Aristotle's Physics: Books 1 & 2 (1970); Edward Hussey (trans.), Aristotle's Physics, Books III and IV (1983); Harold H. Joachim (ed.), Aristotle on Coming-to-Be and Passing-Away (De Generatione et Corruptione) (1922, reprinted 1982); C.J.F. Williams (trans.), Aristotle's De Generatione et Corruptione (1982); R.D. Hicks (trans.), De Anima (1907, reprinted 1976); W.D. Ross (ed.), Parva Naturalia (1955, reprinted 1970); G.R.T. Ross (trans.), De Sensu and De Memoria (1906, reprinted 1973); Richard Sorabji, Aristotle on Memory (1972); D.M. Balme (trans.), Aristotle's De Partibus Animalium I; and, De Generatione Animalium I (1972); Martha Craven Nussbaum (ed. and trans.), Aristotle's De Motu Animalium (1978); W.D. Ross (ed.), Metaphysics, 2nd ed. (1928); Christopher Kirwan (trans.), Aristotle's Metaphysics (1971), Books 4-6; Myles Burnyeat (ed.), Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics (1979), and Notes on Books Eta and Theta of Aristotle's Metaphysics (1984); Julia Annas (trans.), Aristotle's Metaphysics (1976), Books 13-14; J.A. Stewart, Notes on the Nichomachean Ethics of Aristotle (1892, reprinted 1973); Michael Woods (trans.), Aristotle's Eudemian Ethics: Books I, II, and VIII (1982); W.L. Newman (ed.), The Politics of Aristotle, 4 vol. (1887-1902, reprinted 1973); Richard Robinson (trans.), Politics, Books III and IV (1962); Edward Meredith Cope (ed.), The Rhetoric of Aristotle, 3 vol. (1877, reprinted 1973); D.W. Lucas (ed.), Poetics (1968, reprinted 1980); P.J. Rhodes (trans.), The Athenian Constitution (1984); and Ingemar Düring (ed.), Protrepticus: An Attempt at Reconstruction (1961).

11 Bibliography

BIBLIOGRAPHY

 

11.1 Aristotle. General works:

There are several good introductions to Aristotle's thought: JONATHAN BARNES, Aristotle (1982); J.L. ACKRILL, Aristotle the Philosopher (1981); D.J. ALLAN, The Philosophy of Aristotle, 2nd ed. (1970, reissued 1978); G.E.R. LLOYD, Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought (1968); W.D. ROSS, Aristotle, 5th ed. (1949, reprinted 1977); and FRANZ BRENTANO, Aristotle and His World View (1978; originally published in German, 1911). For a comprehensive survey see INGEMAR DÜRING, Aristoteles: Darstellung und Interpretation seiner Denkens (1966). Two of the most influential books on Aristotle written in the 20th century are WERNER W. JAEGER, Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, 2nd ed. (1948, reissued 1962; originally published in German, 1923), which advances a theory of the development of Aristotle's thought; and HAROLD CHERNISS, Aristotle's Criticism of Plato and the Academy (1944, reissued 1962), which discusses, in a uniformly critical spirit, Aristotle's knowledge and assessment of Plato's work.

Most of the scholarly work done on Aristotle appears in articles rather than in books. There is a useful anthology: JONATHAN BARNES, MALCOLM SCHOFIELD, and RICHARD SORABJI (eds.), Articles on Aristotle, 4 vol. (1975-79). The proceedings of the triennial Symposium Aristotelicum contain some of the most up-to-date work.

Life: For all aspects of Aristotle's life, see INGEMAR DÜRING, Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition (1957); for his writings, see PAUL MORAUX, Les Listes anciennes des ouvrages d'Aristote (1951); for the history of the Lyceum, see JOHN PATRICK LYNCH, Aristotle's School: A Study of a Greek Educational Institution (1972); and PAUL MORAUX, Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen: Von Andronikos bis Alexander von Aphrodisias, 2 vol. (1973-84).

 

11.2 Thought:

(Logic): On Aristotle's formal syllogistic the classic study is JAN LUKASIEWICZ, Aristotle's Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic, 2nd ed. enlarged (1957, reprinted 1967); and the standard work is GÜNTHER PATZIG, Aristotle's Theory of the Syllogism: A Logico-Philological Study of Book "A" of the "Prior Analytics" (1969; originally published in German, 2nd ed. 1963). A less formal account can be found in ERNEST KAPP, Greek Foundations of Traditional Logic (1942, reissued 1967). See also JONATHAN LEAR, Aristotle and Logical Theory (1980); and, for the Topics, the introduction to JACQUES BRUNSCHWIG (trans.), Topiques (1967). On the development of Aristotle's ideas in logic, see FRIEDRICH SOLMSEN, Die Entwicklung der aristotelischen Logik und Rhetorik (1929, reprinted 1975). For Aristotle's modal logic, see STORRS McCALL, Aristotle's Modal Syllogisms (1963); and for less formal treatments of his ideas about modality, see JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Time & Necessity: Studies in Aristotle's Theory of Modality (1973); and SARAH WATERLOW, Passage and Possibility: A Study of Aristotle's Modal Concepts (1982). On the connection between Aristotle's logic and his scientific methodology, see J.M. LE BLOND, Logique et méthode chez Aristote: étude sur la recherche des principes dans la physique aristotélicinne, 2nd ed. (1970).

 

11.3 (Theory of science):

The standard introduction to the Physics is AUGUSTE MANSION, Introduction à la physique aristotélicienne, 2nd rev. ed. (1946); see also FRIEDRICH SOLMSEN, Aristotle's System of the Physical World: A Comparison with His Predecessors (1960, reprinted 1970). Among the most stimulating recent studies are WOLFGANG WIELAND, Die aristotelische Physik; 2nd rev. ed. (1970); RICHARD SORABJI, Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's Theory (1980), and Time, Creation, and the Continuum: Theories in Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages (1983); and SARAH WATERLOW, Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle's "Physics" (1982).

 

11.4 (Biology):

It is still worth consulting D'ARCY WENTWORTH THOMPSON, On Aristotle as a Biologist (1913); the best recent study is PIERRE PELLEGRIN, La Classification des animaux chez Aristote: statut de la biologie et unité de l'aristotélisme (1982).

 

11.5 (Psychology):

FRANZ BRENTANO, The Psychology of Aristotle: In Particular His Doctrine of the Active Intellect (1977; originally published in German, 1867), remains one of the most valuable works in this area. The standard study of the development of Aristotle's views on the soul is FRANÇOIS NUYENS, L'Évolution de la psychologie d'Aristote (1948, reissued 1973). Among more recent works are EDWIN HARTMAN, Substance, Body, and Soul: Aristotelian Investigations (1977); and DAVID CHARLES, Aristotle's Philosophy of Action (1984).

 

11.6 (Metaphysics):

There are two large and comprehensive volumes: JOSEPH OWENS, The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics: A Study in the Greek Background of Medieval Thought, 3rd ed. rev. (1978); and PIERRE AUBENQUE, Le Problème de l'être chez Aristote: essai sur la problèmatique aristotélicienne, 4th ed. (1977). There is a helpful brief introduction in G.E.M. ANSCOMBE and P.T. GEACH, Three Philosophers (1961, reprinted 1963). On special aspects of the metaphysics, see FRANZ BRENTANO, On the Several Senses of Being in Aristotle (1975, reprinted 1981; originally published in German, 1862); R.M. DANCY, Sense and Contradiction: A Study in Aristotle (1975); SUZANNE MANSION, Le Jugement d'existence chez Aristote, 2nd ed. rev. (1976); and A.C. LLOYD, Form and Universal in Aristotle (1981).

 

11.7 (Ethics):

W.F.R. HARDIE, Aristotle's Ethical Theory, 2nd ed. (1980), provides a helpful companion. Some of the best recent work is collected in AMÉLIE OKSENBERG RORTY (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's "Ethics" (1980). See also STEPHEN R.L. CLARK, Aristotle's Man: Speculations upon Aristotelian Anthropology (1975), reprinted 1983); JAMES J. WALSH, Aristotle's Conception of Moral Weakness (1963); JOHN M. COOPER, Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (1975); ANTHONY KENNY, The Aristotelian Ethics: A Study of the Relationship Between the Eudemian and Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle (1978), and Aristotle's Theory of the Will (1979); and TROELS ENGBERG-PEDERSEN, Aristotle's Theory of Moral Insight (1983, reprinted 1985).

11.8 (Politics):

The standard discussion is ERNEST BARKER, The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (1906, reissued 1959); see also R.G. MULGAN, Aristotle's Political Theory: An Introduction for Students of Political Theory (1977). On Aristotle's historical interests, see GEORGE HUXLEY, On Aristotle and Greek Society: An Essay (1979).

(Rhetoric): WILLIAM M.A. GRIMALDI, Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle's Rhetoric (1972). On the psychological aspects of rhetoric, see W.W. FORTENBAUGH, Aristotle on Emotion: A Contribution to Philosophical Psychology, Rhetoric, Poetics, Politics, and Ethics (1975).

 

11.9 (Poetics):

JOHN JONES, On Aristotle and Greek Tragedy (1962, reissued 1980); and RICHARD JANKO, Aristotle on Comedy: Towards a Reconstruction of "Poetics" II (1984).

 

11.10 Aristotelianism. Aristotelianism as covered in general histories:

Extensive treatment of Aristotelianism is included in the fundamental history of philosophy by FRIEDRICH UEBERWEG, A History of Philosophy, from Thales to the Present Time, 2 vol. (1872-74, reprinted 1972; originally published in German, 4th ed., 3 vol., 1871-73), with a vast bibliography. Useful histories of philosophy, general or partial, are FREDERICK C. COPLESTON, A History of Philosophy, 9 vol. (1946-74); MEYRICK H. CARRÉ, Phases of Thought in England (1949, reprinted 1972), which is particularly good on Aristotelianism; JOHN HERMAN RANDALL, The Career of Philosophy, 2 vol. (1962-65, reissued 1970), imaginative and stimulating; and ÉTIENNE GILSON, History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages (1955, reissued 1980), a personal interpretation, with documentation and bibliography.

 

11.11 Aristotelianism in various periods or cultures:

INGEMAR DÜRING, "Von Aristoteles bis Leibniz: Einige Hauptlinien in der Geschichte des Aristotelismus," Antike und Abendland, 4:118-154 (1954), mostly on Greek and medieval Aristotelianism; LORENZO MINIO-PALUELLO, Opuscula: The Latin Aristotle (1972), a collection of articles and essays concerning the Latin transmission of Aristotle's works; and RICHARD McKEON, "Aristotelianism in Western Christianity," in JOHN THOMAS McNEILL, MATTHEW SPINKA, and HAROLD R. WILLOUGHBY (eds.), Environmental Factors in Christian History, pp. 206-231 (1939, reissued 1970). On Boethius, see HENRY CHADWICK, Boethius: The Consolation of Music, Logic, Theology, and Philosophy (1981); and MARGARET GIBSON (ed.), Boethius: His Life, Thought, and Influence (1981). (On Greek Aristotelianism): EDUARD ZELLER, Die Philosophie der Griechen, vol. 2, Sokrates, Plato, Aristoteles (1846), and vol. 3, parts 1-2, Die nacharistotelische Philosophie (1852), parts of which have been translated from various editions: Aristotle and the Earlier Peripatetics, trans. by B.F.C. COSTELLOE and J.H. MUIRHEAD (1897); and A History of Eclecticism in Greek Philosophy, trans. by S.F. ALLEYNE (1883), fundamental for the first eight centuries; PAUL MORAUX, D'Aristote à Bessarion: trois exposés sur l'histoire et la transmission de l'aristotélisme grec (1970); "Rückblick: Der Peripatos in vorchristlicher Zeit," in FRITZ R. WEHRLI (ed.), Die Schule des Aristoteles, vol. 10, pp. 93-128 (1959); KLAUS OEHLER, "Aristotle in Byzantium," Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies, 5(2):133-146 (Summer 1964); and BASILE TATAKIS, La Philosophie byzantine, 2nd ed. (1959), an extensive survey, with a rich bibliography. (On Latin Aristotelianism): FERNAND VAN STEENBERGHEN, Aristotle in the West: The Origins of Latin Aristotelianism, 2nd ed. (1970; originally published in French, 1946), a scholarly survey of contemporary studies; RICHARD J. LEMAY, Abu Ma'shar and Latin Aristotelianism in the Twelfth Century: The Recovery of Aristotle's "Natural Philosophy" Through Arabic Astrology (1962), important contributions; D.A. CALLUS, "Introduction of Aristotelian Learning to Oxford," Proceedings of the British Academy, 29:229-281 (1943), original, fundamental research; PAUL MORAUX et al., Aristote et Saint Thomas d'Aquin (1957), which includes some of the most reliable studies on the subject; M.-D. CHENU, La Théologie comme science au XIIIe siècle, 3rd ed. rev. (1957, reissued 1969), on the interplay of Aristotelian methodology and dogma; and HASTINGS RASHDALL, The Universities of Europe in the Middle Ages, new ed., 3 vol. (1936, reissued 1969), basic for Aristotelianism in the schools. (On Syriac, Arabic, and Jewish Aristotelianism): ANTON BAUMSTARK, Geschichte der syrischen Literatur mit Ausschluss der christlich-palästinensischen Texte (1922, reprinted 1968), with exhaustive factual information and a bibliography; ANTON BAUMSTARK (ed.), Aristoteles bei den Syrern vom 5. bis 8. Jahrhundert: Syrische Texte (1900, reprinted 1975), specialized research and texts; T.J. DE BOER, The History of Philosophy in Islam (1903, reprinted 1983; originally published in German, 1901); CARL BROCKELMANN, Geschichte der arabischen Litteratur, 2 vol. (1898-1902), exhaustive factual information and bibliography; F.E. PETERS, Aristoteles Arabus: The Oriental Translations and Commentaries of the Aristotelian Corpus (1968), from Syriac and Arabic; R. WALZER, "Aristutalis," in The Encyclopaedia of Islam, new ed., vol. 1, pp. 630-633, and related articles; ISAAC HUSIK, A History of Mediaeval Jewish Philosophy (1916, reissued 1974); GEORGES VAJDA, Introduction à la pensée juive du Moyen Age (1947), limited in scope, with a good bibliography; HARRY A. WOLFSON, "Revised Plan for the Publication of a Corpus Commentariorum Averrois in Aristotelem," Speculum, 38(1):88-104 (January 1963), complete lists of Arabic, Latin, and Hebrew texts of Averroës' commentaries, and Crescas' Critique of Aristotle: Problems of Aristotle's "Physics" in Jewish and Arabic Philosophy (1929, reprinted 1971); and "Aristotle," in Encyclopaedia Judaica, vol. 3, col. 445-449 (1971), and related articles. (On Renaissance and later Aristotelianism): PAUL OSKAR KRISTELLER, Renaissance Philosophy and the Mediaeval Tradition (1966), a brilliant survey, with bibliography, and Studies in Renaissance Thought and Letters (1956, reprinted 1969), many relevant essays; BRUNO NARDI, Saggi sull'Aristotelismo padovano dal secolo XIV al XVI (1958), one of several fundamental works by this author; PETER PETERSEN, Geschichte der aristotelischen Philosophie in protestantischen Deutschland (1921, reprinted 1964), and Die Philosophie Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburgs: ein Beitrag zur Geschichte des Aristoteles im 19. Jahrhundert (1913); and CHARLES B. SCHMITT, Aristotle and the Renaissance (1983).

11.12 Aristotelianism in various areas or disciplines:

(On logic): WILLIAM KNEALE and MARTHA KNEALE, The Development of Logic (1962, reprinted 1984), an objective assessment of the Aristotelian and non-Aristotelian elements in the history of logic; and I.M. BOCHENSKI, A History of Formal Logic, 2nd ed. (1970; originally published in German, 1956), technical, with much bibliography. (On science): GEORGE SARTON, Introduction to the History of Science, 3 vol. in 5 (1927-48, reprinted 1975), fundamental, with extensive information and bibliography; RENÉ TATON (ed.), A General History of the Sciences, 4 vol. (1963-66; originally published in French, 1957-64); ALASTAIR C. CROMBIE, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science, 1100-1700 (1953, reissued 1971), which upholds the view of Aristotelian impact on experimental method; ANNELIESE MAIER, Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, 5 vol. (1949-58), fundamental research; and ALEXANDRE KOYRÉ, Galileo Studies (1978; originally published in French, 1939), indispensable for a proper evaluation of anti-Aristotelianism. (On politics): GEORGE H. SABINE, A History of Political Theory, 4th ed. rev. by THOMAS LANDON THORSON (1973); ALEXANDER PASSERIN D'ENTRÈVES, The Medieval Contribution to Political Thought: Thomas Aquinas, Marsilius of Padua, Richard Hooker (1939, reprinted 1959); GEORGES DE LAGARDE, La Naissance de l'esprit laïque au déclin du Moyen Age, 3rd ed., 5 vol. (1956-70), fundamental for the 14th century; and HORST DREITZEL, Protestantischer Aristotelismus und absoluter Staat: Die "Politica" des Henning Arnisaeus (ca. 1575-1636) (1970), excellent, with an extensive bibliography on German Aristotelianism. (Poetics and rhetoric): BERNARD WEINBERG, A History of Literary Criticism in the Italian Renaissance, 2 vol. (1961, reprinted 1974), containing good surveys concerning Aristotle; LANE COOPER, The Poetics of Aristotle: Its Meaning and Influence (1923, reissued 1972); MARVIN T. HERRICK, The Fusion of Horatian and Aristotelian Literary Criticism, 1531-1555 (1946), and The Poetics of Aristotle in England (1930, reprinted 1976), indispensable complements to Cooper's book; and CHARLES S. BALDWIN, Renaissance Literary Theory and Practice: Classicism in the Rhetoric and Poetic of Italy, France, and England, 1400-1600 (1939, reissued 1959), useful for both poetics and rhetoric.

  • Àú¼­
    • ³í¸®ÇÐ(¼¼°è»ç»óÀüÁý 13) : ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º, ÃÖ¹ÎÈ« ¿ª, ¼ºÃ¢ÃâÆÇ»ç, 1986
    • ´ÏÄÚ¸¶ÄÚ½º À±¸®ÇÐ : ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º, ÃÖ¸í°ü ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1984
    • ½ÃÇÐ : ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º, õº´Èñ ¿ª, ¿î¾Ï»ç, 1983
    • Á¤Ä¡ÇС¤½ÃÇÐ(¼¼°è»ç»óÀüÁý 5) : ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º, ³ªÁ¾ÀÏ ¿ª, »ï¼ºÃâÆÇ»ç, 1982
  • ÃÑ·Ð
    • ¼­¾ç°í´ëöÇÐÀÇ ¼¼°è : ¼­¾ç°í´ëöÇÐȸ Æí, ¼­±¤»ç, 1993
    • öÇÐÀÚ ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º : J. L. ¾ÆÅ©¸±, ÇѼ®È¯ ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1992
    • ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ : J. ¹Ý½º, ¹®°è¼® ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1989
    • ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º : A. F. Å×ÀÏ·¯, ÀÌÁ¤¿í ¿ª, Á¾·Î¼­Àû, 1986
    • öÇÐÀÇ ±Ùº»ÀÌÇØ-¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º, Å丶½º ¾ÆÄû³ª½ºÀÇ Ã¶ÇÐ : J. ¸¶¸®ÅÊ, ¹Ú¿µµµ ¿ª, ¼­±¤»ç, 1984
  • À±¸®¡¤Á¤Ä¡ÇÐ
    • ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½ºÀÇ ½ÇõÀû ÁöÇý : ¹ÚÀü±Ô, ¼­±¤»ç, 1985
    • ¾Æ¸®½ºÅäÅÚ·¹½º(À¯Ç³»ç»ó½Å¼­ 14) : ±è¿µÃ¶, À¯Ç³ÃâÆÇ»ç, 1979
¡¡ ¡¡



¡¡
¡¡
 

 °Ô½ÃÆÇ  °Ë»ö  ÀÚ·á½Ç  »çÀÌÆ®¸Ê  ¿¹¼ö¿Í³ª?

¡¡
 

Jesusi.com Homepage



This page was last modified 2001/05/30